Skip to main content

Full text of "Plans and the structure of behavior"

See other formats


and  the 


of 


BEHAVIOR 


UNIVERSITY 
OF  FLORIDA 
LIBRARIES 


Digitized  by  the  Internet  Archive 

in  2010  with  funding  from 

Lyrasis  IVIembers  and  Sloan  Foundation 


http://www.archive.org/details/plansstructureofOOmill 


PLANS 

and  the 

STRUCTURE 

of 

BEHAVIOR 


PLANS 

AND   THE 

STRUCTURE 

OF 

BEHAVIOR 


GEORGE     A.     MILLER,     Harvard  University 
EUGENE     GALANTER,     University  of  Pennsylvania 
KARL     H.     PRIBRAM,     Stanford  University 


HOLT,   RINEHART  AND   WINSTON,    INC. 


150. IH 
c.  3    ' 


Copyright  ©  1960 

by  Holt,  Rinehart  and  Winston,  Inc. 

6789  071  1615141312111 

Library  of  Congress  Catalog  Card  Number:  60-7982 

Printed  in  the  United  States  of  America 

ISBN:  0-03-010075-5 


ACKNOWLEDGMENTS 


It  is  an  ill-kept  secret  that  many  more  people  than  the  authors 
participate  in  the  creation  of  every  book.  In  our  case,  an  entire  insti- 
tution was  involved  in  a  supporting  role;  it  is  one  of  our  most  pleasant 
chores  to  acknowledge  our  debt  to  the  Center  for  Advanced  Study  in 
the  Behavioral  Sciences  in  Stanford,  California.  The  Director  of  the 
Center,  Dr.  Ralph  Tyler,  won  our  deep  and  lasting  affection  by  mak- 
ing available  to  us  the  time  and  facilities  we  needed  for  our  collabora- 
tion, and  by  giving  us  the  freedom  to  exploit  them.  But  the  Center  is 
a  great  deal  more  than  an  institution,  a  pleasant  place  to  work;  it  is 
a  collection  of  scholars  and  scientists  drawn  from  all  the  different 
branches  of  the  behavioral  sciences.  Many  of  those  men  and  women 
spent  time  with  us  when  we  were  confused  and  gave  freely  of  their 
wisdom  and  experience.  Those  who  read  some  of  the  preliminary 
drafts  and  tried  to  save  us  from  our  mistakes  included  Cora  Dubois, 
Helen  Peak,  Frank  Barron,  Frank  Beach,  Jerome  Frank,  Roman  Jakob- 
son,  James  Jenkins,  Thomas  Kuhn,  Charles  Osgood,  Seymour  Perlin, 
and  Willard  V,  Quine.  Of  course,  this  expression  of  our  gratitude  to 
them  does  not  mean  that  they  endorse  the  views  expressed  in  the  fol- 
lowing pages. 

An  early  draft  of  the  manuscript  was  sent  to  some  of  our  friends. 
Many  of  them  found  or  made  the  time  to  reply  to  us,  some  at  great 

Acknowledgments  ■  vii 


length,  and  so  we  gratefully  acknowledge  the  corrections  and  improve- 
ments suggested  by  Robert  R.  Bush,  Noam  Chomsky,  Frederick  C. 
Frick,  Burt  Green,  Francis  W.  Irwin,  R.  Duncan  Luce,  Allen  Newell, 
Herbert  A.  Simon,  and  Donald  W.  Taylor.  The  fact  that  they  criticized 
an  early  version,  of  course,  does  not  deprive  them  of  their  right  to  crit- 
icize the  present  one  as  well. 

We  count  ourselves  particularly  fortunate  to  have  had  the  very 
best  kind  of  assistance  in  getting  our  words  into  print.  Katherine  J. 
Miller  and  Phyllis  Ellis  typed  our  visions  and  revisions  quickly  and 
accurately,  correcting  our  spelling  and  grammar  as  best  they  could. 

In  addition,  we  wish  to  express  our  thanks  to  the  individuals, 
publishers,  and  journals  who  gave  us  permission  to  reprint  passages 
from  their  articles  or  books. 

January  1960 

G.A.M. 

E.G. 

K.H.P. 


viii  ■  Acknowledgments 


CONTENTS 


Prologue 

I 

1 .  Images  and  Plans 

5 

2.  The  Unit  of  Analysis 

21 

3.  The  Simulation  of  Psychological  Processes 

41 

4.  Values,  Intentions,  and  the  Execution  of  Plans 

59 

5.  Instincts 

73 

6.  Motor  Skills  and  Habits 

8i 

7.  The  Integration  of  Plans 

95 

8.  Relinquishing  the  Plan 

103 

9.  Nondynamic  Aspects  of  Personality 

117 

10.  Plans  for  Remembering 

125 

1 1 .  Plans  for  Speaking 

139 

Contents  ■  ix 

12.  Plans  for  Searching  and  Solving  159 

13.  The  Formation  of  Plans  177 

14.  Some  Neuropsychological  Speculations  195 
Epilogue  211 
Index  of  Authors  217 
Index  of  Subjects  221 


X  ■  Contents 


PLANS 

and  the 

STRUCTURE 

of 

BEHAVIOR 


PROLOGUE 


As  I  sit  at  my  desk,  I  know  where  I  am.  I  see  before  me  a  win- 
dow; beyond  that  some  trees;  beyond  that  the  red  roofs  of  the 
campus  of  Stanford  University;  beyond  them  the  trees  and  roof 
tops  which  mark  the  town  of  Palo  Alto:  beyond  them  the  bare 
golden  hills  of  the  Hamilton  Range.  I  know,  however,  more  than 
I  see.  Behind  me,  although  I  am  not  looking  in  that  direction,  I 
know  there  is  a  vmidow,  and  beyond  that  the  little  campus  of  the 
Center  for  Advanced  Study  in  the  Behavioral  Sciences;  beyond 
that  the  Coast  Range;  beyond  that  the  Pacific  Ocean. 


With  these  words  the  economist  Kenneth  E.  Boulding  begins  a 

short  treatise  entitled  The  Image,  in  which  he  explores  some  of 

the  dimensions  of  our  picture  of  man  and  the  universe.^  He  goes  on  to 

sketch  some  of  the  larger  aspects  of  his  own  Image  whereby  he  feels 

himself  located  in  space  and  time  and  society  and  nature  and  his  own 

personal  history.  He  is  not  thinking  here  of  simple  visual  images; 

blind  men  have  Images,  too.  The  Image  is  his  knowledge  of  the  world. 

His  behavior  depends  upon  the  Image.  Meaningful  messages  change 

1  Kenneth  E.  Bovilding,  The  Image  (Ann  Arbor:   University  of  Michigan 
Press,  1956). 

Prologue  ■  i 


the  Image.  He  pursues  men's  Images  through  biology,  sociology,  eco- 
nomics, political  science,  and  history,  and  he  weaves  together  a 
tapestry  of  private  and  pubHc  Images,  of  personal  and  shared  knowl- 
edge, which  can  best  be  described  as  a  snapshot  of  a  twentieth-cen- 
tury mind  at  work. 

Boulding  wrote  The  Image  during  the  summer  of  1955  at  the 
close  of  an  academic  year  spent  in  California  at  the  Center  for  Ad- 
vanced Study  in  the  Behavioral  Sciences.  It  was  just  three  years  later, 
during  the  academic  year  1958-59,  that  the  present  authors  as- 
sembled, not  entirely  accidentally,  at  that  same  Center.  We  had  our 
individual  problems.  We  had  some  shared  problems  that  dated  back 
to  a  summer  together  at  Harvard  in  1956.  And  we  had  a  general 
commitment  to  continue  our  own  education.  It  was  in  the  course  of 
that  latter  project  that  we  came  across  The  Image  on  the  shelf  of  the 
Center's  library.  To  psychologists  who  like  alternatives  to  nickel-in- 
the-slot,  stimulus-response  conceptions  of  man,  an  Image  has  con- 
siderable appeal.  (It  is  so  reasonable  to  insert  between  the  stimulus 
and  the  response  a  little  wisdom.  And  there  is  no  particular  need  to 
apologize  for  putting  it  there,  because  it  was  already  there  before 
psychology  arrived. )  The  Image  became  a  part  of  the  Image  we  were 
building  for  ourselves,  in  our  conversations  and  our  arguments  and 
our  virritings. 

But  as  the  year  advanced  and  our  Image  grew,  we  slowly  be- 
came convinced  that  Boulding — and  cognitive  psychologists  gen- 
erally— had  not  told  a  complete  story.  We  thought  we  knew  a  part 
that  was  missing.  Although  we  could  accept,  in  spirit  if  not  in  detail, 
the  argument  that  cognitive  theorists  made,  it  left  an  organism  more 
in  the  role  of  a  spectator  than  of  a  participant  in  the  drama  of  hving. 
Unless  you  can  use  your  Image  to  do  something,  you  are  like  a  man 
who  collects  maps  but  never  makes  a  trip.  It  seemed  to  us  that  a 
Plan  is  needed  in  order  to  exploit  the  Image. 

The  notion  of  a  Plan  that  guides  behavior  is,  again  not  entirely 
accidentally,  quite  similar  to  the  notion  of  a  program  that  guides  an 
electronic  computer.  In  order  to  discover  how  to  get  the  Image  into 
motion,  therefore,  we  reviewed  once  more  the  cybernetic  literature 
on  the  analogies  between  brains  and  computers,  between  minds  and 
programs.  In  this  survey  we  were  especially  fortunate  in  having  at  our 

2  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


disposal  a  large  mass  of  material,  much  of  it  still  unpublished,  that 
Miller  had  obtained  from  Allen  Newell,  J.  C.  Shaw,  and  Herbert  A. 
Simon  in  the  course  of  a  Research  Training  Institute  on  the  Simula- 
tion of  Cognitive  Processes  held  at  RAND  Corporation,  Santa  Monica, 
California,  July  1958,  and  sponsored  by  the  Social  Science  Research 
Council.  Unfortunately,  however,  when  these  materials  were  trans- 
ported from  the  think-center  in  Santa  Monica  to  the  think-center  in 
Stanford,  the  electronic  computer,  its  attendants,  and  the  research 
workers  themselves  had  to  be  left  behind.  Without  those  supporting 
facilities,  all  we  could  do  was  try  to  understand  the  spirit  of  the  work 
as  simply  and  concretely  as  we  could — but  doubtless  there  was  con- 
siderable distortion  in  the  channel.  Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon  inspired 
us  by  their  successes,  but  they  should  not  be  held  responsible  for  our 
mistakes  or  embellishments.  Nor  should  Wiener,  Ashby,  von  Neu- 
mann, Minsky,  Shannon,  MacKay,  McCuUoch,  Chomsky,  or  any  of  the 
other  authors  whose  work  we  studied.  Our  only  hope  is  that  there 
really  can  be  such  a  thing  as  creative  misunderstanding. 

Our  fundamental  concern,  however,  was  to  discover  whether 
the  cybernetic  ideas  have  any  relevance  for  psychology.  The  men 
who  have  pioneered  in  this  area  have  been  remarkably  innocent 
about  psychology — the  creatures  whose  behavior  they  want  to  simu- 
late often  seem  more  like  a  mathematician's  dream  than  like  living 
animals.  But  in  spite  of  all  the  evidence,  we  refused  to  believe  that 
ignorance  of  psychology  is  a  cybernetic  prerequisite  or  even  an  ad- 
vantage. There  must  be  some  way  to  phrase  the  new  ideas  so  that 
they  can  contribute  to  and  profit  from  the  science  of  behavior  that 
psychologists  have  created.  It  was  the  search  for  that  favorable  in- 
tersection that  directed  the  course  of  our  year-long  debate. 

With  an  Image,  a  Plan,  and  a  debate  simmering  in  our  minds, 
it  soon  became  necessary  for  us  to  write  the  argument  down  in 
order  to  remember  what  it  was.  And  as  things  became  clearer,  sud- 
denly it  seemed  necessary  to  make  a  book  of  the  argument.  It  was  to 
be  a  little  book,  even  smaller  than  it  turned  out  to  be.  It  was  to  take 
only  a  few  days  to  write,  but  those  days  stretched  into  months.  It  was 
to  be  our  intellectual  diary  for  the  year,  with  none  of  the  defensive- 
ness  or  documentation  that  have  since  crept  into  it.  But  in  spite  of 
all  those  familiar  academic  vectors  acting  upon  it,  it  has  turned  out 

Prologue  ■  3 


to  be  a  spontaneous,  argumentative,  personal  kind  of  book  that 
should  irritate  our  sober-sided  colleagues.  That  would  be  aU  right— r 
sober-sided  colleagues  deserve  to  be  irritated — except  that  more  is  at 
stake  than  the  authors'  reputations.  Some  of  the  ideas  we  have  used 
are  too  good  to  lose.  It  would  be  unfortunate  if  our  style  were  to  con- 
ceal the  true  merit  of  the  arguments  we  try  to  present.  If  we  had  had 
more  time  together,  we  might  have  been  able  to  argue  our  way 
through  to  a  better-balanced  composition.  But  a  year  is  only  a  year 
long.  So,  gentle  reader,  if  your  anger  starts  to  rise,  take  a  deep  breath, 
accept  our  apologies — and  push  ahead. 


4  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


CHAPTER  1 


IMAGES  AND   PLANS 


Consider  how  an  ordinary  day  is  put  together.  You  awaken,  and 
as  you  lie  in  bed,  or  perhaps  as  you  move  slowly  about  in  a  protective 
shell  of  morning  habits,  you  think  about  what  the  day  will  be  like — 
it  will  be  hot,  it  will  be  cold;  there  is  too  much  to  do,  there  is  nothing 
to  fill  the  time;  you  promised  to  see  him,  she  may  be  there  again  to- 
day. If  you  are  compulsive,  you  may  worry  about  fitting  it  all  in, 
you  may  make  a  list  of  all  the  things  you  have  to  do.  Or  you  may 
launch  yourself  into  the  day  with  no  clear  notion  of  what  you  are 
going  to  do  or  how  long  it  will  take.  But,  whether  it  is  crowded  or 
empty,  novel  or  routine,  uniform  or  varied,  your  day  has  a  structure 
of  its  own — it  fits  into  the  texture  of  your  life.  And  as  you  think  what 
your  day  will  hold,  you  construct  a  plan  to  meet  it.  What  you  expect 
to  happen  foreshadows  what  you  expect  to  do. 

The  authors  of  this  book  believe  that  the  plans  you  make  are  in- 
teresting and  that  they  probably  have  some  relation  to  how  you  actu- 
ally spend  your  time  during  the  day.  We  call  them  "plans"  without 
mahce — we  recognize  that  you  do  not  draw  out  long  and  elaborate 
blueprints  for  every  moment  of  the  day.  You  do  not  need  to.  Rough- 
sketchy,  flexible  anticipations  are  usually  sufficient.  As  you  brush 

Images  and  Plans  ■  5 


your  teeth  you  decide  that  you  will  answer  that  pile  of  letters  you 
have  been  neglecting.  That  is  enough.  You  do  not  need  to  Ust  the 
names  of  the  people  or  to  draft  an  outline  of  the  contents  of  the  let- 
ters. You  think  simply  that  today  there  will  be  time  for  it  after  lunch. 
After  lunch,  if  you  remember,  you  turn  to  the  letters.  You  take  one 
and  read  it.  You  plan  your  answer.  You  may  need  to  check  on  some 
information,  you  dictate  or  type  or  scribble  a  reply,  you  address  an 
envelope,  seal  the  folded  letter,  find  a  stamp,  drop  it  in  a  mailbox. 
Each  of  these  subactivities  runs  off  as  the  situation  arises — you  did 
not  need  to  enumerate  them  while  you  were  planning  the  day.  All 
you  need  is  the  name  of  the  activity  that  you  plan  for  that  segment 
of  the  day,  and  from  that  name  you  then  proceed  to  elaborate  the  de- 
tailed actions  involved  in  carrying  out  the  plan. 

You  imagine  what  your  day  is  going  to  be  and  you  make  plans  to 
cope  with  it.  Images  and  plans.  What  does  modem  psychology  have 
to  say  about  images  and  plans? 

Presumably,  the  task  of  modem  psychology  is  to  make  sense 
out  of  what  people  and  animals  do,  to  find  some  system  for  under- 
standing their  behavior.  If  we,  as  psychologists,  come  to  this  task 
with  proper  scientific  caution,  we  must  begin  with  what  we  can  see 
and  we  must  postulate  as  little  as  possible  beyond  that.  What  we  can 
see  are  movements  and  environmental  events.  The  ancient  subject 
matter  of  psychology — the  mind  and  its  various  manifestations — is 
distressingly  invisible,  and  a  science  with  invisible  content  is  likely 
to  become  an  invisible  science.  We  are  therefore  led  to  underline  the 
fundamental  importance  of  behavior  and,  in  particular,  to  try  to  dis- 
cover recurrent  patterns  of  stimulation  and  response. 

What  an  organism  does  depends  on  what  happens  around  it.  As 
to  the  way  in  which  this  dependency  should  be  described,  however, 
there  are,  as  in  most  matters  of  modern  psychology,  two  schools  of 
thought.  On  the  one  hand  are  the  optimists,  who  claim  to  find  the  de- 
pendency simple  and  straightforward.  They  model  the  stimulus- 
response  relation  after  the  classical,  physiological  pattern  of  the  re- 
flex arc  and  use  Pavlov's  discoveries  to  explain  how  new  reflexes  can 
be  formed  through  experience.  This  approach  is  too  simple  for  all  but 
the  most  extreme  optimists.  Most  psychologists  quickly  realize  that 

6  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


behavior  in  general,  and  human  behavior  in  particular,  is  not  a  chain 
of  conditioned  reflexes.  So  the  model  is  complicated  slightly  by  in- 
corporating some  of  the  stimuli  that  occur  after  the  response  in  addi- 
tion to  the  stimuli  that  occur  before  the  response.  Once  these  "rein- 
forcing" stimuli  are  included  in  the  description,  it  becomes  possible 
to  understand  a  much  greater  variety  of  behaviors  and  to  acknowl- 
edge the  apparently  purposive  nature  of  behavior.  That  is  one  school 
of  thought. 

Arrayed  against  the  reflex  theorists  are  the  pessimists,  who 
think  that  living  organisms  are  complicated,  devious,  poorly  designed 
for  research  purposes,  and  so  on.  They  maintain  that  the  effect  an 
event  will  have  upon  behavior  depends  on  how  the  event  is  repre- 
sented in  the  organism's  picture  of  itself  and  its  universe.  They  are 
quite  sure  that  any  correlations  between  stimulation  and  response 
must  be  mediated  by  an  organized  representation  of  the  environment, 
a  system  of  concepts  and  relations  within  which  the  organism  is 
located.  A  human  being — and  probably  other  animals  as  well — 
builds  up  an  internal  representation,  a  model  of  the  universe,  a 
schema,  a  simulacrum,  a  cognitive  map,  an  Image.  Sir  Frederic  C. 
Bartlett,  who  uses  the  term  "schema"  for  this  internal  representa- 
tion, describes  it  in  this  way: 

"Schema"  refers  to  an  active  organisation  of  past  reactions, 
or  of  past  experiences,  which  must  always  be  supposed  to  be 
operating  in  any  well-adapted  organic  response.  That  is,  when- 
ever there  is  any  order  or  regularity  of  behavior,  a  particular 
response  is  possible  only  because  it  is  related  to  other  similar 
responses  which  have  been  serially  organised,  yet  which  operate, 
not  simply  as  individual  members  coming  one  after  another,  but 
as  a  unitary  mass.  Determination  by  schemata  is  the  most  funda- 
mental of  all  the  ways  in  which  we  can  be  influenced  by  reactions 
and  experiences  which  occurred  some  time  in  the  past.  All  in- 
coming impulses  of  a  certain  kind,  or  mode,  go  together  to  build 
up  an  active,  organised  setting:  visual,  auditory,  various  types 
of  cutaneous  impulses  and  the  like,  at  a  relatively  low  level;  all 
the  experiences  connected  by  a  common  interest:  in  sport,  in 
Uterature,  history,  art,  science,  philosophy,  and  so  on,  on  a 
higher  level.^ 

1  Frederic  C.  Bartlett,  Remembering,  A  Study  in  Experimental  and  Social 
Psychology  (Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press,  1932),  p.  201. 

Images  and  Plans  ■  7 


The  crux  of  the  argument,  as  every  psychologist  knows,  is 
whether  anything  so  mysterious  and  inaccessible  as  "the  organism's 
picture  of  itself  and  its  universe,"  or  "an  active  organisation  of  past 
reactions,"  etc.,  is  really  necessary.  Necessary,  that  is  to  say,  as  an 
explanation  for  the  behavior  that  can  be  observed  to  occur. 

The  view  that  some  mediating  organization  of  experience  is 
necessary  has  a  surprisingly  large  number  of  critics  among  hard- 
headed,  experimentally  trained  psychologists.  The  mediating  or- 
ganization is,  of  course,  a  theoretical  concept  and,  out  of  respect  for 
Occam's  Razor,  one  should  not  burden  the  science  with  unnecessary 
theoretical  luggage.  An  unconditional  proof  that  a  completely  con- 
sistent account  of  behavior  cannot  be  formulated  more  economically 
does  not  exist,  and  until  we  are  certain  that  simpler  ideas  have  failed 
we  should  not  rush  to  embrace  more  complicated  ones.  Indeed, 
there  are  many  psychologists  who  think  the  simple  stimulus-re- 
sponse-reinforcement models  provide  an  adequate  description  of 
everything  a  psychologist  should  concern  himself  with. 

For  reasons  that  are  not  entirely  clear,  the  battle  between  these 
two  schools  of  thought  has  generally  been  waged  at  the  level  of  ani- 
mal behavior.  Edward  Tolman,  for  example,  has  based  his  defense  of 
cognitive  organization  almost  entirely  on  his  studies  of  the  behavior 
of  rats — surely  one  of  the  least  promising  areas  in  which  to  investi- 
gate intellectual  accomplishments.  Perhaps  he  felt  that  if  he  could 
win  the  argument  with  the  simpler  animal,  he  would  win  it  by  de- 
fault for  the  more  compUcated  ones.  If  the  description  of  a  rodent's 
cognitive  structure  is  necessary  in  order  to  understand  its  behavior, 
then  it  is  just  that  much  more  important  for  understanding  the  be- 
havior of  a  dog,  or  an  ape,  or  a  man.  Tolman's  position  was  put  most 
simply  and  directly  in  the  following  paragraph : 

[The  brain]  is  far  more  like  a  map  control  room  than  it  is 
Hke  an  old-fashioned  telephone  exchange.  The  stimuli,  which  are 
allowed  in,  are  not  connected  by  just  simple  one-to-one  switches 
to  the  outgoing  responses.  Rather,  the  incoming  impulses  are 
usually  worked  over  and  elaborated  in  the  central  control  room 
into  a  tentative,  cognitivelike  map  of  the  environment.  And  it 
is  this  tentative  map,  indicating  routes  and  paths  and  environ- 
mental relationships,  which  finally  determines  what  responses, 
if  any,  the  animal  will  finally  release.^ 

2  Edward  C.  Tolman,  Cognitive  maps  in  rats  and  men.  Psychological  Re- 
view, 1948,  55,  189-208. 

8  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


We  ourselves  are  quite  sympathetic  to  this  kind  of  theorizing, 
since  it  seems  obvious  to  us  that  a  great  deal  more  goes  on  between 
the  stimulus  and  the  response  than  can  be  accounted  for  by  a  simple 
statement  about  associative  strengths.  The  pros  and  cons  cannot  be 
reviewed  here — the  argument  is  long  and  other  texts  ^  exist  in  which 
an  interested  reader  can  pursue  it — so  we  shall  simply  announce  that 
our  theoretical  preferences  are  all  on  the  side  of  the  cognitive  theo- 
rists. Life  is  complicated. 

Nevertheless,  there  is  a  criticism  of  the  cognitive  position  that 
seems  quite  important  and  that  has  never,  so  far  as  we  know,  re- 
ceived an  adequate  answer.  The  criticism  is  that  the  cognitive  proc- 
esses Tolman  and  others  have  postulated  are  not,  in  fact,  sufficient 
to  do  the  job  they  were  supposed  to  do.  Even  if  you  admit  these 
ghostly  inner  somethings,  say  the  critics,  you  will  not  have  explained 
anything  about  the  animal's  behavior.  Guthrie  has  made  the  point 
about  as  sharply  as  anyone : 

Signs,  in  Tolman's  theory,  occasion  in  the  rat  realization, 
or  cognition,  or  judgment,  or  hypotheses,  or  abstraction,  but 
they  do  not  occasion  action.  In  his  concern  with  what  goes  on  in 
the  rat's  mind,  Tolman  has  neglected  to  predict  what  the  rat  will 
do.  So  far  as  the  theory  is  concerned  the  rat  is  left  buried  in 
thought;  if  he  gets  to  the  food-box  at  the  end  that  is  his  concern, 
not  the  concern  of  the  theory.* 

Perhaps  the  cognitive  theorists  have  not  understood  the  force  of 
this  criticism.  It  is  so  transparently  clear  to  them  that  if  a  hungry  rat 
knows  where  to  find  food — if  he  has  a  cognitive  map  with  the  food- 
box  located  on  it — he  will  go  there  and  eat.  What  more  is  there  to  ex- 
plain? The  answer,  of  course,  is  that  a  great  deal  is  left  to  be  ex- 
plained. The  gap  from  knowledge  to  action  looks  smaller  than  the 
gap  from  stimulus  to  action — yet  the  gap  is  still  there,  still  indefinitely 
large.  Tolman,  the  omniscient  theorist,  leaps  over  that  gap  when  he 
infers  the  rat's  cognitive  organization  from  its  behavior.  But  that 
leaves  still  outstanding  the  question  of  the  rat's  abihty  to  leap  it.  Ap- 
parently, cognitive  theorists  have  assumed  that  their  best  course  was 

3  See,  for  example,  either  E.  R.  Hilgard,  Theories  of  Learning  (New  York: 
Appleton-Century-Crofts,  ed.  2,  1956),  or  W.  K.  Estes  et  al..  Modern  Learning 
Theory  (New  York:  Appleton-Century-Crofts,  1954),  or  D.  O.  Hebb,  The  Organi- 
zation of  Behavior  (New  York:  Wiley,  1949), 

4  E.  R.  Guthrie,  The  Psychology  of  Learning  (New  York:  Harper,  1935), 
p.  172. 

Images  and  Plans  ■  g 


to  show  that  the  reflex  theories  are  inadequate;  they  seem  to  have 
been  quite  unprepared  when  the  same  argument — that  things  are 
even  more  complicated  than  they  dared  to  imagine — was  used 
against  them.  Yet,  if  Guthrie  is  right,  more  cognitive  theory  is  needed 
than  the  cognitive  theorists  normally  supply.  That  is  to  say,  far  from 
respecting  Occam's  Razor,  the  cognitive  theorist  must  ask  for  even 
more  theoretical  luggage  to  carry  around.  Something  is  needed  to 
bridge  the  gap  from  knowledge  to  action. 

It  is  unfair  to  single  out  Tolman  and  criticize  him  for  leaving 
the  cognitive  representation  paralytic.  Other  cognitive  theorists  could 
equally  well  be  cited.  Wolfgang  Kohler,  for  example,  has  been  sub- 
jected to  the  same  kind  of  heckling.  In  reporting  his  extremely  per- 
ceptive study  of  the  chimpanzees  on  Tenerife  Island  during  the  first 
World  War,  Kohler  wrote : 

We  can  .  .  .  distinguish  sharply  between  the  kind  of 
behavior  which  from  the  very  beginning  arises  out  of  a  consider- 
ation of  the  structure  of  a  situation,  and  one  that  does  not.  Only 
in  the  former  case  do  we  speak  of  insight,  and  only  that  behavior 
of  animals  definitely  appears  to  us  intelligent  which  takes  ac- 
count from  the  beginning  of  the  lay  of  the  land,  and  proceeds  to 
deal  with  it  in  a  single,  continuous,  and  definite  course.  Hence 
follows  this  criterion  of  insight:  the  appearance  of  a  complete 
solution  with  reference  to  the  whole  lay-out  of  the  field.^ 

Other  psychologists  have  been  less  confident  that  they  could  tell  the 
difference  between  behavior  based  on  an  understanding  of  the  whole 
layout  and  behavior  based  on  less  cognitive  processes,  so  there  has 
been  a  long  and  rather  fruitless  controversy  over  the  relative  merits 
of  trial-and-error  and  of  insight  as  methods  of  learning.  The  point  we 
wish  to  raise  here,  however,  is  that  Kohler  makes  the  standard  cogni- 
tive assumption:  once  the  animal  has  grasped  the  whole  layout  he  will 
behave  appropriately.  Again,  the  fact  that  grasping  the  whole  layout 
may  be  necessary,  but  is  certainly  not  sufficient  as  an  explanation  of 
intelligent  behavior,  seems  to  have  been  ignored  by  Kohler.  Many 
years  later,  for  example,  we  heard  Karl  Lashley  say  this  to  him : 

I  attended  the  dedication,  three  weeks  ago,  of  a  bridge  at 
Dyea,  Alaska.  The  road  to  the  bridge  for  nine  miles  was  blasted 

5  Wolfgang  Kohler,  The  Mentality  of  Apes  (translated  from  the  second  edi- 
tion by  Ella  Winter;  London:  Routledge  and  Kegan  Paul,  1927),  pp.  169-170. 

ID  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


along  a  series  of  cliffs.  It  led  to  a  magnificent  steel  bridge,  per- 
manent and  apparently  indestructible.  After  the  dedication  cere- 
monies I  walked  across  the  bridge  and  was  confronted  with  an 
impenetrable  forest  of  shrubs  and  underbrush,  through  which 
only  a  couple  of  trails  of  bears  led  to  indeterminate  places.  In  a 
way,  I  feel  that  Professor  Kohler's  position  is  somewhat  that  of 
the  bridge.  .  .  .  The  neurological  problem  is  in  large  part,  if  not 
entirely,  the  translation  of  the  afferent  pattern  of  impulses  into 
the  efferent  pattern.  The  field  theory  in  its  present  form  includes 
no  hint  of  the  way  in  which  the  field  forces  induce  and  control 
the  pattern  of  efferent  activity.  It  applies  to  perceptual  experi- 
ence but  seems  to  end  there.® 

Many  other  voices  could  be  added  to  this  dialogue.  Much  de- 
tailed analysis  of  different  psychological  theories  could  be  displayed 
to  show  why  the  cognitive  theorists  feel  they  have  answered  the 
criticism  and  why  their  critics  still  maintain  that  they  have  not.  But 
we  will  not  pursue  it.  Our  point  is  that  many  psychologists,  including 
the  present  authors,  have  been  disturbed  by  a  theoretical  vacuum  be- 
tween cognition  and  action.  The  present  book  is  largely  the  record  of 
prolonged — and  frequently  violent — conversations  about  how  that 
vacuum  might  be  filled. 

No  doubt  it  is  perfectly  obvious  to  the  reader  that  we  have  here 
a  modern  version  of  an  ancient  puzzle.  At  an  earlier  date  we  might 
have  introduced  the  topic  directly  by  announcing  that  we  intended  to 
discuss  the  will.  But  today  the  will  seems  to  have  disappeared  from 
psychological  theory,  assimilated  anonymously  into  the  broader  topic 
of  motivation.  The  last  serious  attempt  to  make  sense  out  of  the  will 
was  the  early  work  of  Kurt  Lewin  and  his  students.  Lewin's  contribu- 
tions are  so  important  that  we  will  treat  them  in  detail  in  Chapter  4; 
we  cannot  dismiss  them  summarily  by  a  paragraph  in  this  introduc- 
tion. In  order  to  show  what  a  psychology  of  will  might  be  like,  there- 
fore, it  is  necessary  to  return  to  an  earlier  and  more  philosophical 
generation  of  psychologists.  William  James  provides  the  sort  of  dis- 
cussion that  was  once  an  indispensable  part  of  every  psychology  text, 
so  let  us  consider  briefly  how  he  handled  the  topic. 

The  second  volume  of  The  Principles  contains  a  long  chapter 

^  Lloyd  A.  JefFress,  ed..  Cerebral  Mechanisms  in  Behavior  (New  York: 
Wiley,  1951),  p.  230. 

Images  and  Plans  ■   1 1 


(106  pages)  entitled  "Will."  The  first  third  of  it  is  James's  struggle 
against  theories  based  on  "sensations  of  innervation" — the  notion 
that  the  innervation  required  to  perform  the  appropriate  action  is  it- 
self a  part  of  the  cognitive  representation.  James  maintains  instead 
that  it  is  the  anticipation  of  the  kinesthetic  effects  of  the  movement 
that  is  represented  in  consciousness.  He  then  turns  to  the  topic  of 
"ideo-motor  action,"  which  provides  the  foundation  for  his  explana- 
tion of  all  phenomena  of  will.  If  a  person  forms  a  clear  image  of  a 
particular  action,  that  action  tends  to  occur.  The  occurrence  may  be 
inhibited,  limited  to  covert  tensions  in  the  muscles,  but  in  many  cases 
having  an  idea  of  an  action  is  sufficient  for  action.  If  there  is  anything 
between  the  cognitive  representation  and  the  overt  action,  it  is  not 
represented  in  consciousness.  Introspectively,  therefore,  there  seems 
to  be  no  vacuum  to  be  filled,  and  James,  had  he  heard  them,  would 
have  felt  that  criticisms  of  the  sort  made  by  Guthrie  and  Lashley 
were  not  justified. 

But  what  of  the  more  complicated  cases  of  willing?  What  occurs 
when  we  force  ourselves  through  some  unpleasant  task  by  "the  slow 
dead  heave  of  the  will?"  According  to  James,  the  feeling  of  effort 
arises  from  our  attempt  to  keep  our  attention  focused  on  the  un- 
pleasant idea.  "The  essential  achievement  of  the  wHl,"  he  tells  us,  "is 
to  attend  to  a  difficult  object  and  hold  it  fast  before  the  mind."  ^  If  an 
idea  can  be  maintained  in  attention,  then  the  action  that  is  envisioned 
in  the  idea  occurs  automatically — a  direct  example  of  ideo-motor  ac- 
tion. All  of  which  helps  us  not  in  the  least.  The  bridge  James  gives  us 
between  the  ideo  and  the  motor  is  nothing  but  a  hyphen.  There  seems 
to  be  no  alternative  but  to  strike  out  into  the  vacuum  on  our  own. 

The  problem  is  to  describe  how  actions  are  controlled  by  an  or- 
ganism's internal  representation  of  its  universe.  If  we  consider  what 
these  actions  are  in  the  normal,  freely  ranging  animal,  we  must  be 
struck  by  the  extent  to  which  they  are  organized  into  patterns.  Most 
psychologists  maintain  that  these  action  patterns  are  punctuated  by 
goals  and  subgoals,  but  that  does  not  concern  us  for  the  moment.  We 
wish  to  call  attention  to  the  fact  that  the  organization  does  exist — 
configuration  is  just  as  important  a  property  of  behavior  as  it  is  of 

7  William  James,  The  Principles  of  Psychology,  Vol.  II  (New  York:  Holt, 
1890),  p.  561. 

12  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


perception.  The  configurations  of  behavior,  however,  tend  to  be  pre- 
dominantly temporal — it  is  the  sequence  of  motions  that  flows  on- 
ward so  smoothly  as  the  creature  runs,  swims,  flies,  talks,  or  what- 
ever. What  we  must  provide,  therefore,  is  some  way  to  map  the 
cognitive  representation  into  the  appropriate  pattern  of  activity.  But 
how  are  we  to  analyze  this  flowing  pattern  of  action  into  manageable 
parts? 

The  difficulty  in  analyzing  the  actions  of  an  animal  does  not 
arise  from  any  lack  of  ways  to  do  it  but  from  an  embarrassment  of 
riches.  We  can  describe  an  action  as  a  sequence  of  muscle  twitches, 
or  as  a  sequence  of  movements  of  limbs  and  other  parts,  or  as  a  se- 
quence of  goal-directed  actions,  or  in  even  larger  units.  Following 
Tolman,  most  psychologists  distinguish  the  little  units  from  the  big 
units  by  calling  the  little  ones  "molecular,"  the  big  ones,  "molar."  Any- 
one who  asks  which  unit  is  the  correct  size  to  use  in  describing  be- 
havior is  told  that  behavioral  laws  seem  more  obvious  when  molar 
units  are  used,  but  that  just  how  molar  he  should  be  in  any  particular 
analysis  is  something  he  will  have  to  learn  from  experience  and  ob- 
servation in  research. 

The  implication  is  relatively  clear,  however,  that  the  molar  units 
must  be  composed  of  molecular  units,  which  we  take  to  mean  that  a 
proper  description  of  behavior  must  be  made  on  all  levels  simul- 
tan£ously.  That  is  to  say,  we  are  trying  to  describe  a  process  that  is 
organized  on  several  different  levels,  and  the  pattern  of  units  at  one 
level  can  be  indicated  only  by  giving  the  units  at  the  next  higher,  or 
more  molar,  level  of  description.  For  example,  the  molar  pattern  of 
behavior  X  consists  of  two  parts,  A  and  B,  in  that  order.  Thus, 
X  =  AB.  But  A,  in  turn,  consists  of  two  parts,  a  and  b;  and  B  consists 
of  three,  c,  d,  and  e.  Thus,  X  =  AB  =  abcde,  and  we  can  describe  the 
same  segment  of  behavior  at  any  one  of  the  three  levels.  The  point, 
however,  is  that  we  do  not  want  to  pick  one  level  and  argue  that  it  is 
somehow  better  than  the  others;  the  complete  description  must  in- 
clude all  levels.  Otherwise,  the  configurational  properties  of  the  be- 
havior will  be  lost — if  we  state  only  abcde,  for  example,  then  (ab) 
(cde)  may  become  confused  with  (abc)(de),  which  may  be  a  very  dif- 
ferent thing. 

This  kind  of  organization  of  behavior  is  most  obvious,  no  doubt, 

Images  and  Plans  "13 


in  human  verbal  behavior.  The  individual  phonemes  are  organized 
into  morphemes,  morphemes  are  strung  together  to  form  phrases, 
phrases  in  the  proper  sequence  form  a  sentence,  and  a  string  of  sen- 
tences makes  up  the  utterance.  The  complete  description  of  the  ut- 
terance involves  all  these  levels.  The  kind  of  ambiguity  that  results 
when  all  levels  are  not  known  is  suggested  by  the  sentence,  "They  are 
flying  planes."  The  sequence  of  phonemes  may  remain  unchanged, 
but  the  two  analyses  (They) (are  flying) (planes')  and  (They) (are) 
(flying  planes)  are  very  different  utterances.* 

Psychologists  have  seldom  demonstrated  any  reluctance  to  infer 
the  existence  of  such  molar  units  as  "words"  or  even  "meanings" 
when  they  have  dealt  with  verbal  behavior,  even  though  the  actual 
responses  available  to  perception  are  merely  the  strings  of  phones, 
the  acoustic  representations  of  the  intended  phonemes.  Exactly  the 
same  recognition  of  more  molar  units  in  nonverbal  behavior  de- 
serves the  same  kind  of  multi-level  description.  Unfortunately,  how- 
ever, the  psychologist  usually  describes  behavior — or  some  aspect  of 
behavior — at  a  single  level  and  leaves  his  colleagues  to  use  their  own 
common  sense  to  infer  what  happened  at  other  levels.  The  meticu- 
lous recording  of  every  muscle  twitch,  even  if  anyone  were  brave 
enough  to  try  it,  would  still  not  suffice,  for  it  would  not  contain  the 
structural  features  that  characterize  the  molar  units — and  those 
structural  features  must  be  inferred  on  the  basis  of  a  theory  about  be- 
havior. Our  theories  of  behavior,  in  this  sense  of  the  term,  have  al- 
ways remained  implicit  and  intuitive.  (It  is  rather  surprising  to  realize 
that  after  half  a  century  of  behaviorism  this  aspect  of  the  problem 
of  describing  behavior  has  almost  never  been  recognized,  much  less 
solved. ) 

8  The  traditional  method  of  parsing  a  sentence  is  the  prototype  of  the  kind 
of  behavioral  description  we  demand.  Noam  Chomsky,  in  Chapter  4  of  his 
monograph.  Syntactic  Structures  (The  Hague:  Mouton,  1957),  provides  a  formal 
representation  of  this  kind  of  description,  which  linguists  refer  to  as  "constituent 
analysis."  We  shall  discuss  Chomsky's  method  of  representing  verbal  behavior 
in  more  detail  in  Chapter  11.  The  suggestion  that  linguistic  analysis  provides  a 
model  for  the  description  of  all  kinds  of  behavior  is,  of  course,  no  novelty;  it  has 
been  made  frequently  by  both  linguists  and  psychologists.  For  example,  in  The 
Study  of  Language  (Cambridge:  Harvard  University  Press,  1953),  John  B.  Car- 
roll, a  psychologist,  observed  that,  "From  linguistic  theory  we  get  the  notion  of  a 
hierarchy  of  units — from  elemental  units  like  the  distinctive  feature  of  a  pho- 
neme to  large  units  like  a  sentence-type.  It  may  be  suggested  that  stretches  of 
any  kind  of  behavior  may  be  organized  in  somewhat  the  same  fashion"  (p.  106). 

14  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


In  those  fortunate  instances  that  do  give  us  adequate  descrip- 
tions of  behavior — instances  provided  almost  entirely  by  linguists 
and  ethologists — it  is  quite  obvious  that  the  behavior  is  organ- 
ized simultaneously  at  several  levels  of  complexity.  We  shall  speak  of 
this  fact  as  the  "hierarchical  organization  of  behavior."  ^  The  hier- 
archy can  be  represented  in  various  ways.  The  diagram  of  a  hier- 
archy usually  takes  the  form  of  a  tree,  the  arborizations  indicating 
progressively  more  molecular  representations.  Or  it  can  be  cast  as  an 
outline : 

X. 
A. 

a. 

h. 
B. 

c. 

d. 

e. 
This  outline  show^s  the  structure  of  the  hypothetical  example  intro- 
duced on  page  13.  Or  it  can  be  considered  as  a  collection  of  lists: 
X  is  a  list  containing  the  two  items,  A  and  B;  A  is  a  list  containing 
two  items,  a  and  b;  B  is  a  list  containing  three  items,  c,  d,  and  e."  Or 
it  can  be  considered  as  a  set  of  rules  governing  permissible  substitu- 

9  Many  psychologists  are  familiar  with  the  notion  that  behavior  is  hier- 
archically organized  because  they  remember  Clark  Hull's  use  of  the  phrase 
"habit-family  hierarchy."  We  must  hasten  to  say,  therefore,  that  Hull's  use  of 
the  term  "hierarchy"  and  our  present  use  of  that  term  have  almost  nothing  in 
common.  We  are  talking  about  a  hierarchy  of  levels  of  representation.  Hull  was 
talking  about  an  ordering  of  alternative  (interchangeable,  substitutable)  re- 
sponses according  to  their  strengths.  See,  for  example,  C.  L.  Hull,  The  concept 
of  the  habit-family  hierarchy  and  maze  learning.  Psychological  Review,  1934, 
41,  33-54;  134-152.  Closer  to  the  spirit  of  the  present  discussion  is  the  system  of 
behavioral  episodes  used  by  Roger  G.  Barker  and  Herbert  F.  Wright,  in  Midwest 
and  Its  Children  (Evanston:  Row,  Peterson,  1954),  to  describe  the  molar  behav- 
ior of  children  in  their  natural  habitats.  The  work  of  Barker  and  Wright  is  a 
noteworthy  exception  to  our  assertion  that  psychologists  have  not  tried  to  de- 
scribe the  structural  features  of  behavior. 

1°  The  tree  and  outline  forms  of  representation  are  quite  ancient  and  fa- 
miliar, but  the  use  of  list  structures  for  representing  such  organizations  is,  we 
believe,  relatively  new.  We  first  became  acquainted  with  it  through  the  work  of 
Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon  on  the  simulation  of  cognitive  processes  by  computer 
programs.  See,  for  example,  Allen  NeweU  and  Herbert  A.  Simon,  The  logic  theory 
machine:  A  complex  information  processing  system,  IRE  Transactions  on  In- 
formation Theory,  1956,  Vol.  IT-2,  No.  3,  61-79.  Also,  Allen  Newell  and  J.  C. 
Shaw,  Programming  the  logic  theory  machine.  Proceedings  of  the  Western  Joint 
Computer  Conference,  Los  Angeles,  February  1957,  pp.  230-240. 

Images  and  Plans  ■   15 


tions:  Where  X  occurs,  we  can  substitute  for  it  AB;  where  A  occurs 
we  can  substitute  ab;  etc.^^  Each  of  these  methods  of  presentation  of 
a  hierarchy  has  its  special  advantages  in  special  situations. 

Now,  if  the  hierarchical  nature  of  the  organization  of  behavior 
can  be  taken  as  axiomatic,  the  time  has  come  to  set  aside  a  few 
terms  for  the  special  purposes  of  the  present  discussions.  Because 
definitions  make  heavy  reading,  we  shall  keep  the  hst  as  short  as  pos- 
sible. 

Plan.  Any  complete  description  of  behavior  should  be  adequate 
to  serve  as  a  set  of  instructions,  that  is,  it  should  have  the  characteris- 
tics of  a  plan  that  could  guide  the  action  described.  When  we  speak  of 
a  Plan  in  these  pages,  however,  the  term  will  refer  to  a  hierarchy  of 
instructions,  and  the  capitaUzation  will  indicate  that  this  special  in- 
terpretation is  intended.  A  Plan  is  any  hierarchical  process  in  the 
organism  that  can  control  the  order  in  which  a  sequence  of  operations 
is  to  be  performed. 

A  Plan  is,  for  an  organism,  essentially  the  same  as  a  program 
for  a  computer,  especially  if  the  program  has  the  sort  of  hierarchical 
character  described  above.  Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon  have  exphcitly 
and  systematically  used  the  hierarchical  structure  of  Hsts  in  their  de- 
velopment of  "information-processing  languages"  that  are  used  to 
program  high-speed  digital  computers  to  simulate  human  thought 
processes.  Their  success  in  this  direction — which  the  present  au- 
thors find  most  impressive  and  encouraging — argues  strongly  for  the 
hypothesis  that  a  hierarchical  structure  is  the  basic  form  of  organiza- 
tion in  human  problem-solving.  Thus,  we  are  reasonably  confident 
that  "program"  could  be  substituted  everywhere  for  "Plan"  in  the 
following  pages.  However,  the  reduction  of  Plans  to  nothing  but  pro- 
grams is  still  a  scientific  hypothesis  and  is  still  in  need  of  further 
validation.  For  the  present,  therefore,  it  should  be  less  confusing  if 
we  regard  a  computer  program  that  simulates  certain  features  of  an 
organism's  behavior  as  a  theory  about  the  organismic  Plan  that  gen- 
erated the  behavior.^^ 

11  Chomsky,  op.  cit.,  p.  26. 

12  It  should  be  clearly  recognized  that,  as  Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon  point 
out,  comparing  the  sequence  of  operations  executed  by  an  organism  and  by  a 
properly  programmed  computer  is  quite  different  from  comparing  computers 
with  brains,  or  electrical  relays  with  synapses,  etc.  See  Allen  Newell,  J.  C.  Shaw, 
and  Herbert  A.  Simon,  Elements  of  a  theory  of  human  problem  solving.  Psy- 

i6  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


Moreover,  we  shall  also  use  the  term  'Tlan"  to  designate  a 
rough  sketch  of  some  course  of  action,  just  the  major  topic  headings 
in  the  outline,  as  well  as  the  completely  detailed  specification  of  every 
detailed  operation. ^^ 

Strategy  and  Tactics.  The  concept  of  the  hierarchical  organiza- 
tion of  behavior  was  introduced  earlier  with  the  distinction  between 
molar  and  molecular  units  of  analysis.  Now,  however,  we  wish  to 
augment  our  terminology.  The  molar  units  in  the  organization  of 
behavior  will  be  said  to  comprise  the  behavioral  strategy,  and  the 
molecular  units,  the  tactics. 

Execution.  We  shall  say  that  a  creature  is  executing  a  particular 
Plan  when  in  fact  that  Plan  is  controlling  the  sequence  of  operations 
he  is  carrying  out.  When  an  organism  executes  a  Plan  he  proceeds 
through  it  step  by  step,  completing  one  part  and  then  moving  to  the 
next.  The  execution  of  a  Plan  need  not  result  in  overt  action — espe- 
cially in  man,  it  seems  to  be  true  that  there  are  Plans  for  collecting  or 
transforming  information,  as  well  as  Plans  for  guiding  actions.  Al- 
though it  is  not  actually  necessary,  we  assume  on  intuitive  grounds 
that  only  one  Plan  is  executed  at  a  time,  although  relatively  rapid 
alternation  between  Plans  may  be  possible.  An  organism  may — 
probably  does — store  many  Plans  other  than  the  ones  it  happens  to  be 
executing  at  the  moment. 

Image.  The  Image  is  all  the  accumulated,  organized  knowledge 
that  the  organism  has  about  itself  and  its  world.  The  Image  consists 
of  a  great  deal  more  than  imagery,  of  course.  What  we  have  in  mind 
when  we  use  this  term  is  essentially  the  same  kind  of  private  repre- 
sentation that  other  cognitive  theorists  have  demanded.  It  includes 


chological  Review,  1958,  65,  151-166.  Also,  Herbert  A.  Simon  and  Allen  Newell, 
Models,  their  uses  and  limitations,  in  L.  D.  White,  ed..  The  State  of  the  Social 
Sciences  (Chicago:  University  of  Chicago  Press,  1956),  pp.  66-83. 

13  Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon  have  also  used  "plan"  to  describe  a  general 
strategy  before  the  details  have  been  worked  out,  but  they  distinguish  between 
such  a  plan  and  the  program  that  enables  a  computer  to  use  planning  as  one  of 
its  problem-solving  techniques.  See  Allen  Newell,  J.  C.  Shaw,  and  Herbert  A. 
Simon,  A  report  on  a  general  problem  solving  program.  Proceedings  of  the  Inter- 
national  Conference  on  Information  Processing,  Paris,  1959  (in  press). 

Other  workers  have  used  the  term  "machine"  rather  loosely  to  include  both 
the  Plan  and  the  instrument  that  executes  it.  For  example,  see  M.  L.  Minsky, 
Heuristic  Aspects  of  the  Artificial  Intelligence  Problem,  Group  Report  34—55, 
Lincoln  Laboratory,  Massachusetts  Institute  of  Technology,  17  December  1956, 
especially  Section  ni.3. 

Images  and  Plans  ■   17 


everything  the  organism  has  learned — his  values  as  well  as  his 
facts — organized  by  whatever  concepts,  images,  or  relations  he  has 
been  able  to  master. 

In  the  course  of  prolonged  debates  the  present  authors  heard 
themselves  using  many  other  terms  to  modify  "Plan"  in  rather  spe- 
cial ways,  but  they  will  not  be  Hsted  here.  New  terms  will  be  defined 
and  developed  as  they  are  needed  in  the  course  of  the  argument  that 
follows.  For  the  moment,  however,  we  have  defined  enough  to  be 
able  to  say  that  the  central  problem  of  this  book  is  to  explore  the  rela- 
tion between  the  Image  and  the  Plan. 

Stated  so,  it  may  seem  to  imply  some  sharp  dichotomy  between 
the  two,  so  that  it  would  be  meaningful  to  ask,  "Is  such-and-such  a 
process  exclusively  in  the  Plan  or  exclusively  in  the  Image?"  That  the 
two  points  of  view  cannot  be  used  in  that  way  to  classify  processes 
into  mutually  exclusive  categories  should  become  apparent  from  such 
considerations  as  these : 

— A  Plan  can  be  learned  and  so  would  be  a  part  of  the  Image. 

— The  names  that  Plans  have  must  comprise  a  part  of  the  Image 
for  human  beings,  since  it  must  be  part  of  a  person's  Image  of  him- 
self that  he  is  able  to  execute  such-and-such  Plans. 

— Knowledge  must  be  incorporated  into  the  Plan,  since  other- 
wise it  could  not  provide  a  basis  for  guiding  behavior.  Thus,  Images 
can  form  part  of  a  Plan. 

— Changes  in  the  Images  can  be  effected  only  by  executing 
Plans  for  gathering,  storing,  or  transforming  information. 

— Changes  in  the  Plans  can  be  effected  only  by  information 
drawn  from  the  Images. 

— The  transformation  of  descriptions  into  instructions  is,  for 
human  beings,  a  simple  verbal  trick. 

Psychologists  who  are  accustomed  to  think  of  their  problem  as 
the  investigation  of  relations  between  Stimulus  and  Response  are  apt 
to  view  the  present  undertaking  in  a  parallel  way — as  an  investigation 
of  relations  between  a  subjective  stimulus  and  a  subjective  response. 
If  that  were  all  we  had  to  say,  however,  we  would  scarcely  have  writ- 
ten a  book  to  say  it.  Stimulus  and  response  are  physiological  concepts 
borrowed  from  the  discussion  of  reflexes.  But  we  have  rejected  the 
classical  concept  of  the  reflex  arc  as  the  fundamental  pattern  for  the 

i8  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


organization  of  all  behavior,  and  consequently  we  do  not  feel  a  need 
to  extend  the  classic  disjunction  between  stimulus  and  response 
variables  into  the  realm  of  Images  and  Plans.  To  assume  that  a  Plan 
is  a  covert  response  to  some  inner  Image  of  a  stimulus  does  nothing 
but  parallel  objective  concepts  with  subjective  equivalents  and  leaves 
the  reflex  arc  still  master — albeit  a  rather  ghostly  master — of  the 
machinery  of  the  mind.  We  are  not  likely  to  overthrow  an  old  master 
without  the  help  of  a  new  one,  so  it  is  to  the  task  of  finding  a  successor 
that  we  must  turn  next. 


Images  and  Plans  ■   ig 


CHAPTER  2 


THE   UNIT  OF 
ANALYSIS 


Most  psychologists  take  it  for  granted  that  a  scientific  account  of 
the  behavior  of  organisms  must  begin  with  the  definition  of  fixed, 
recognizable,  elementary  units  of  behavior — something  a  psycholo- 
gist can  use  as  a  biologist  uses  cells,  or  an  astronomer  uses  stars,  or 
a  physicist  uses  atoms,  and  so  on.  Given  a  simple  unit,  complicated 
phenomena  are  then  describable  as  lawful  compounds.  That  is  the 
essence  of  the  highly  successful  strategy  called  "scientific  analysis." 

The  elementary  unit  that  modern,  experimental  psychologists 
generally  select  for  their  analysis  of  behavior  is  the  reflex.  "The  isola- 
tion of  a  reflex,"  B.  F.  Skinner  tells  us,  "is  the  demonstration  of  a 
predictable  uniformity  in  behavior.  In  some  form  or  other  it  is  an 
inevitable  part  of  any  science  of  behavior,  ...  A  reflex  is  not,  of 
course,  a  theory.  It  is  a  fact.  It  is  an  analytical  unit,  which  makes  the 
investigation  of  behavior  possible."  ^  Skinner  is  quite  careful  to  define 
a  reflex  as  a  unit  of  behavior  that  will  yield  orderly  data:  "The  ap- 

1  B.  F.  Skinner,  The  Behavior  of  Organisms  (New  York:  Appleton-Century- 
Crofts,  1938),  p.  9. 

The  Unit  of  Analysis  ■  21 


pearance  of  smooth  curves  in  dynamic  processes  marks  a  unique 
point  in  the  progressive  restriction  of  a  preparation,  and  it  is  to  this 
uniquely  determined  entity  that  the  term  reflex  may  be  assigned."  ^ 
This  somevs^hat  odd  approach  to  the  reflex — in  terms  of  the  smooth- 
ness of  curves — results  from  Skinner's  consistent  attempt  to  define  a 
unit  of  behavior  in  terms  of  behavior  itself  instead  of  by  reference  to 
concepts  drawn  from  some  other  branch  of  science. 

Although  Skinner's  approach  absolves  the  psychologist  of  certain 
burdensome  responsibilities  toward  his  biological  colleagues,  the  fact 
remains  that  the  reflex  is  a  concept  borrowed  originally  from  physi- 
ology and  made  to  seem  psychologically  substantial  largely  by  the 
myth  of  the  reflex  arc:  stimulus  ->  receptor —>  afferent  nerve  — >  con- 
nective fibers  — >  efferent  nerve  -»  effector  -^  response.  For  many  years 
aU  those  elementary  textbooks  of  psychology  that  mentioned  the 
nervous  system  featured  the  traditional,  simplified  diagram  of  the  re- 
flex arc  in  a  very  prominent  position.  You  may  ignore  a  behaviorist 
when  he  tells  you  that  the  reflex  is  a  fact,  but  you  can  scarcely  ignore 
a  physiologist  when  he  draws  you  a  picture  of  it.  You  might  as  well 
deny  the  small  intestines  or  sneer  at  the  medulla  oblongata  as  to 
doubt  the  reflex  arc.  Even  the  most  obstinate  opponent  of  physiologi- 
cal explanations  in  psychology  can  scarcely  forget  the  bloody  tissue 
from  which  the  reflex — even  the  reflex-sans-arc — originally  grew. 

But  let  us  suppose,  by  a  wild  and  irresponsible  flight  of  fancy, 
that  the  physiologists  and  neurologists  suddenly  announced  that 
they  had  been  mistaken,  that  there  was  no  such  fact  as  a  reflex  arc 
and  that  the  data  on  which  the  theory  had  been  based  were  actually 
quite  different  from  what  had  originally  been  supposed.  What  then 
would  psychologists  say?  Would  they  persist  in  talking  about  re- 
flexes? Has  the  reflex  concept  been  so  tremendously  helpful  that 
behaviorists  could  not  afford  to  give  it  up,  even  if  its  biological  basis 
were  demohshed? 

There  is  some  reason  to  think  that  the  reflex  unit  has  been 
vastly  overrated  and  that  a  good  many  psychologists  would  like  to 
get  out  from  under  it  if  they  could.  The  reflex  arc  may  have  been  help- 
ful in  getting  psychology  started  along  scientific  paths,  but  the  suspi- 
cion has  been  growing  in  recent  years  that  the  reflex  idea  is  too  sim- 

2  Ibid.,  p.  40. 

22  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


pie,  the  element  too  elementary.  For  the  most  part,  serious  students 
of  behavior  have  had  to  ignore  the  problem  of  units  entirely.  Or  they 
have  had  to  modify  their  units  so  drastically  for  each  new  set  of  data 
that  to  speak  of  them  as  elementary  would  be  the  most  unblushing 
sophistry.  After  watching  psychologists  struggle  under  their  burden 
of  conditioning  reflexes,  Chomsky,  the  linguist  and  logician,  recently 
summarized  their  plight  in  the  following  terms : 

The  notions  of  "stimulus,"  "response,"  "reinforcement"  are 
relatively  well  defined  with  respect  to  the  bar-pressing  experi- 
ments and  others  similarly  restricted.  Before  we  can  extend 
them  to  real-life  behavior,  however,  certain  difficulties  must  be 
faced.  We  must  decide,  first  of  all,  whether  any  physical  event 
to  which  the  organism  is  capable  of  reacting  is  to  be  called  a  stim- 
ulus on  a  given  occasion,  or  only  one  to  which  the  organism  in 
fact  reacts;  and  correspondingly,  we  must  decide  whether  any 
part  of  behavior  is  to  be  called  a  response,  or  only  one  connected 
with  stimuli  in  lawful  ways.  Questions  of  this  sort  pose  some- 
thing of  a  dilemma  for  the  experimental  psychologist.  If  he  ac- 
cepts the  broad  definitions,  characterizing  any  physical  event 
impinging  on  the  organism  as  a  stimulus  and  any  part  of  the  or- 
ganism's behavior  as  a  response,  he  must  conclude  that  behavior 
has  not  been  demonstrated  to  be  lawful.  In  the  present  state  of 
our  knowledge,  we  must  attribute  an  overwhelming  influence  on 
actual  behavior  to  ill-defined  factors  of  attention,  set,  volition, 
and  caprice.  If  we  accept  the  narrower  definitions,  then  behavior 
is  lawful  by  definition  (if  it  consists  of  responses);  but  this  fact 
is  of  limited  significance,  since  most  of  what  the  animal  does 
will  simply  not  be  considered  behavior.^ 

Faced  with  the  choice  of  being  either  vague  or  irrelevant,  many  psy- 
chologists have  been  restive  and  ill  at  ease  with  their  borrowed  terms. 
What  went  wrong?  How  was  the  reflex  arc  conceived  originally,  and 
for  what  purpose?  Can  we  supplant  the  reflex  arc  with  some  theory  of 
the  reflex  that  is  more  suited  to  our  current  knowledge  and  inter- 
ests? 

Sir  Charles  Sherrington  and  Ivan  Petrovitch  Pavlov  are  the  two 
men  who  are  probably  most  responsible  for  confirming  the  psycholo- 
gist's Image  of  man  as  a  bundle  of  S-R  reflexes.  Yet  one  may  be  per- 

8  The  passage  quoted  is  from  page  30  of  Chomsky's  review  of  B.  F.  Skinner, 
Verbal  Behavior,  in  Language,  1959,  35,  26-58. 

The  Unit  of  Analysis  ■  23 


mitted  to  speculate  that  neither  of  them  would  approve  of  the  way 
their  concepts  have  been  extended  by  psychologists.  In  his  Integra- 
tive Action  of  the  Nervous  System  (1906)  Sherrington  is  particularly 
explicit  in  his  qualifications  and  warnings  about  the  reflex.  Again 
and  again  he  states  that  "the  simple  reflex  is  a  useful  fiction" — 
useful  for  the  study  of  the  spinal  preparation.  He  expressed  considera- 
ble doubt  that  a  stretch  reflex,  of  which  the  knee  jerk  is  the  most  fre- 
quently quoted  example,  represented  his  notion  of  a  simple  reflex  and 
questioned  whether  it  should  be  considered  a  reflex  at  all.  The 
synapse  was  invented  by  Sherrington  in  order  to  explain  the  differ- 
ences between  the  observed  properties  of  nerve  trunks  and  the  prop- 
erties that  had  to  be  inferred  to  describe  the  neural  tissue  that  in- 
tervenes between  receptor  stimulation  and  effector  response.  Nerve 
trunks  will  transmit  signals  in  either  direction.  Characteristically, 
the  signals  are  of  an  all-or-none  type.  Reflex  action,  on  the  other 
hand,  is  unidirectional  and  the  response  is  characteristically  graded 
according  to  the  intensity  of  the  stimulus.  How  can  these  be  recon- 
ciled? Sherrington  resolved  the  differences  by  supporting  the  neuron 
doctrine:  the  nervous  system  is  made  up  of  discrete  neural  units 
that  have  the  properties  of  nerve  trunks;  intercalated  between  these 
units  are  discontinuities  which  he  christened  "synapses,"  and  these 
have  the  properties  unique  to  reflexes. 

In  recent  years,  graded  responses  have  been  shown  to  be  a  pre- 
potent characteristic  not  only  of  synapses  but  also  of  all  excitable 
tissue,  for  example,  of  the  finer  arborizations  of  the  nerve  cells.  The 
cerebral  cortex,  man's  claim  to  phylogenetic  eminence,  "still  oper- 
ates largely  by  means  of  connections  characteristic  of  primitive 
neuropil  [which  is]  the  most  appropriate  mechanism  for  the  main- 
tenance of  a  continuous  or  steady  state,  as  contrasted  to  the  trans- 
mission of  information  about  such  states."  * 

Moreover,  additional  data  have  come  to  light.  Today  we  know 
that  neural  and  receptor  tissues  are  spontaneously  active  irrespec- 
tive of  environmental  excitation.  This  spontaneous  activity  is,  of 
course,  altered  by  environmental  events — but  the  change  in  spon- 
taneous activity  may  outlast  the  direct  excitation  by  hours  and  even 

*  George  Bishop,  The  natural  history  of  the  nerve  impulse,  Physiological  Re- 
views, 1956,  36,  376-399. 

24  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


days.  Furthermore,  we  know  now  that  the  activity  of  receptors  is  con- 
trolled by  efferents  leading  to  them  from  the  central  nervous  sys- 
tem. As  an  example,  consider  the  events  that  control  muscular  con- 
traction. (Similar,  though  not  identical,  mechanisms  have  also  been 
described  for  the  various  sensory  systems.)  One  third  of  the  "motor" 
nerve  fibers  that  go  to  muscle  actually  end  in  spindles  that  are  the 
stretch-sensitive  receptors.  Electrical  stimulation  of  these  nerve 
fibers  does  not  result  in  contraction  of  muscle;  but  the  number  of 
signals  per  unit  time  that  are  recorded  from  the  "sensory"  nerves 
coming  from  the  spindles  is  altered  drastically.  It  is  assumed,  there- 
fore, that  the  central  nervous  mechanism  must  compare  the  incoming 
pattern  of  signals  with  the  centrally  originating  "spindle  control" 
signal  pattern  in  order  to  determine  what  contribution  the  muscular 
contraction  has  made  to  the  "spindle  sensing"  pattern.  The  outcome 
of  this  comparison,  or  test,  constitutes  the  stimulus  (the  psychophysi- 
cist's  proximal  stimulus)  to  which  the  organism  is  sensitive.  The  test 
represents  the  conditions  which  have  to  be  met  before  the  response 
win  occur.  The  test  may  occur  in  the  receptor  itself  (e.g.,  in  the 
retina)  or  in  a  more  centrally  located  neuronal  aggregate  (as  is 
probably  the  case  for  muscle  stretch). 

It  is  clear  from  examples  such  as  this  that  the  neural  mecha- 
nism involved  in  reflex  action  cannot  be  diagrammed  as  a  simple  re- 
flex arc  or  even  as  a  chain  of  stimulus-response  connections.  A  much 
more  complex  kind  of  monitoring,  or  testing,  is  involved  in  reflex  ac- 
tion than  the  classical  reflex  arc  makes  any  provision  for.  The  only 
conditions  imposed  upon  the  stimulus  by  the  classical  chain  of  ele- 
ments are  the  criteria  implicit  in  the  thresholds  of  each  element;  if  the 
distal  stimulus  is  strong  enough  to  surmount  the  thresholds  aU  along 
the  arc,  then  the  response  must  occur.  In  a  sense,  the  threshold  is  a 
kind  of  test,  too,  a  condition  that  must  be  met,  but  it  is  a  test  of 
strength  only.  And  it  must  have  encouraged  psychologists  to  beUeve 
that  the  only  meaningful  measurement  of  a  reflex  was  its  strength 
(probabihty,  magnitude,  or  latency). 

The  threshold,  however,  is  only  one  of  many  different  ways  that 
the  input  can  be  tested.  Moreover,  the  response  of  the  effector  de- 
pends upon  the  outcome  of  the  test  and  is  most  conveniently  con- 
ceived as  an  effort  to  modify  the  outcome  of  the  test.  The  action  is 

The  Unit  of  Analysis  ■  25 


initiated  by  an  "incongruity"  between  the  state  of  the  organism  and 
the  state  that  is  being  tested  for,  and  the  action  persists  until  the  in- 
congruity (i.e.,  the  proximal  stimulus)  is  removed.  The  general  pat- 
tern of  reflex  action,  therefore,  is  to  test  the  input  energies  against 
some  criteria  established  in  the  organism,  to  respond  if  the  result  of 
the  test  is  to  show  an  incongruity,  and  to  continue  to  respond  until 
the  incongruity  vanishes,  at  which  time  the  reflex  is  terminated.  Thus, 
there  is  "feedback"  from  the  result  of  the  action  to  the  testing  phase, 
and  we  are  confronted  by  a  recursive  loop.  The  simplest  kind  of 
diagram  to  represent  this  conception  of  reflex  action — an  alternative 
to  the  classical  reflex  arc — would  have  to  look  something  like  Fig- 
ure 1. 

The  interpretation  toward  which  the  argument  moves  is  one 
that  has  been  called  the  "cybernetic  hypothesis,"  namely,  that  the 
fundamental  building  block  of  the  nervous  system  is  the  feedback 


'/  '^  ^  ^ 

^ 

1  t^^L 

(Congruitij) 

(Incongrui 

> 

> 

\ 

Operate 

FIGURE  I.  The  TOTE  unit 


26  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


loop.^  The  development  of  a  mathematical  theory  for  servomecha- 
nisms,  wedded  to  the  physiological  accounts  of  homeostatic  mecha- 
nisms, has  stimulated  widespread  discussion  and  speculation  about 
devices  closely  akin  to  Figure  1.  The  argument,  therefore,  moves  to- 
ward popular  ground. 

But  what  good  is  this  alternative  interpretation  of  the  reflex?  The 
psychologist  was  interested  in  reflexes  because  he  thought  they 
might  provide  the  units  he  needed  to  describe  behavior.  But  simple 
reflexes  have  been  inadequate.  And  if  reflexes  based  on  afferent-ef- 
ferent arcs  would  not  turn  the  trick,  why  should  we  hope  for  better 
things  from  reflexes  based  on  feedback  loops?  It  is  the  reflex  itself — 
not  merely  the  reflex  arc — that  has  failed,  and  repairing  the  neurolog- 
ical theory  underlying  it  is  not  likely  to  save  the  day.  What  do  we 
hope  to  gain  from  such  a  reinterpretation? 

Obviously,  the  reflex  is  not  the  unit  we  should  use  as  the  ele- 
ment of  behavior:  the  unit  should  be  the  feedback  loop  itself.  If  we 
think  of  the  Test-Operate-Test-Exit  unit — for  convenience,  we  shall 
call  it  a  TOTE  unit — as  we  do  of  the  reflex  arc,  in  purely  anatomical 
terms,  it  may  describe  reflexes,  but  little  else.  That  is  to  say,  the 
reflex  should  be  recognized  as  only  one  of  many  possible  actualiza- 
tions of  a  TOTE  pattern.  The  next  task  is  to  generalize  the  TOTE 
unit  so  that  it  will  be  useful  in  a  majority — hopefully,  in  all — of  the 
behavioral  descriptions  we  shall  need  to  make. 

Consider  what  the  arrows  in  Figure  1  might  represent.  What 
could  flow  along  them  from  one  box  to  another?  We  shall  discuss 
three  alternatives:  energy,  information,  and  control.  If  we  think  of 
energy^neural  impulses,  for  example — flowing  from  one  place  to 
another  over  the  arrows,  then  the  arrows  must  correspond  to  recog- 
nizable physical  structures — neurons,  in  the  example  chosen.  As  a 
diagram  of  energy  flow  over  discrete  pathways,  therefore,  the  TOTE 
unit  described  in  Figure  1  might  represent  a  simple  reflex.  Or  it  might 
represent  a  servomechanism. 

There  is,  however,  a  second  level  of  abstraction  that  psycholo- 

5  Norbert  Wiener,  Cybernetics  (New  York:  Wiley,  1948).  For  a  short  review 
of  the  early  development  of  this  idea,  see  J.  O.  Wisdom,  The  hypothesis  of  cyber- 
netics, British  Journal  for  the  Philosophy  of  Science,  1951,  2,  1-24.  For  more 
comprehensive  discussion,  see  W.  Sluckin,  Minds  and  Machines  (London:  Pen- 
guin, 1954).  A  little  of  the  cybernetic  story  is  reviewed  in  the  next  chapter. 

The  Unit  of  Analysis  ■  27 


gists  usually  prefer.  We  can  think  of  information  as  flowing  from 
one  place  to  another  over  the  arrows.  According  to  the  method  of 
measuring  information  that  has  been  developed  by  Norbert  Wiener_ 
and  by  Claude  Shannon,  information  is  transmitted  over  a  channel  to 
the  extent  that  the  output  of  the  channel  is  correlated  with  the  input.® 
We  could  therefore  think  of  this  second  level  of  abstraction  as  the 
transmission  of  correlation  over  the  arrows.  In  that  case,  we  are 
concerned  not  with  the  particular  structures  or  kinds  of  energy  that 
are  involved  in  producing  the  correlation  but  only  with  the  fact  that 
events  at  the  two  ends  of  the  arrow  are  correlated.  The  situation  is 
quite  familiar  to  psychologists,  for  it  is  exactly  what  they  mean  when 
they  draw  an  arrow  leading  from  Stimulus  to  Response  in  their  S-R 
diagrams  or  when  they  define  a  reflex  as  a  correlation  between  S  and 
R  but  refuse  to  talk  about  the  neurological  basis  for  that  correlation. 
A  third  level  of  abstraction,  however,  is  extremely  important  for 
the  ideas  we  shall  discuss  in  the  pages  that  follow.  It  is  the  notioii 
that  what  flows  over  the  arrows  in  Figure  1  is  an  intangible  something 
called  control.  Or  perhaps  we  should  say  that  the  arrow  indicates  only 
succession.  This  concept  appears  most  frequently  in  the  discussion 
of  computing  machines,  where  the  control  of  the  machine's  opera- 
tions passes  from  one  instruction  to  another,  successively,  as  the  ma- 
chine proceeds  to  execute  the  list  of  instructions  that  comprise  the 
program  it  has  been  given.  But  the  idea  is  certainly  not  limited  to^ 
computers!  As  a  simple  example  drawn  from  more  familiar  activities, 
imagine  that  you  wanted  to  look  up  a  particular  topic  in  a  certain 
book  in  order  to  see  what  the  author  had  to  say  about  it.  You  would 
open  the  book  to  the  index  and  find  the  topic.  Following  the  entry  is  a 
string  of  numbers.  As  you  look  up  each  page  reference  in  turn,  your 
behavior  can  be  described  as  under  the  control  of  that  list  of  numbers, 
and  control  is  transferred  from  one  number  to  the  next  as  you  pro- 
ceed through  the  list.  The  transfer  of  control  could  be  symbolized  by 
drawing  arrows  from  one  page  number  to  the  next,  but  the  arrows 

6  A  short  introduction  to  these  ideas  written  for  psychologists  can  be  found 
in  G.  A.  Miller,  What  is  information  measurement?  American  Psychologist,  1953, 
8,  3-11.  A  fuller  account  has  been  given  by  Fred  Attneave,  Applications  of  In- 
formation Theory  to  Psychology  (New  York:  Holt,  1959).  See  also  the  highly 
readable  account  by  Colin  Cherry,  On  Human  Communication  (Cambridge: 
Technology  Press,  1957). 

28  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


would  have  a  meaning  quite  different  from  the  two  meanings  men- 
tioned previously.  Here  we  are  not  concerned  with  a  flow  of  energy  or 
transmission  of  information  from  one  page  number  to  the  next  but 
merely  with  the  order  in  which  the  "instructions"  are  executed. 

At  this  abstract  level  of  description  we  are  no  longer  required  to 
think  of  the  test  as  a  simple  threshold  that  some  stimulus  energy 
must  exceed.  The  test  phase  can  be  regarded  as  any  process  for  de- 
termining that  the  operational  phase  is  appropriate.  For  example,  to 
be  clear  though  crude,  we  do  not  try  to  take  the  square  root  of  "rati- 
ocinate." We  may  know  full  well  how  to  extract  square  roots,  but  be- 
fore we  can  execute  that  operation  we  must  have  digits  to  work  on. 
The  operation  of  extracting  square  roots  is  simply  irrelevant  when 
we  are  dealing  with  words.  In  order  to  ensure  that  an  operation  is 
relevant,  a  test  must  be  built  into  it.  Unless  the  test  gives  the  appro- 
priate outcome,  control  cannot  be  transferred  to  the  operational 
phase. 

When  Figure  1  is  used  in  the  discussion  of  a  simple  reflex  it 
represents  all  three  levels  of  description  simultaneously.  When  it  is 
used  to  describe  more  complex  activities,  however,  we  may  want  to 
consider  only  the  transfer  of  information  and  control  or  in  many  in- 
stances only  the  transfer  of  control.  In  all  cases,  however,  the  exist- 
ence of  a  TOTE  should  indicate  that  an  organizing,  coordinating  unit 
has  been  established,  that  a  Plan  is  available. 

In  the  following  pages  we  shall  use  the  TOTE  as  a  general  de- 
scription of  the  control  processes  involved;  the  implications  it  may 
have  for  functional  anatomy  will  remain  more  or  less  dormant  until 
Chapter  14,  at  which  point  we  shall  indulge  in  some  neuropsycholog- 
ical speculations.  Until  then,  however,  the  TOTE  will  serve  as  a 
description  at  only  the  third,  least  concrete,  level.  In  its  weakest  form, 
the  TOTE  asserts  simply  that  the  operations  an  organism  performs 
are  constantly  guided  by  the  outcomes  of  various  tests. 

The  present  authors  feel  that  the  TOTE  unit,  which  incorporates 
the  important  notion  of  feedback,  is  an  explanation  of  behavior  in 
general,  and  of  reflex  action  in  particular,  fundamentally  different 
from  the  explanation  provided  by  the  reflex  arc.  Consequently,  the 
traditional  concepts  of  stimulus  and  response  must  be  redefined  and 
reinterpreted  to  suit  their  new  context.  Stimulus  and  response  must 

The  Unit  of  Analysis  ■  29 


be  seen  as  phases  of  the  organized,  coordinated  act.  We  might  sum- 
marize it  this  way : 

The  stimulus  is  that  phase  of  the  forming  coordination 
which  represents  the  conditions  which  have  to  be  met  in  bringing 
it  to  a  successful  issue;  the  response  is  that  phase  of  one  and  the 
same  forming  coordination  which  gives  the  key  to  meeting  these 
conditions,  which  serves  as  instrument  in  effecting  the  success- 
ful coordination.  They  are  therefore  strictly  correlative  and  con- 
temporaneous.^ 

Because  stimulus  and  response  are  correlative  and  contemporaneous, 
the  stimulus  processes  must  be  thought  of  not  as  preceding  the  re- 
sponse but  rather  as  guiding  it  to  a  successful  elimination  of  the  in- 
congruity. That  is  to  say,  stimulus  and  response  must  be  considered 
as  aspects  of  a  feedback  loop. 

The  need  for  some  kind  of  feedback  channel  in  the  description 
of  behavior  is  well  recognized  by  most  reflex  theorists,  but  they  have 
introduced  it  in  a  pecuhar  way.  For  example,  it  is  customary  for  them 
to  speak  of  certain  consequences  of  a  reflex  action  as  strengthening, 
or  reinforcing,  the  reflex — such  reinforcing  consequences  of  action 
are  a  clear  example  of  feedback.  Reinforcements  are,  however,  a  spe- 
cial kind  of  feedback  that  should  not  be  identified  with  the  feedback 
involved  in  a  TOTE  unit.  That  is  to  say:  (1)  a  reinforcing  feedback 
must  strengthen  something,  whereas  feedback  in  a  TOTE  is  for  the 
purpose  of  comparison  and  testing;  (2)  a  reinforcing  feedback  is  con- 
sidered to  be  a  stimulus  (e.g.,  pellet  of  food),  whereas  feedback  in  a 
TOTE  may  be  a  stimulus,  or  information  (e.g.,  knowledge  of  results), 
or  control  (e.g.,  instructions);  and  (3)  a  reinforcing  feedback  is  fre- 
quently considered  to  be  valuable,  or  "drive  reducing,"  to  the  organ- 
ism, whereas  feedback  in  a  TOTE  has  no  such  value  (see  Chapter  4). 

When  a  TOTE  has  been  executed — the  operations  performed, 

the  test  satisfied,  and  the  exit  made — the  creature  may  indeed  appear 

to  have  attained  a  more  desirable  state.  It  may  even  be  true,  on  the 

average,  that  the  TOTE  units  that  are  completed  successfully  in  a 

given  situation  tend  to  recur  with  increased  probability,  although 

'  This  passage  is  from  an  article  by  John  Dewey  entitled,  "The  Reflex  Arc 
Concept  in  Psychology,"  an  article  as  valuable  today  for  its  wisdom  and  insight 
as  it  was  in  1896. 

30  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


such  a  relation  would  not  be  necessary.  Thus  it  is  possible  to  discuss 
a  TOTE  in  the  language  of  reinforcements.  Nevertheless,  the  TOTE 
involves  a  much  more  general  conception  of  feedback.  The  concept 
of  reinforcement  represents  an  important  step  forward  from  reflex 
arcs  toward  feedback  loops,  but  bolder  strides  are  needed  if  behavior 
theory  is  to  advance  beyond  the  description  of  simple  conditioning 
experiments. 

Perhaps  variations  in  the  basic  TOTE  pattern  will  prove  neces- 
sary, so  for  the  purposes  of  the  present  discussion  we  shall  continue 
to  regard  the  diagram  in  Figure  1  as  a  hypothesis  rather  than  a  fact. 
The  importance  of  this  hypothesis  to  the  general  thesis  of  the  book, 
however,  should  not  be  overlooked.  It  is,  in  capsule,  the  account  we 
wish  to  give  of  the  relation  between  Image  and  action.  The  TOTE 
represents  the  basic  pattern  in  which  our  Plans  are  cast,  the  test 
phase  of  the  TOTE  involves  the  specification  of  whatever  knowledge 
is  necessary  for  the  comparison  that  is  to  be  made,  and  the  opera- 
tional phase  represents  what  the  organism  does  about  it — and  what 
the  organism  does  may  often  involve  overt,  observable  actions.  Fig- 
ure 1,  therefore,  rephrases  the  problem  posed  in  Chapter  1 :  How  does 
a  Plan  relate  the  organism's  Image  of  itself  and  its  universe  to  the 
actions,  the  responses,  the  behavior  that  the  organism  is  seen  to 
generate? 

Let  us  see  what  we  must  do  in  order  to  expand  this  proposal  into 
something  useful.  One  of  the  first  difficulties — a  small  one —  is  to  say 
more  exactly  what  we  mean  by  the  "incongruity"  that  the  test  phase  is 
looking  for.  Why  not  talk  simply  about  the  difference,  rather  than  the 
incongruity,  as  providing  the  proximal  stimulus?  The  answer  is  not 
profound :  We  do  not  want  to  bother  to  distinguish  between  TOTEs  in 
which  the  operations  are  performed  only  when  a  difference  is  de- 
tected (and  where  the  operations  serve  to  diminish  the  difference) 
and  TOTEs  in  which  the  operations  are  released  only  when  no  dif- 
ference is  detected.  When  the  diagram  is  used  to  describe  servomecha- 
nisms,  for  example,  it  is  quite  important  to  distinguish  "positive" 
from  "negative"  feedback,  but,  because  we  are  going  to  be  interested 
primarily  in  the  feedback  of  control,  such  questions  are  not  critical. 
Rather  than  treat  aU  these  varieties  as  different  units  of  analysis,  it 

The  Unit  of  Analysis  "31 


seems  simpler  to  treat  them  all  as  examples  of  a  more  general  type 
of  "incongruity-sensitive"  mechanism.® 

A  second  difficulty — this  one  rather  more  important — is  the 
question  of  how  we  can  integrate  this  TOTE  unit  into  the  sort  of 
hierarchical  structure  of  behavior  that  we  insisted  on  in  Chapter  1. 
How  can  the  two  concepts — feedback  and  hierarchy — be  reconciled? 
One  method  of  combining  feedback  components  in  a  hierarchy  has 
been  described  by  D.  M.  MacKay,^  who  proposed  to  make  the  conse- 
quences of  the  operational  phase  in  one  component  provide  the  input 
to  the  comparator  of  a  second  component;  MacKay's  suggestion  leads 
to  a  string  of  such  feedback  components,  each  representing  a  progres- 
sively higher  degree  of  abstraction  from  the  external  reahty.  Al- 
though MacKay's  scheme  is  quite  ingenious,  we  are  persuaded  that 
a  somewhat  different  method  of  constructing  the  hierarchy  vtdll  bet- 
ter serve  a  psychologist's  descriptive  purposes.  A  central  notion  of  the 
method  followed  in  these  pages  is  that  the  operational  components  of 
TOTE  units  may  themselves  be  TOTE  units.  That  is  to  say,  the  TOTE 
pattern  describes  both  strategic  and  tactical  units  of  behavior.  Thus 
the  operational  phase  of  a  higher-order  TOTE  might  itself  consist  of 
a  string  of  other  TOTE  units,  and  each  of  these,  in  turn,  may  contain 
still  other  strings  of  TOTEs,  and  so  on.  Since  this  method  of  retaining 
the  same  pattern  of  description  for  the  higher,  more  strategic  units  as 
for  the  lower,  more  tactical  units  may  be  confusing  on  first  acquaint- 
ance, we  shall  consider  an  example. 

R.  S.  Woodworth  has  pointed  out  how  frequently  behavioral  ac- 
tivities are  organized  in  two  stages. ^°  Woodworth  refers  to  them  as 
"two-phase  motor  units."  The  first  phase  is  preparatory  or  mobilizing; 
the  second,  effective  or  consummatory.  To  jump,  you  first  flex  the 
hips  and  knees,  then  extend  them  forcefully;  the  crouch  prepares  for 
the  jump.  To  grasp  an  object,  the  first  phase  is  to  open  your  hand, 
the  second  is  to  close  it  around  the  object.  You  must  open  your 

8  The  notion  of  an  "incongruity-sensitive"  mechanism  appears  to  the  authors 
to  be  related  to  Festinger's  conceptions  of  "cognitive  dissonance,"  but  we  have  not 
attempted  to  explore  or  develop  that  possibility.  See  Leon  Festinger,  A  Theory  of 
Cognitive  Dissonance  (Evanston:  Row,  Peterson,  1957). 

9  D.  M.  MacKay,  The  epistemological  problem  for  automata,  in  C.  E.  Shannon 
and  J.  McCarthy,  eds.,  Automata  Studies  (Princeton:  Princeton  University  Press, 
1956),  pp.  235-251. 

10  Robert  S.  Woodworth,  Dynamics  of  Behavior  (New  York:  Holt,  1958),  pp. 
36  £E. 

32  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


mouth  before  you  can  bite.  You  must  draw  back  your  arm  before  you 
can  strike,  etc.  The  two  phases  are  quite  different  movements,  yet 
they  are  obviously  executed  as  a  single  unit  of  action.  If  stimulation 
is  correct  for  releasing  the  action,  first  the  preparatory  TOTE  unit 
is  executed,  and  when  it  has  been  completed  the  stimulation  is  ade- 
quate for  the  consummatory  TOTE  unit  and  the  action  is  executed. 
Many  of  these  two-phase  plans  are  repetitive :  the  completion  of  the 
second  phase  in  turn  provides  stimuli  indicating  that  the  execution 
of  the  first  phase  is  again  possible,  so  an  alternation  between  the  two 
phases  is  set  up,  as  in  walking,  running,  chewing,  drinking,  sweep- 
ing, knitting,  etc. 

We  should  note  well  the  construction  of  a  "two-phase"  TOTE 
unit  out  of  two  simpler  TOTE  units.  Consider  hammering  a  nail  as  an 


Hammering 


Lifting  Striking 

FIGURE  2.  Hammering  as  a  hierarchy 

example.  As  a  Plan,  of  course,  hammering  has  two  phases,  lifting  the 
hammer  and  then  striking  the  nail.  We  could  represent  it  by  a  tree,  or 
hierarchy,  as  in  Figure  2.  If  we  ask  about  details,  however,  the  repre- 
sentation of  hammering  in  Figure  2  as  a  simple  list  containing  two 
items  is  certainly  too  sketchy.  It  does  not  tell  us,  for  one  thing,  how 
long  to  go  on  hammering.  What  is  the  "stop  rule"?  For  this,  we  must 
indicate  the  test  phase,  as  in  Figure  3.  The  diagram  in  Figure  3 
should  indicate  that  when  control  is  transferred  to  the  TOTE  unit 
that  we  are  calling  "hammering,"  the  hammering  continues  until  the 
head  of  the  nail  is  flush  with  the  surface  of  the  work.  When  the  test 
indicates  that  the  nail  is  driven  in,  control  is  transferred  elsewhere. 
Now,  however,  we  seem  to  have  lost  the  hierarchical  structure.  The 
hierarchy  is  recovered  when  we  look  at  the  box  labeled  "hammer,"  for 
there  we  find  two  TOTE  units,  each  with  its  own  test,  as  indicated  in 
Figure  4.  When  the  pair  of  TOTE  units  combined  in  Figure  4  are  put 

The  Unit  of  Analysis  ■  33 


inside  the  operational  phase  in  Figure  3,  the  result  is  the  hierarchical 
Plan  for  hammering  nails  that  is  shown  in  Figure  5. 

If  this  description  of  hammering  is  correct,  we  should  expect 
the  sequence  of  events  to  run  off  in  this  order:  Test  nail.  (Head  sticks 
up.)  Test  hammer.  (Hammer  is  down.)  Lift  hammer.  Test  hammer. 
(Hammer  is  up.)  Test  hammer.  (Hammer  is  up.)  Strike  nail.  Test 


Test 

Nail 

(Head  flush) 

> 

(Head 

sticks  up) 

LJ  ^—t  »v^  tr%^\  ^^  "B-* 

JtlCLW 

init^i 

FIGURE  3.  Hammering  as  a  TOTE  unit 

hammer.  (Hammer  is  down.)  Test  nail.  (Head  sticks  up.)  Test  ham- 
mer. And  so  on,  until  the  test  of  the  nail  reveals  that  its  head  is  flush 
with  the  surface  of  the  work,  at  which  point  control  can  be  transferred 
elsewhere.  Thus  the  compound  of  TOTE  units  unravels  itself  simply 
enough  into  a  coordinated  sequence  of  tests  and  actions,  although 
the  underlying  structure  that  organizes  and  coordinates  the  behavior 
is  itself  hierarchical,  not  sequential. 

It  may  seem  slightly  absurd  to  analyze  the  motions  involved  in 


34  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


s  i 

1 

^•2 

2 

1 

Test 
Hammer 

•no 

CO 

1 

\ 

1. 


-^ 

<t) 

•i^ 

O 

<i) 

s 

c 

o 

u 

ij) 

t^ 

« 

05 

CO 

•1^ 

<5> 

K 

»i. 

S 

s 

o> 

e 

e 

o 

s 

h. 

^ 

s 

Si. 

s 

1 

i^ 

CO 

K. 

o 

O 

s 

b^ 

H-^ 

'T3 

^ 

^ 

o 

p< 

.« 

u 

•t^ 

CO 

a* 

CI 

o 

•fo 

u 

Tl 

1J 

s 

s 

•r-a 

<u 

ns 

CO 

a 

Q) 

Q 

00 

-« 

■^ 

fa* 

o 

PE<        Q 


— >- 

Test 
Nail 

(flush) 

(sticks  up) 

>^             I 

> 

Hammer 

(down) 

Test 
Hammer 

(np)^ 

Test 
Ham.m.er 

(d 

DWIlj 

> 
) 

< 

> 

Lift 

Strike 

FIGURE  5.  The  hierarchical  Plan  for  hammering  nails 


hammering  a  nail  in  this  explicit  way,  but  it  is  better  to  amuse  a 
reader  than  to  confuse  him.  It  is  merely  an  illustration  of  how  several 
simple  TOTE  units,  each  with  its  own  test-operate-test  loop,  can  be 
embedded  in  the  operational  phase  of  a  larger  unit  with  its  particular 
test-operate-test  loop.  Without  such  an  explicit  illustration  it  might 
not  have  been  immediately  obvious  how  these  circles  within  circles 
could  yield  hierarchical  trees. 

More  complicated  Plans — Woodworth  refers  to  them  as  "poly- 
phase motor  units" — can  be  similarly  described  as  TOTE  units  built 
up  of  subplans  that  are  themselves  TOTE  units.  A  bird  will  take  off, 
make  a  few  wing  strokes,  glide,  brake  with  its  wings,  thrust  its  feet 
forward,  and  land  on  the  limb.  The  whole  action  is  initiated  as  a  unit, 
is  controlled  by  a  single  Plan,  yet  is  composed  of  several  phases,  each 
involving  its  own  Plan,  which  may  in  turn  be  comprised  of  subplans, 
etc. 

Note  that  it  is  the  operational  phase  of  the  TOTE  that  is  ex- 
panded into  a  list  of  other  TOTE  units.  If  we  wish  to  preserve  the 
TOTE  pattern  as  it  is  diagrammed  in  Figure  1,  we  cannot  use  it  to 
build  up  more  complicated  tests.^^  The  tests  that  are  available,  there- 
fore, are  conceived  to  be  relatively  fixed;  it  is  the  operational  phase 
that  may  be  quite  various  and  complex.  The  operational  phase  may, 
of  course,  consist  of  a  list  of  TOTEs,  or  it  may  terminate  in  efferent 
activity.^  If  we  consider  complex  Plans — TOTE  hierarchies  in  which 
the  operation  of  one  TOTE  is  itself  a  Hst  of  TOTE  units— then  some 
general  properties  of  such  systems  become  apparent : 

11  The  reason  that  the  TOTE  of  Figure  1  can  be  expanded  only  in  its  opera- 
tional phase  is  purely  formal  and  can  be  appreciated  by  simple  counting:  There 
are  four  arrows  associated  with  Test;  there  are  two  arrows  associated  with  Oper- 
ate; and  there  are  two  arrows  associated  with  TOTE  as  a  unit.  Therefore,  if  the 
two-arrowed  TOTE  is  used  to  construct  some  component  of  another  TOTE,  the 
component  it  constructs  must  be  the  two-arrowed  Operate,  not  the  four-arrowed 
Test.  However,  rigid  restrictions  such  as  these  are  probably  unrealistic  and  justi- 
fiable only  in  terms  of  pedagogic  simplification.  Anyone  who  has  studied  the 
hierarchically  organized  programs  written  by  Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon  to  simu- 
late human  problem-solving  will  recognize  how  primitive  and  unelaborated  these 
TOTE  hierarchies  really  are. 

12  If  we  take  seriously  the  suggested  form  of  the  TOTE,  the  system  may  be 
easily  trapped  into  loops.  For  example,  if  the  subtests  in  the  expansion  of  an 
operational  phase  all  pass,  but  the  basic  test  fails,  a  loop  will  exist.  In  order  to 
avoid  loops  we  might  insist  that  the  basic  test  imply  the  disjunction  of  the  sub- 
tests. A  more  realistic  solution  would  accept  the  occurrence  of  loops  as  a  signal 
that  the  Plan  was  not  successful  in  producing  the  result  for  which  the  basic  test 
was  designed;  it  would  then  be  necessary  to  provide  fvurther  machinery  for  dis- 
covering and  stopping  such  loops. 

The  Unit  of  Analysis  ■  37 


— The  hierarchical  structure  underlying  behavior  is  taken  into 
account  in  a  way  that  can  be  simply  described  with  the  computer  lan- 
guage developed  by  Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon  for  processing  lists. 

— Planning  can  be  thought  of  as  constructing  a  list  of  tests  to 
perform.  When  we  have  a  clear  Image  of  a  desired  outcome,  we  can 
use  it  to  provide  the  conditions  for  which  we  must  test,  and  those 
tests,  when  arranged  in  sequence,  provide  a  crude  strategy  for  a  pos- 
sible Plan.  (Perhaps  it  would  be  more  helpful  to  say  that  the  condi- 
tions for  which  we  must  test  are  an  Image  of  the  desired  outcome.) 

— The  operational  phase  can  contain  both  tests  and  operations. 
Therefore  the  execution  of  a  Plan  of  any  complexity  must  involve 
many  more  tests  than  actions.  This  design  feature  would  account  for 
the  general  degradation  of  information  that  occurs  whenever  a  hu- 
man being  is  used  as  a  communication  channel. 

In  lower  animals  it  appears  that  the  pattern  of  their  behavior  is 
normally  constructed  more  or  less  fortuitously  by  the  environment 
— only  man  cherishes  the  illusion  of  being  master  of  his  fate.  That  is 
to  say,  the  environment  provides  stimuli  that  "release"  the  next  stage 
of  the  animal's  activity.  It  is  something  of  a  philosophical  question  as 
to  whether  we  wish  to  believe  in  plans  that  exist  somewhere  outside 
of  nervous  systems,  so  perhaps  we  should  say  merely  that  lower  ani- 
mals appear  to  have  more  tactics  than  strategy. 

As  we  ascend  the  evolutionary  scale  we  find  in  mammals  an  in- 
creasing complexity  in  the  kind  of  tests  the  animals  can  perform.  In 
man  we  have  a  unique  capacity  for  creating  and  manipulating  sym- 
bols, and  when  that  versatiUty  is  used  to  assign  names  to  TOTE  units, 
it  becomes  possible  for  him  to  use  language  in  order  to  rearrange  the 
symbols  and  to  form  new  Plans.  We  have  every  reason  to  believe  that 
man's  verbal  abilities  are  very  intimately  related  to  his  planning  abili- 
ties. And,  because  human  Plans  are  so  often  verbal,  they  can  be 
communicated,  a  fact  of  crucial  importance  in  the  evolution  of  our 
social  adjustments  to  one  another. 

Such  matters  deserve  several  separate  chapters,  but  first  we  shall 
sketch  in  some  history.  A  reader  familiar  with  the  background  out 
of  which  such  a  proposal  as  the  TOTE  hierarchy  might  grow  may 
wish  to  jump  directly  to  Chapter  4.  A  reader  curious  to  see  the  idea 

38  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


in  its  proper  perspective  on  the  intellectual  landscape,  however,  will 
want  to  know  something  about  the  relevant  discussions  and  experi- 
ments that  have  educated  the  present  authors.  Chapter  3  gives  some 
of  that  material,  along  with  references  to  books  and  articles  that  sup- 
ply a  great  deal  more. 


The  Unit  of  Analysis  ■  39 


CHAPTER  3 


THE  SIMULATION   OF 

PSYCHOLOGICAL 

PROCESSES 


A  reflex  theorist  who  is  asked  to  abandon  his  palpable  S's  and 
Rs,  to  surrender  his  network  of  S-R  connections  modeled  after  a  tele- 
phone switchboard,  and  to  replace  it  all  by  ghostly  Images  and  in- 
tangible Plans,  is  likely  to  feel  he  has  been  asked  to  walk  on  air. 
"How,"  he  grumbles,  "can  a  tough-minded  scientist  make  sense  out 
of  such  cognitive  moonshine?"  For  years  the  reflex  theorist's  stock 
in  trade  has  been  his  accusation  that  the  cognitive  theorist  was  at 
heart  a  vitahst  who  could  never  produce  a  believable  mechanism 
that  would  accomplish  what  he  claimed  for  the  Hving  brain.  "Every- 
one recognizes,"  he  would  say,  "that  comparing  the  brain  to  a  map 
control  room  is  only  a  metaphor.  If  we  were  to  take  it  seriously,  we 
would  have  to  assume  that  there  is  a  little  man  inside  the  head,  a 
homunculus  who  can  read  maps  and  make  decisions."  ^  At  least  since 

1  It  is  amusing  that  so  many  psychologists  who  abhor  subjectivism  and 
anthropomorphism  unhesitatingly  put  telephone  switchboards  inside  our  heads. 
In  1943,  for  example,  Clark  HuU,  in  his  Principles  of  Behavior  (New  York: 
Appleton-Century-Crofts),  could  take  it  as  self-evident  that  the  brain  "acts  as  a 

The  Simulation  of  Psychological  Processes  "41 


the  time  of  Descartes,  who  invented  reflex  theory  as  part  of  his  thesis 
that  the  body  is  just  a  machine,  reflex  theorists  have  been  winning 
arguments  by  insisting  on  mechanical  models  for  living  systems. 

Today,  suddenly,  the  argument  has  lost  its  force.  Now  at  long 
last  there  are  machines  complicated  enough  to  do  everything  that 
cognitive  theorists  have  been  talking  about.  Descartes  was  impressed 
by  the  clockwork  figures  that  jumped  out  of  the  shrubbery  to  startle  a 
stroller;  think  how  much  more  impressed  he  would  be  by  a  modem 
electronic  computer  that  spins  out  calculations  at  lightning  speeds. 
Leibnitz  dreamed  of  such  a  machine  and  tried  to  describe  a  thought- 
calculus  it  might  use  to  compute  answers  to  problems  that  require 
thinking.  Today  such  machines  are  operating  in  hundreds  of  labora- 
tories. The  reflex  theorist  is  no  longer  the  only  psychologist  who  can 
summon  up  a  tangible  mechanism  to  make  his  claims  sound  more 
reasonable.  Today  a  cognitive  theorist  is  also  free  to  become  a  ma- 
terialist in  good  standing — if  that  is  what  he  wants. 

Typical  of  the  new  freedom  deriving  from  a  deeper  conception 
of  what  machines  can  be  and  do  was  the  discovery  that  machines  can 
behave  purposively.  In  1943  Rosenblueth,  Wiener,  and  Bigelow 
shocked  many  psychologists  by  putting  their  very  tough-minded 
reputations  behind  the  assertion  that  machines  with  negative  feed- 
back were  teleological  mechanisms.^  At  that  time  psychologists  gen- 
erally regarded  "teleological"  and  "unscientific"  as  synonymous,  and 
it  was  therefore  surprising  to  realize  that  machines  could  strive  to- 
ward goals,  could  collect  information  about  the  difference  between 
their  intentions  and  their  performance  and  then  work  to  reduce  that 
difference.    If   entelechy   was    compatible    with    mechanism,    then 


kind  of  automatic  switchboard"  (p.  18,  repeated  on  p.  384).  However,  the  im- 
portant adjective,  "automatic,"  is  a  recent  accomplishment.  The  telephone  engi- 
neers who  had  to  build  and  maintain  those  early  switchboards  that  reflex 
theorists  loved  so  well  were  dissatisfied  with  them  because  they  required  a  human 
operator  to  make  the  connections.  Eventually,  of  course,  the  operator  was  re- 
placed by  more  elaborate  machinery,  thus  rendering  reflex  theory  scientifically 
impeccable  at  last.  But  in  1892,  when  Karl  Pearson  wrote  The  Grammar  of 
Science,  he  unblushingly  provided  a  "clerk"  who  carried  on  the  same  valuable 
services  in  the  brain  as  he  would  in  a  central  telephone  exchange. 

2  Arturo  Rosenblueth,  Norbert  Wiener,  and  Julian  Bigelow,  Behavior,  pur- 
pose, and  teleology,  Philosophy  of  Science,  1943,  10,  18-24.  W.  Ross  Ashby  had 
also  introduced  the  feedback  mechanism  as  early  as  1940  in  his  paper,  Adaptive- 
ness  and  equilibrium.  Journal  of  Mental  Science,  1940,  86,  478—483.  Priorities  are 
uncertain  because  the  ideas  were  part  of  the  development  of  servomechanisms 
and  were  subject  to  security  restrictions  during  the  war. 

42  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


entelechy  could  be  admitted  as  a  respectable  concept  in  psychology. 
Wiener  stated  the  argument  this  way : 

It  is  my  thesis  that  the  physical  functioning  of  the  living 
individual  and  the  operation  of  some  of  the  newer  communica- 
tion machines  are  precisely  parallel  in  their  analogous  attempts 
to  control  entropy  through  feedback.  Both  of  them  have  sensory 
receptors  as  one  stage  of  their  cycle  of  operation:  that  is,  in  both 
of  them  there  exists  a  special  apparatus  for  collecting  informa- 
tion from  the  outer  world  at  low  energy  levels,  and  for  making  it 
available  in  the  operation  of  the  individual  or  of  the  machine. 
In  both  cases  these  external  messages  are  not  taken  neat,  but 
through  the  internal  transforming  powers  of  the  apparatus, 
whether  it  be  alive  or  dead.  The  information  is  then  turned  into 
a  new  form  available  for  the  further  stages  of  performance.  In 
both  the  animal  and  the  machine  this  performance  is  made  to  be 
effective  on  the  outer  world.  In  both  of  them,  their  performed 
action  on  the  outer  world,  and  not  merely  their  intended  action,  is 
reported  back  to  the  central  regulatory  apparatus.^ 

Such  declarations  seemed  remarkable  at  first.  Given  a  little 
time  to  reflect,  however,  psychologists  realized  that  these  purposive 
machines  were  quite  familiar,  though  the  language  used  to  discuss 
them  was  somewhat  new.  As  early  as  1896  the  philosopher-psychol- 
ogist John  Dewey  had  described  in  much  detail  the  servomechanism 
involved  in  reaching  toward  a  candle  flame  and  then  jerking  away. 
'The  fact  is,"  he  said,  "that  stimulus  and  response  are  not  distinctions 
of  existence,  but  teleological  distinctions,  that  is,  distinctions  of  func- 
tion, or  part  played,  with  reference  to  reaching  or  maintaining  an 
end."  *  The  new  terms  and  explicit  analysis  supplied  by  the  engineer- 
ing development  were  needed,  however,  before  the  importance  of 
Dewey's  insight  could  be  fully  appreciated.  Once  a  teleological  mech- 
anism could  be  built  out  of  metal  and  glass,  psychologists  recog- 
nized that  it  was  scientifically  respectable  to  admit  they  had  known  it 
all  along.  They  had  known,  for  example,  of  the  homeostatic  mech- 
anisms studied  by  Walter  B.  Cannon  and  his  associates  during  the 

3  Norbert  Wiener,  The  Human  Use  of  Human  Beings  (Boston:  Houghton 
Miiflin,  1954),  pp.  26-27. 

*  John  Dewey,  The  reflex  arc  concept  in  psychology.  Psychological  Review, 
1896,  3,  357—370.  This  remarkable  paper,  one  of  the  cornerstones  of  American 
functional  psychology,  an  anticipation  of  Gestalt  psychology,  and  a  criticism  in 
advance  of  behaviorism,  has  been  reprinted  in  Wayne  Dennis,  ed.,  Readings  in 
the  History  of  Psychology  (New  York:  Appleton-Century-Crofts,  1948). 

The  Simulation  of  Psychological  Processes  ■  43 


1920's.  They  had  known  about  L.  T.  Troland,  who  in  1928  intro- 
duced the  term  "retroflex"  to  name  the  sensory  feedback.^  They  had 
known  about  the  "circular  reflexes"  that  E.  B.  Holt  revived  and  elab- 
orated in  1931.^  And  they  had  known  about  Edward  Tolman,  who 
anticipated  the  new  respectability  of  teleology  by  at  least  two  decades 
and  who,  in  1939,  had  described  a  perfectly  respectable  feedback 
mechanism  that  he  called  the  "schematic  sowbug."  ^  Even  in  1939, 
however,  Tolman  could  claim  no  priority,  for  he  had  borrowed  the 
central  idea  from  the  mechanistic  biologist  Jacques  Loeb.  That  was 
something  else  the  psychologists  had  known  all  along.  Loeb's  theory 
of  tropisms  was,  in  1890,  one  of  the  earliest  descriptions  of  a  ma- 
chine that  would  exhibit  purposive,  taxic  behavior.®  The  idea  of  the 
biological  servomechanism  had  been  there  all  along — but  the  me- 
chanical actualization  of  the  idea  in  inorganic  hardware  provided  the 
kind  of  demonstration  that  could  no  longer  be  ignored.  Today  we 
can,  almost  as  a  matter  of  course,  propose  teleological  arrangements 
such  as  the  TOTE  unit  discussed  in  the  preceding  chapter — the  par- 
ticular realization  of  the  unit  in  tissue  or  in  metal  need  not  deter  us, 
for  we  know  now  that  it  can  be  accomplished  in  a  variety  of  ways. 

What  is  the  source  of  this  remarkable  increase  in  confidence  that 
psychologists  experience  when  their  ideas  can  be  translated  into 
machinery?  Clark  Hull  has  suggested  that  designing  robots  is  a  "pro- 
phylaxis against  anthropomorphic  subjectivism,"  and  he  recom- 
mends the  following  to  his  readers : 

Regard  .   .  .  the  behaving  organism  as  a  completely  self- 
maintaining  robot,  constructed  of  materials  as  unlike  ourselves 

5  L.  T.  Troland,  The  Fundamentals  of  Human  Motivation  (New  York:  Van 
Nostrand,  1928). 

6  Edwin  B.  Holt,  Animal  Drive  and  the  Learning  Process  (New  York:  Holt, 
1931).  For  the  history  of  the  circular  reflexes,  see  Wayne  Dennis,  A  note  on  the 
circular  response  hypothesis.  Psychological  Review,  1954,  61,  334—338.  Dennis 
traces  the  circular  response  back  to  David  Hartley  in  1749. 

^  E.  C.  Tolman,  Prediction  of  vicarious  trial  and  error  by  means  of  the 
schematic  sowbug.  Psychological  Review,  1939,  46,  318-336. 

8  W.  J.  Crozier,  The  study  of  living  organisms,  in  C.  Murchison,  ed..  The 
Foundations  of  Experimental  Psychology  (Worcester:  Clark  University  Press, 
1929),  pp.  45-127.  Another  biologist  who  provided  a  clear  and  significant  pre- 
cybernetic  account  of  teleological  mechanisms  was  Alfred  J.  Lotka.  See  his 
Elements  of  Physical  Biology  (Baltimore:  Williams  &  Wilkins,  1925).  (Reissued 
in  1956  by  Dover  Press  as  Elements  of  Mathematical  Biology.)  Lotka  illustrates 
his  argument  by  the  operation  of  a  mechanical  beetle  that  was  able  to  avoid 
falling  off  table  edges;  and  he  expresses  his  scorn  for  thinkers  who  call  a  system 
teleological  only  so  long  as  they  are  ignorant  of  its  workings. 

44  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


as  may  be.  In  doing  this  it  is  not  necessary  to  attempt  the  solu- 
tion of  the  detailed  engineering  problems  connected  with  the 
design  of  such  a  creature.  It  is  a  wholesome  and  revealing  exer- 
cise, however,  to  consider  the  various  general  problems  in  be- 
havior dynamics  which  must  be  solved  in  the  design  of  a  truly 
self-maintaining  robot.  .  .  .  The  temptation  to  introduce  an 
entelechy,  soul,  spirit,  or  daemon  into  a  robot  is  slight;  it  is  rela- 
tively easy  to  realize  that  the  iJitroduction  of  an  entelechy  would 
not  really  solve  the  problem  of  design  of  a  robot  because  there 
would  still  remain  the  problem  of  designing  the  entelechy  itself, 
which  is  the  core  of  the  original  problem  all  over  again.  The 
robot  approach  thus  aids  us  in  avoiding  the  very  natural  but 
childish  tendency  to  choose  easy  though  false  solutions  to  our 
problems,  by  removing  all  excuses  for  not  facing  them  squarely 
and  without  evasion.^ 

Passages  such  as  this  suggest  that  nothing  less  than  the  construc- 
tion of  a  teleological  machine  would  convince  an  experimental  psy- 
chologist that  there  is  not  something  occult  impUed  by  the  terms 
"goal,"  "purpose,"  "expectation,"  "entelechy." 

Surely  there  is  something  more  to  a  psychologist's  feeling  of 
materialistic  satisfaction  and  confidence  than  just  his  triumph  over 
subjectivism.  Machines  are  not  the  only  way  he  has  of  facing  his 
problems  "squarely  and  without  evasion."  Indeed,  psychologists  are 
most  likely  to  construct  machines  for  just  those  functions  whose  ob- 
jective character  is  least  in  doubt,  where  the  threat  of  subjectivism  is 

9  Hull,  Principles  of  Behavior,  pp.  27-28.  This  passage  expresses  Hull's  dis- 
taste for  nineteenth-century  vitalism  in  general,  and  particularly  for  that  purpose- 
ful, organizing,  vital  principle  that  Hans  Driesch  named  "entelechy."  In  the 
twentieth  century  it  has  become  clear  that  Driesch  was  wrong,  but  not  for  the 
reason  Hull  gives.  Hull  thought  that  the  vitalistic  distinction  between  animals 
and  robots  failed  because  animals,  being  nothing  but  machines,  could  not  oper- 
ate purposefully.  In  fact,  however,  the  distinction  failed  because  both  organisms 
and  machines  can  demonstrate  the  operation  of  a  purposeful  entelechy.  Designing 
an  entelechy  is  no  trick  at  all  for  an  electrical  engineer.  In  spite  of  this  resound- 
ing failure,  however,  vitalism  is  not  dead.  It  has  merely  retreated.  In  order  to 
find  something  distinctive  about  biological  systems,  the  modern  vitalists  have 
retreated  from  purpose  to  memory,  an  alternative  first  suggested  by  Henri 
Bergson.  The  current  contention  is  that  the  stability  of  genetic  and  personal 
memory  is- — according  to  the  laws  of  quantum  mechanics — incompatible  with 
the  microscopic  sizes  of  the  gene  and  the  synapse.  Therefore,  the  stability  of 
memory  requires  some  nonphysical  explanation.  For  a  sophisticated  defense  of 
the  idea  that  maintaining  information  in  an  organism  is  not,  in  general,  accom- 
plished by  mechanistic  means,  see  Walter  M.  Elsasser,  The  Physical  Foundation 
of  Biology  (New  York:  Pergamon,  1958).  According  to  Elsasser's  view,  a  self- 
maintaining  robot  that  behaved  like  an  organism  would  prove  nothing  unless  its 
component  parts  were  reduced  to  the  extremely  small  size  characteristic  of  bio- 
logical systems. 

The  Simulation  of  Psychological  Processes  ■  45 


most  remote.  The  conditioned  reflex,  for  example,  is  seldom  con- 
sidered an  example  of  "anthropomorphic  subjectivism,"  yet  numerous 
machines  have  been  designed  and  built  to  demonstrate  the  phenom- 
enon of  conditioning  or  of  conditioning  aided  by  the  law  of  effect.^" 
They  were  not  designed  to  perform  any  mentalistic  function  but 
merely  to  display  the  rather  mechanical  fact  that  a  new  connection 
was  being  formed. 

It  seems  to  the  present  authors  that  the  attempts  to  simulate 
psychological  processes  with  machines  are  motivated  in  large  meas- 
ure by  the  desire  to  test — or  to  demonstrate — the  designer's  under- 
standing of  the  theory  he  espouses.  History  suggests  that  man  can 
create  almost  anything  he  can  visualize  clearly.  The  creation  of  a 
model  is  proof  of  the  clarity  of  the  vision.  If  you  understand  how  a 
thing  works  well  enough  to  build  your  own,  then  your  understanding 
must  be  nearly  perfect. 

The  germ  of  wisdom  behind  this  intuition  was  made  explicit  by 
the  mathematician  A.  M.  Turing  in  1937.^^  The  import  of  Turing's 
work  for  psychologists  was  that  if  they  could  describe  exactly  and 
unambiguously  anything  that  a  living  organism  did,  then  a  com- 
puting machine  could  be  built  that  would  exhibit  the  same  behavior 
with  sufficient  exactitude  to  confuse  the  observer.  The  existence  of 
the  machine  would  be  the  test  of  the  accuracy  of  the  description. 

One  consequence  of  taking  Turing's  theorem  seriously  is  that  it 
directs  attention  toward  the  electronic  computer  as  the  right  kind 

10  In  1946  E.  G.  Boring,  in  Mind  and  mechanism,  American  Journal  of 
Psychology,  1946,  59,  173-192,  listed  the  following  attempts  to  design  robots  that 
would  learn:  J.  M.  Stephens,  A  mechanical  explanation  of  the  law  of  effect, 
American  Journal  of  Psychology,  1929,  41,  422-431;  A.  Walton,  Conditioning 
illustrated  by  an  automatic  mechanical  device,  American  Journal  of  Psychology, 
1930,  42,  110  f.;  H.  D.  Baernstein  and  C.  L.  Hull,  A  mechanical  model  of  the 
conditioned  reflex.  Journal  of  General  Psychology,  1931,  5,  99-106;  R.  G.  Rreuger 
and  C.  L.  Hull,  An  electrochemical  parallel  to  the  conditioned  reflex.  Journal  of 
General  Psychology,  1931,  5,  262-269;  G.  K.  Bennett  and  L.  B.  Ward,  A  model  of 
the  synthesis  of  conditioned  reflexes,  American  Journal  of  Psychology,  1933,  45, 
339-342;  D.  G.  Ellson,  A  mechanical  synthesis  of  trial-and-error  learning.  Journal 
of  General  Psychol.,  1935,  13,  212-218;  H.  Bradner,  A  new  mechanical  "learner," 
Journal  of  General  Psychology,  1937,  17,  414^19;  T.  Ross,  The  synthesis  of 
intelligence — its  implications.  Psychological  Review,  1938,  45,  185-189.  The 
frequency  with  which  these  toys  were  described  in  the  journals  (and  no  one  can 
guess  how  many  more  vanished  unreported)  bears  eloquent  testimony  to  the 
importance  psychologists  attach  to  having  a  credible  mechanism  to  support  their 
theoretical  speculations. 

11  An  excellent  introduction  to  Turing  machines  will  be  found  in  Martin 
Davis,  Computahility  and  Unsolvability  (New  York:  McGraw-Hill,  1958). 

46  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


of  machine  to  simulate  human  behavior.  But  many  psychologists, 
impressed  by  the  haphazard  unpredictability  of  behavior  generally, 
feel  intuitively  that  models  based  on  random  processes  offer  better 
prospects  than  the  computers  do,  and  so  the  two  kinds  of  machines, 
deterministic  and  stochastic,  seem  to  compete  with  each  other  for  the 
psychologist's  attention.  Kochen  and  Galanter,  however,  argue  that 
computer  models  are  more  appropriate  than  stochastic  models  for 
describing  human  choice  behavior: 

Ignoring  the  question  of  whether  or  not  a  "conscious"  plan 
guides  the  decision-making  procedure  at  each  trial,  it  is  assumed 
that  the  choices  are  made  according  to  a  plan.  Such  a  plan  shall 
be  called  a  strategy.  It  differs  mainly  in  degree  from  a  relatively 
"stochastic  decision-making  procedure,"  as  might  be  observed  in 
the  behavior  of  rats  in  a  T-maze.  The  latter  type  of  behavior 
seems  best  described  by  certain  kinds  of  stochastic  processes, 
whereas  a  computerlike  mechanism  in  which  random  elements 
play  a  secondary  role  seems  a  more  fruitful  model  for  "planned" 
behavior.^^ 

Although  the  work  on  stochastic  models  is  being  actively  pursued  by 
mathematical  psychologists,  it  will  not  be  reviewed  here;  since  we  are 
concerned  here  primarily  with  planned  behavior,  we  shall  con- 
centrate on  deterministic  automata. 

Another  thing  that  Turing's  theorem  did — or  should  have  done 
— was  to  focus  attention  on  the  adequacy  of  the  description  of  behav- 
ior. A  machine  cannot  be  expected  to  simulate  something  that  has 
never  been  described — it  can  be  held  responsible  only  for  those 
aspects  of  behavior  that  an  observer  has  recorded.  No  simulation  is 
complete  and  no  simulation  preserves  all  the  characteristics  of 
behavior.  If  in  building  a  machine  to  simulate  the  behavior  of  a 
moth  flying  toward  a  light  we  use  wheels  so  that  the  machine  rolls 
rather  than  flies,  the  simulation  is  considered  adequate  up  to  trans- 
formations of  locomotion.  In  a  sense,  we  say  that  we  do  not  care  how 
the  beast  gets  there  so  long  as  its  trajectory  is  "equivalent"  to  that  of 

12  Manfred  Kochen  and  Eugene  H.  Galanter,  The  acquisition  and  utilization 
of  information  in  problem  solving  and  thinking.  Information  and  Control,  1958, 
1,  267-288.  Of  course,  an  electronic  computer  can  be  used  to  study  stochastic 
models  as  well  as  deterministic  ones;  see,  for  exanaple,  Saul  Gorn,  On  the  me- 
chanical stimulation  of  habit-forming  and  learning.  Information  and  Control, 
1959,  2,  22&-259. 

The  Simulation  of  Psychological  Processes  ■  47 


the  moth.  But  even  that  is  acceptable  only  when  we  allow  a  shift 
from  three  to  two  dimensions  of  movement. 

A  simulation  is  invariant  with  the  behavior  being  simulated 
only  up  to  some  group  of  allowable  transformations.  The  simulator 
and  his  critics  must,  for  example,  agree  in  advance  on  the  aspects  of 
the  behavior  that  are  to  remain  the  same  from  organism  to  machine. 
This  agreement  is  normally  established  by  requiring  the  machine 
to  simulate,  not  the  behavior  per  se,  but  the  psychologist's  record  of 
the  behavior.  A  theorist  is,  therefore,  at  the  mercy  of  the  person  who 
decides  what  aspects  of  the  behavior  are  worth  recording  and  simu- 
lating. 

The  extent  to  which  an  organism  and  a  machine  can  be  inter- 
changed without  altering  specified  aspects  of  the  situation  is  the 
extent  to  which  the  simulation  is  successful.  A  successful  model  does 
not  have  to  look  like  the  organism  it  simulates — the  fact  that  clever 
modelers  can  make  a  mechanical  mouse  look  like  a  mouse,  or  a  me- 
chanical moth  look  like  a  turtle,  is  mere  window  dressing.  A  woman 
who  broke  a  valuable  vase  took  the  pieces  to  a  potter,  asked  him  to 
make  an  "exact  duplicate" — and  was  rightfully  distressed  when  he 
duplicated  every  chip  and  shard. 

The  situation  is  most  familiar,  perhaps,  in  the  concept  of 
synonymy.  We  say  that  "bachelor"  and  "unmarried  man"  are  synon- 
ymous because  they  are  interchangeable  in  (nearly)  all  contexts  with- 
out alteration  of  the  truth  value  of  the  propositions  in  which  they 
occur.  In  that  case,  it  is  the  truth  value  that  must  remain  invariant. 
In  the  case  of  a  successful  model,  the  thing  that  must  remain  invari- 
ant is  the  aspect  of  the  organism's  behavior  that  the  experimenter 
chose  to  record. 

Since  it  is  necessary  to  simulate  only  the  record  of  the  animal's 
behavior,  not  the  animal  itself,  the  big,  fast  digital  computers  that 
began  to  evolve  after  World  War  II  could  be  used — they  did  not  need 
to  scurry  around  the  room  like  a  rat  in  a  maze  or  resemble  the  three 
pints  of  brain  matter  they  were  supposed  to  imitate.  The  computer 
did  not  even  need  to  observe  the  same  time  scale.  The  computer's 
task  was  merely  to  simulate — to  compute — those  aspects  of  the 
experimental  situation  that  students  of  human  behavior  were  inter- 
ested in.  A  theorist  could  embody  his  ideas  in  a  program  of  instruc- 

48  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


tions,  the  program  could  be  stored  in  the  "memory"  of  the  computer, 
and  when  "stimuli"  were  presented  the  computer  would,  like  an 
organism,  operate  upon  the  input  information  according  to  the 
instructions  it  had  been  given  in  order  to  generate  a  "response."  In 
principle,  it  sounds  very  simple. 

For  several  years,  however,  there  was  a  good  deal  more  talk  than 
work.  Writing  the  kind  of  complicated  programs  that  are  necessary 
in  order  to  simulate  a  human  being  requires  a  tremendous  investment 
of  time  and  ingenuity.  While  the  computers  and  the  programming  art 
were  expanding,  the  theorists  discussed  how  best  to  use  them,  even- 
tually, for  simulation.  The  first  direction  these  discussions  took  was 
toward  neurological,  rather  than  psychological,  simulation.  This  di- 
rection seemed  especially  promising  because  of  a  long  list  of  analogies: 
the  open-or-shut  relay  was  analogous  to  the  all-or-none  neuron,  the 
electrical  pulses  in  the  computer  were  analogous  to  the  neural  im- 
pulses, the  mercury  delay  lines  were  analogous  to  the  reverberating 
circuits  in  the  nervous  system,  the  memory  circuits  of  the  computer 
were  analogous  to  the  association  areas  of  the  brain,  and  so  on  and 
on.  The  neurological  direction  also  seemed  promising  because  Mc- 
Culloch  and  Pitts  had  invented  a  formal  representation  of  neural 
nets  and  used  it  to  establish  that  any  function  that  could  be  described 
logically,  strictly,  and  unambiguously  in  a  finite  number  of  words 
could  be  realized  by  such  nets."  That  is  to  say,  they  showed  that  their 
neural  nets  comprised  a  Turing  machine.  This  formalization  madi 
possible  some  very  sophisticated  analyses  of  neurological  functions 
and  properties  even  before  they  were  simulated  by  computers.  The 
speculations  about  neural  nets  were  widely  publicized  and  seem  to 
have  had  a  stimulating  effect  on  neurology  and  neurophysiology. 
We  have  every  reason  to  expect  great  strides  forward  in  this  field.  It 
is  not,  however,  the  kind  of  theory  we  are  interested  in  here. 

Our  present  interest  is  in  the  use  of  computers  as  automata  to 

13  Warren  S.  McCulloch  and  Walter  Pitts,  A  logical  calculus  of  the  ideas 
immanent  in  nervous  activity.  Bulletin  of  Mathematical  Biophysics,  1943,  5,  115— 
133.  For  some  of  the  earlier  work,  see  Nicholas  Rashevsky,  Mathematical  Bio- 
physics (Chicago:  University  of  Chicago  Press,  1938).  For  some  of  the  more 
recent  work,  see  M.  L.  Minsky,  Neural-Analog  Netzvorks  and  the  Brain-Model 
Problem,  Ph.D.  tliesis,  Princeton  University,  1954;  see  also  the  several  selections  ' 
in  C.  E.  Shannon  and  J.  McCarthy,  eds.,  Automata  Studies  (Princeton:  Princeton 
University  Press,  1956).  And  for  perspective,  see  John  von  Neumann,  The  Com- 
puter and  the  Brain  (New  Haven:  Yale  University  Press,  1958). 

The  Simulation  of  Psychological  Processes  ■  49 


illustrate  the  operation  of  various  psychological  theories.  EfPorts  in 
this  direction  lagged  somewhat  behind  the  neurological  and  seem  to 
have  been  of  at  least  two  different  kinds.  Some  of  the  psychological 
theorizing  aimed  the  computer  at  the  Image,  and  some  of  it  aimed 
the  computer  at  the  Plan.  Not  until  late  in  the  1950's  did  these  two 
lines  grow  together. 

Consider  the  Image-inspired  theories  first.  One  of  the  early  at- 
tempts to  use  computer  simulation  in  order  to  understand  psycholog- 
ical (rather  than  neurological)  processes  was  made  by  the  British 
.  psychologist  Kenneth  Craik,  who  was  convinced  that  thought  depends 
on  images.  But  how  was  a  computer  to  have  an  image?  His  answer 
was  that  an  image  is  a  form  of  symbol  and  that  thought  consists  of 
building  and  modifying  such  symbols  by  processing  the  information 
from  the  sense  organs;  to  the  extent  that  a  computer  symboUzes  and 
processes  information,  it  is  thinking.  He  says : 

My  hypothesis  then  is  that  thought  models,  or  parallels, 
reality — that  its  essential  feature  is  not  "the  mind,"  "the  self," 
"sense-data,"  nor  propositions  but  symbolism,  and  that  this  sym- 
bolism is  largely  of  the  same  kind  as  that  which  is  familiar  to  us 
in  mechanical  devices  which  aid  thought  and  calculation." 

In  the  terms  we  have  introduced  here,  Craik  was  struggling  with  the 
problem  of  how  the  Image  could  be  represented  in  a  computer. 

Craik's  untimely  death  prevented  him  from  following  up  these 
ideas,  and  the  work  that  pursued  the  problem  of  image  formation  and 
recognition  by  computers  was  largely  cast  in  neurological  rather  than 
psychological  terms.^^  However,  Donald  M.  MacKay  picked  up  the 

1*  K.  J.  W.  Craik,  The  Nature  of  Explanation  (Cambridge:  Cambridge  Uni- 
versity Press,  1943),  p.  57. 

15  Some  of  the  relevant  contributions  to  a  neurological  theory  of  perception 
were:  W.  Pitts  and  W.  S.  McCuUoch,  How  we  know  universals:  The  perception 
of  auditory  and  visual  forms,  Bulletin  of  Mathematical  Biophysics,  1947,  9,  127- 
147;  D.  O.  Hebb,  The  Organization  of  Behavior  (New  York:  Wiley,  1949);  W.  A, 
Clark  and  B.  G.  Farley,  Generalization  of  pattern  recognition  in  a  self-organizing 
system.  Proceedings  of  the  Western  Joint  Computer  Conference,  Los  Angeles, 
March  1955,  pp.  86-91;  O.  G.  Selfridge,  Pattern  recognition  and  modem  com- 
puters, ibid.,  pp.  91-93;  G.  P.  Dinneen,  Programming  pattern  recognition,  ibid., 
pp.  94-100;  N.  Rochester,  J.  H.  Holland,  L.  H.  Haibt,  and  W.  L.  Duda,  Test  on  a 
cell  assembly  theory  of  the  action  of  the  brain,  using  a  large  digital  computer, 
IRE  Transactions  on  Information  Theory,  1956,  Vol.  PGIT-2,  No.  3,  80-93;  P.  M. 
Milner,  The  cell  assembly:  Mark  II,  Psychological  Review,  1957,  64,  242-252; 
F.  Rosenblatt,  The  perceptron :  A  probabilistic  model  for  information  storage  and 
organization  in  the  brain.  Psychological  Review,  1958,  65,  386—408.  This  list  is 
fax  from  complete.  The  fact  that  we  are  in  this  book  more  interested  in  the  Plan 

50  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


argument  and  carried  it  a  step  further  when  he  pointed  out  that  an 
Image  could  be  constructed  in  a  machine  if  the  machine  were  able  to 
remember  the  reactions  it  required  to  imitate  its  input. ^"^  The  act  of 
replication  might  be  guided  by  feedback — the  difference  between  the 
incoming  configuration  and  the  internal  replication  would  represent 
an  error  signal  for  the  machine  to  reduce.  These  acts  of  replication 
would  then  provide  a  basic  "vocabulary"  in  terms  of  which  the  ma- 
chine could  describe  its  own  experience  (a  notion  not  completely 
unlike  Hebb's  neurological  "phase  sequences"). 

These  theories,  clever  as  they  were,  did  not  seem  to  come  to 
grips  with  the  problem  of  motivation.  It  remained  for  Galanter  and 
Gerstenhaber,  in  1956,  to  point  out  the  importance  of  motivation  and 
to  propose  a  theory  for  determining  which  Images  would  serve  as 
models  for  thinking.  Different  evaluations  do  indeed  modify  a  per- 
son's Image  of  his  problem  and  so  lead  to  different  forms  of  behav- 
ior.^^ 

Of  all  the  work  on  machine  imagery,  however,  the  most  impres- 
sive is  that  by  Gelernter  and  Rochester.^^  They  have  programmed  a 
computer  to  prove  theorems  in  plane  geometry  and  equipped  the  ma- 
chine to  draw  diagrams  experimentally,  much  as  a  student  does.  The 
diagrams  simplify  tremendously  the  process  of  searching  for  a  proof. 
A  more  persuasive  demonstration  that  Tolman's  analogy  to  "a  map 
control  room"  need  not  involve  a  homunculus  to  read  the  maps  could 
hardly  be  imagined. 

Psychologists  seem  to  have  been  somewhat  slower  to  recognize 
that  the  same  kind  of  problems  of  pattern  and  organization  exist  at 
the  behavioral  level  as  at  the  level  of  the  Image.  Perhaps  it  was  the  in- 


than  in  the  Image  deprives  us  of  an  excuse  to  summarize  these  valuable  and 
interesting  contributions  to  perceptual  theory,  but  we  mention  them  as  part  of 
the  accumulating  evidence  that  computer  simulation  will  play  an  increasingly 
important  role  in  the  future  development  of  both  neurological  and  psychological 
theory. 

1^  D.  M.  MacKay,  Mindlike  behavior  in  artefacts,  British  Journal  for  the 
Philosophy  of  Science,  1951,  2,  105-121. 

i'^  Eugene  Galanter  and  Murray  Gerstenhaber,  On  thought:  The  extrinsic 
theory,  Psychological  Review,  1956,  63,  218-227.  Eugene  Galanter  and  W.  A.  S. 
Smith,  Some  experiments  on  a  simple  thought-problem,  American  Journal  of 
Psychology,  1958,  71,  359-366. 

IS  H.  L.  Gelernter  and  N.  Rochester,  Intelligent  behavior  in  problem-solving 
machines,  IBM  Journal  of  Research  and  Development,  1958,  2,  336-345.  H.  L. 
Gelernter,  Realization  of  a  geometry  proving  machine.  Proceedings  of  the  Inter- 
national Conference  on  Information  Processing,  Paris,  1959  (in  press). 

The  Simulation  of  Psychological  Processes  "51 


terminable  discussion  of  "trial-and-error"  processes  that  fostered  a 
general  belief  that  relatively  simple  stochastic  models  would  suffice 
as  theories.  In  1949  Miller  and  Frick  tried  to  complicate  this  simple 
picture  by  using  Markov  processes  to  explain  the  sequential  organiza- 
tion of  behavior.^^  Their  work  represented  a  relatively  obvious  gen- 
eralization of  Claude  Shannon's  suggestion  that  Markov  processes 
could  be  used  to  explain  the  sequential  organization  of  messages.^" 
Surely,  sequential  organization  of  behavior  could  nowhere  be  more 
important  than  for  communication,  so  it  seemed  that  if  Markovian 
machines  would  generate  grammatical  English,  they  would  be  ade- 
quate for  simulating  all  other  forms  of  behavior  as  well.  The  actual 
creation  of  such  a  machine,  however,  was  prohibited  by  the  fantas- 
tically large  number  of  internal  states  that  would  be  required  in  the 
machine  for  even  the  crudest  approximations  to  actual  behavior. 
The  crux  of  the  problem  was  not  clear,  however,  until  Noam  Chomsky 
proved  that  any  machine  that  tries  to  generate  all  the  grammatical 
strings  of  words  by  proceeding,  as  a  Markovian  machine  would,  from 
left  to  right,  one  word  at  a  time  in  strict  order,  will  need  to  have  an 
infinite  number  of  internal  states. ^^  Since  the  point  of  a  theory  is 
simplification,  machines  with  infinitely  many  parameters  cannot 
be  considered  seriously.  The  only  alternative  seems  to  be  one  that 
respects  the  hierarchical  structure  of  the  sequence — the  kind  of 
"parsing"  machine  that  we  have  already  mentioned  in  Chapter  1. 
One  reason  that  linguists  have  been  motivated  to  express  their 
description  of  language  in  terms  congenial  to  communication  theory 
and  to  modern  computers  has  been  their  interest  in  the  possibility  of 
mechanical  translation.  The  development  of  communication  theory 
since   1948  has  revolutionized  our  thinking  in  a  dozen  different 

19  George  A.  Miller  and  Frederick  C.  Frick,  Statistical  behavioristics  and 
sequences  of  responses.  Psychological  Review,  1949,  56,  311-324.  See  also  F.  C. 
Frick  and  G.  A.  Miller,  A  statistical  description  of  operant  conditioning,  American 
Journal  of  Psychology,  1951,  64,  20-36,  and  G.  A.  Miller,  Finite  Markov  processes 
in  psychology,  Psychometrika,  1952,  17,  149-167. 

20  Claude  E.  Shannon,  A  mathematical  theory  of  communication.  Bell  Sys- 
tem Technical  Journal,  1948,  27,  379—423.  Actually,  Markov  himself  had  used 
his  ideas  to  describe  wrritten  texts. 

21  Noam  Chomsky,  Three  models  for  the  description  of  language,  IRE  Trans- 
actions on  Information  Theory,  1956,  Vol.  IT-2,  113-124.  However,  the  difficulties 
Involved  in  applying  stochastic  theory  to  sequences  of  responses  that  are  pat- 
terned in  a  hierarchy  of  units  had  been  noted  earlier  by  John  B.  Carroll,  The 
Study  of  Language  (Cambridge:  Harvard  University  Press,  1953,  p.  107). 

52  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


fields,  ranging  all  the  way  from  electrical  engineering  to  the  social 
sciences.-"  Most  of  the  implications  of  that  work  lie  outside  the 
scope  of  the  present  book,  but  the  attempt  to  use  computers  to  trans- 
late messages  from  one  language  into  another  is  particularly  relevant 
to  this  discussion.'^  The  first  step  in  this  direction,  of  course,  is  to  use 
a  computer  as  an  automatic  dictionary,  to  exploit  its  high  speeds  to 
accomplish  the  humdrum  task  of  searching  through  the  vocabulary 
to  find  the  possible  equivalents  in  the  target  language.  But  word-for- 
word  substitutions,  even  between  closely  related  languages,  do  not 
produce  grammatical  or  even  intelligible  translations.  The  machine 
must  know  something  about  the  grammar  as  well  as  the  vocabulary 
of  the  languages  it  is  translating.  Or,  more  precisely,  it  must  have  a 
set  of  instructions  for  deciding  among  alternative  translations,  for 
recognizing  idioms,  for  rearranging  the  order  of  the  words,  for  de- 
taching or  supplying  affixes  to  roots,  etc.  In  principle,  there  is  no 
reason  we  cannot  store  a  two-language  dictionary  and  several  hun- 
dred coded  rules  of  grammar  in  a  computer  and  get  a  usable  output. 
But  in  practice,  the  actual  coding  of  the  dictionary  and  the  efficient 
phrasing  of  the  rules  pose  many  tedious  and  perplexing  puzzles. 
They  will  probably  be  overcome,  but  at  the  present  writing,  mechani- 
cal translation  is  still  not  proceeding  as  a  routine  business  anywhere 
in  the  United  States. 

The  current  state  of  the  world  makes  translation  an  important 
problem  for  the  survival  of  our  society,  and  we  must  hope  the  lin- 
guists and  their  programmers  will  soon  succeed.  Even  without  suc- 
cess, however,  there  are  certain  lessons  that  we  can  draw  from  their 
experience  that  have  enlightening  implications  for  psychologists  and 
linguists. 

In  the  Gist  place,  the  very  large  amount  of  information  that  has 
to  be  encoded  for  the  computer  has  comprised,  until  very  recently, 
one  of  the  major  bottlenecks  in  the  implementation  of  the  scheme. 
There  just  is  not  enough  room  in  a  computer  for  it  to  contain  a  full 

22  Cf.  George  A.  Miller,  Language  and  Communication  (New  York:  McGraw- 
Hill,  1951). 

23  An  introduction  to  the  problem  can  be  found  in  W.  N.  Locke  and  A.  D. 
Boothe,  eds.,  Machine  Translation  of  Languages  (New  York:  Wiley,  1955).  There 
is  a  journal  devoted  exclusively  to  the  subject:  Mechanical  Translation,  Massa- 
chusetts Institute  of  Technology,  Cambridge,  Mass.  But  see  also  R.  A.  Brower,  ed., 
On  Translation  (Cambridge:  Harvard  University  Press,  1959). 

The  Simulation  of  Psychological  Processes  ■  53 


vocabulary  and  still  be  able  to  retrieve  items  from  the  memory  as 
rapidly  as  they  w^ould  be  needed  for,  say,  ordinary  speech  rates.  In 
the  terms  of  our  present  discussion,  the  Image  of  the  average,  well- 
educated  European  or  American  adult  must  contain  an  amazing 
amount  of  knowledge  all  organized  for  fast  access  to  attention.  In 
some  respects,  apparently,  our  brains  are  still  a  great  deal  more 
complicated  than  the  biggest  computer  ever  built. 

In  the  second  place,  it  becomes  obvious  that  there  are  two  very 
different  attitudes  one  can  take  toward  the  job.  In  one  attitude,  the 
programmer  says,  "I  want  to  make  it  work  any  way  I  can,  but  the 
simpler  it  is,  the  better."  In  the  other  attitude,  he  says,  "I  want  to 
make  the  computer  do  it  the  same  way  people  do  it,  even  though  it 
may  not  look  like  the  most  efficient  method."  As  citizens  we  should 
applaud  the  former  attitude,  but  as  psychologists,  linguists,  neurolo- 
gists— as  students  of  the  human  being — we  are  bound  to  be  more 
interested  in  the  latter.  It  has  been  suggested  that  the  attempt  to 
discover  an  efficient  way  for  the  computer  to  do  the  task  should  be 
called  a  problem  in  "artificial  intelligence,"  whereas  the  attempt  to 
imitate  the  human  being  should  be  called  a  problem  in  "simulation." 
To  date,  little  effort  has  been  made  to  approach  the  translation  prob- 
lem with  the  intent  of  simulating  a  human  translator. 

And,  finally,  there  is  nothing  but  a  distressingly  vague  criterion 
for  determining  when  the  computer  has  succeeded  and  when  it  has 
failed.^*  A  translation  is  multi-dimensional,  and  who  can  say  how 
much  better  one  dimension  must  be  in  order  to  counterbalance  an 
inferiority  in  some  other  dimension?  Probably  the  evaluation  should 
be  based  upon  the  comparison  of  the  machine's  output  with  a  pro- 
fessional translator's  output,  but  exactly  how  the  comparison  is  to  be 
made  is  quite  difficult  to  say.  In  the  most  successful  branches  of 
science  we  have  learned  how  to  measure  the  discrepancies  between 
our  observations  and  our  theories,  but  with  the  kind  of  simulations 
now  possible,  criteria  for  the  goodness  of  fit  have  yet  to  be  devised. 

Mechanical  translation  illustrates  a  general  class  of  non-numeri- 
cal problems  toward  which  the  computer  has  been  directed.  The 
inspiration  for  the  work  did  not  arise  from  an  attempt  to  understand 

24  George  A.  Miller  and  J.  G.  Beebe-Center,  Some  psychological  methods  for 
evaluating  the  quality  of  translations,  Mechanical  Translation,  1956,  3,  73-80. 

54  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


or  develop  any  new  theories  in  neurology  or  psychology,  but  from 
the  translation  problem  itself  and  from  a  desire  to  see  just  how  good 
our  computers  really  are.  It  has  been  principally  the  computer  engi- 
neers, plus  a  few  mathematicians,  who  have  tried  to  make  com- 
puters play  chess,-^  or  prove  theorems  in  logic,^*^  or  wrestle  with  some 
branch  of  mathematics."^  Inasmuch  as  most  of  the  efforts  have  been 
on  problems  of  "artificial  intelligence"  rather  than  in  the  simulation  of 
human  beings,  they  contribute  little  but  context  to  the  psychological 
problem.  However,  the  tasks  that  the  engineers  and  mathematicians 
have  selected  to  explore  on  the  computer  are,  in  some  sense  not  easily 
defined,  about  the  right  "size"  for  present-day  machines  to  tackle. 
The  Image  that  a  computer  must  have  in  order  to  play  chess,  or  to  do 
problems  in  the  prepositional  calculus,  is  quite  restricted  and  reason- 
ably determinate,  and  therefore  does  not  overload  the  computer.  Yet 
at  the  same  time  these  tasks  are  large  and  complicated  enough  to  be 
interesting  and  to  enable  a  machine  to  surprise  us  by  its  successes.-^ 
They  are  good  problems.  But  what  is  needed,  from  the  psychologist's 
point  of  view,  is  an  attempt  to  simulate  the  human  chess-player  or 
logician,  not  just  to  replace  him  or  defeat  him. 

The  first  intensive  effort  to  meet  this  need  was  the  work  of 
Newell,   Shaw,   and   Simon,   who  have   advanced   the  business   of 

25  Some  of  the  publications  on  this  task,  whose  attractiveness  is  not  solely  a 
matter  of  showmanship,  are  C.  E.  Shannon,  Programming  a  computer  for  playing 
chess,  Philosophical  Magazine,  1950,  41,  256-275;  A.  NeweU,  The  chess  machine, 
an  example  of  dealing  with  a  complex  task  by  adaptation.  Proceedings  of  the 
Western  Joint  Computer  Conference,  Los  Angeles,  March  1955,  pp.  101-108; 
J.  Kister,  P.  Stein,  S.  Ulam,  W.  W^alden,  and  M.  W^ells,  Experiments  in  chess, 
Journal  of  the  Association  for  Computing  Machinery,  1957,  4,  174-177;  A.  Bern- 
stein and  M.  deV.  Roberts,  Computer  versus  chess  player.  Scientific  American, 
June  1958,  198,  96-105.  A.  Newell,  J.  C.  Shaw,  and  H.  A.  Simon,  Chess-playing 
programs  and  the  problem  of  complexity,  IBM  Journal  of  Research  and  Develop- 
ment, 1958,  2,  320-335.  See  also  A.  L.  Samuel,  Some  studies  in  machine  learning 
using  the  game  of  checkers,  IBM  Journal  of  Research  and  Development,  1959, 
3,  210-229. 

26  Seven  centuries  of  work  on  mechanical  methods  to  solve  problems  in 
logic  are  reviewed  by  Martin  Gardner,  Logic  Machines  and  Diagrams  (New  York: 
McGraw-Hill,  1958). 

2"  Cf.  Gelernter  and  Rochester,  op.  cit.,  and  Allen  NeweU,  J.  C.  Shaw,  and 
Herbert  A.  Simon,  Report  on  a  general  problem  solving  program.  Proceedings  of 
the  International  Conference  on  Information  Processing  (Paris,  1959,  in  press). 

28  For  a  broad,  imaginative,  though  highly  condensed  survey  of  the  artificial 
intelligence  problem,  see  M.  L.  Minsky,  Heuristic  Aspects  of  the  Artificial  Intel- 
ligence Problem,  Group  Report  34-55,  Lincoln  Laboratory,  Massachusetts  Insti- 
tute of  Technology,  17  December  1956.  Minsky's  psychology  is  generally  quite 
sophisticated. 

The  Simulation  of  Psychological  Processes  ■  55 


psychological  simulation  further  and  with  greater  success  than  any- 
one else.-^  Later,  particularly  in  Chapter  13,  we  discuss  their  ideas  in 
more  detail.  For  the  present,  however,  we  shall  comment  simply 
that  they  have  created  an  information-processing  language  that  en- 
ables them  to  use  the  computer  in  a  non-numerical  manner.  Their 
language  systematically  exploits  a  hierarchical  (list  structure)  system 
of  organization  that  is  uniquely  suitable  for  writing  heuristic  pro- 
grams for  problem  solving,  programs  that  enable  a  computer  to 
simulate  the  information  processing  done  by  human  subjects  who 
are  given  the  same  task  to  solve. ^°  Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon  have 
used  their  techniques  to  simulate  human  problem  solving  in  logic, 
chess,  and  trigonometry  and  have  evolved  a  set  of  principles,  ap- 
plicable to  a  wide  variety  of  situations,  that  they  feel  are  character- 
istic of  the  ways  human  beings  solve  problems  in  general.  Their  ac- 
complishments have  influenced  the  present  authors  in  many  ways — 
not  merely  in  terms  of  their  specific  solutions  to  innumerable  tech- 
nical problems  but  generally  by  their  demonstration  that  what  so 
many  had  so  long  described  was  finally  coming  to  pass. 

It  is  impressive  to  see,  and  to  experience,  the  increase  in  confi- 
dence that  comes  from  the  concrete  actualization  of  an  abstract  idea 
— the  kind  of  confidence  a  reflex  theorist  must  have  felt  in  the  1930's 
when  he  saw  a  machine  that  could  be  conditioned  like  a  dog.  Today, 
however,  that  confidence  is  no  longer  reserved  exclusively  for  reflex 
theorists.  Perhaps  some  of  the  more  fanciful  conjectures  of  the  "men- 
talists"  should  now  be  seriously  reconsidered.  Psychologists  have 
been  issued  a  new  license  to  conjecture.  What  will  they  do  with  it? 
Will  the  new  ideas  be  incorporated  into  existing  theory?  Or  will  it  be 
easier  to  begin  afresh? 

A  major  impetus  behind  the  v^rriting  of  this  book  has  been  the 
conviction  that  these  new  ideas  are  compatible  with,  and  provide 
extensions  of,  famihar  and  established  psychological  principles.  In 

29  Cf.  footnotes  10,  12,  13  in  Chapter  1. 

30  Since  the  development  by  Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon  of  their  information- 
processing  language  (IPL),  two  other  new  programming  languages  have  been 
created  around  the  idea  of  list  structures:  At  the  Massachusetts  Institute  of 
Technology,  John  McCarthy  has  developed  LISP,  and  at  International  Business 
Machines,  H.  L.  Gelernter  has  developed  FLPL.  At  the  time  this  is  written,  how- 
ever, neither  of  these  newer  programming  languages  has  been  described  in  publi- 
cations. 

56  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


the  pages  that  follow  the  attempt  will  be  made  to  show  what  these 
principles  are  and  how  they  can  be  revised  and  elaborated  in  the 
hght  of  recent  developments  in  our  understanding  of  man  viewed  as  a 
system  for  processing  information. 


The  Simulation  of  Psychological  Processes  ■  57 


CHAPTER  4 


VALUES,   INTENTIONS, 

AND   THE 
EXECUTION   OF   PLANS 


All  acts  have  in  common  the  character  of  being  intended  or 
willed.  But  one  act  is  distinguishable  from  another  by  the  con- 
tent of  it,  the  expected  result  of  it,  which  is  here  spoken  of  as  its 
intent.  There  is  no  obvious  way  in  which  we  can  say  what  act  it 
is  which  is  thought  of  or  is  done  except  by  specifying  this  intent 
ofit.i 

In  this  passage  from  his  Cams  Lectures,  C.  I.  Lewis  reminds  us 
that  the  acts  people  perform  cannot  be  characterized  simply  by 
specifying  the  time-order  of  their  parts — in  the  way  we  might  de- 
scribe the  motions  of  a  billiard  ball  or  a  falling  stone.  The  term  "in- 
tent" is  Lewis's  way  of  trying  to  catch  this  elusive  and  unique  feature 
of  the  behavior  of  living  systems.  In  speaking  in  these  terms  he  is 
like  any  ordinary  person  who  tries  to  say  what  makes  his  actions 
meaningful — but  he  is  quite  unlike  most  experimental  psychologists. 

1  Clarence  Irving  Lewis,  An  Analysis  of  Knowledge  and  Valuation  (La  Salle, 
m.:  Open  Court,  1946),  p.  367. 

Values,  Intentions,  and  the  Execution  of  Plans  ■  59 


Intention  went  out  of  style  as  a  psychological  concept  when 
reflex  theory  and  its  derivatives  became  the  foundation  for  our 
scientific  theories  of  behavior.  Only  rarely  in  the  past  twenty  years 
has  the  concept  been  used  outside  the  clinic  as  a  technical  term  in  a 
psychological  explanation.  And  most  of  the  explicit  uses  that  have 
occurred  can  probably  be  traced  to  the  influence  of  Kurt  Lewin.^ 

Lewin  used  the  concept  of  intention  in  order  to  combat  an  overly 
simple  theory  that  actions  are  always  strengthened  whenever  they 
are  successful.  He  uses  the  example  of  someone  who  intends  to  mail  a 
letter.  The  first  mailbox  he  passes  reminds  him  of  the  action.  He 
drops  the  letter  in.  Thereafter,  the  mailboxes  he  passes  leave  him 
altogether  cold.  He  does  not  even  notice  them.  Now,  according  to 
Lewin,  the  intention  to  mail  the  letter  created  a  positive  valence  on 
the  mailbox,  which  attracted  the  person's  attention  to  it.  When  the 
occasion  arose  and  the  intentional  act  was  consummated,  the  valence 
vanished  and  further  mailboxes  were  ignored.  According  to  classical 
theory,  dropping  the  letter  into  the  mailbox  should  have  the  effect  of 
strengthening  the  association  between  mailboxes  and  the  response 
of  reaching  into  the  pocket  for  a  letter  to  be  mailed.  The  poor  fellow 
should  have  made  abortive  responses  toward  three  or  four  mailboxes 
before  the  strength  of  the  association  had  diminished.  Instead  of 
accumulating  habit  strength,  however,  the  fact  is  he  had  no  further 
interest  in  mailboxes.  Therefore,  reasoned  Lewin,  the  simpler  theory 
is  inadequate  and  a  more  complex  representation  of  a  life  space,  com- 
plete with  valences  created  by  intentions,  is  required. 

The  present  authors  are  in  fundamental  agreement  with  Lewin. 
Intention  does  pose  an  interesting  and  important  problem  for 
psychology.  And  we  agree  that  the  associationistic  doctrine  described 
above  can  never  provide  an  adequate  explanation.  But  Lewin  goes  on 
to  draw  an  interesting  analogy  that  we  want  to  reject.  An  intention, 
he  says,  creates  a  quasi-need.  Just  as  hunger  gives  food  a  positive 
valence,  so  does  the  intention  to  mail  the  letter  give  the  maflbox  a 
positive  valence.  Just  as  eating  reduces  the  positive  valence  of  food, 
so  does  mailing  the  letter  reduce  the  quasi-need  and  remove  the 

-  Kurt  Lewin,  Intention,  will  and  need,  in  David  Rapaport,  Organization  and 
Pathology  of  Thought  (New  York:  Columbia  University  Press,  1951),  Chapter 
5.  A  summary  can  be  found  in  W.  D.  Ellis,  A  Source  Book  of  Gestalt  Psychology 
(New  York:  Humanities  Press,  1938). 

6o  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


positive  valence  from  mailboxes.  For  Lewin,  there  is  a  complete  par- 
allel between  the  dynamics  of  intentions  and  the  dynamics  of  any 
other  kind  of  motivated  behavior.  It  is  this  dynamic  property  of  an 
intention  that  we  feel  is  confusing,  and  we  wish  to  reformulate  it. 

There  are  simpler  alternatives.  What  does  it  mean  when  an 
ordinary  man  has  an  ordinary  intention?  It  means  that  he  has  begun 
the  execution  of  a  Plan  and  that  this  intended  action  is  a  part  of  it. 
"I  intend  to  see  Jones  when  I  get  there"  means  that  I  am  already  com- 
mitted to  the  execution  of  a  Plan  for  traveling  and  that  a  part  of  this 
Plan  involves  seeing  Jones.  "Do  you  intend  to  see  Smith,  too?"  asks 
about  other  parts  of  the  Plan.  "Yes"  would  be  a  clear  reply.  "No"  is  a 
little  ambiguous  but  probably  means  that  it  is  part  of  my  Plan  to 
avoid  Smith.  "I  don't  know"  means  that  that  part  of  the  Plan  has  not 
yet  been  developed  in  detail  and  that  when  it  is  developed  it  either 
may  or  may  not  include  Smith.  People  are  reasonably  precise  in  their 
use  of  "intent"  in  ordinary  conversation.  And  they  do  not  use  it  to 
mean  that  something  is  temporarily  valuable  or  that  they  have  any 
particular  needs,  either  real  or  quasi.  The  term  is  used  to  refer  to 
the  uncompleted  parts  of  a  Plan  whose  execution  has  already  begun.^ 

Criminal  lawyers  are  constantly  troubled  over  the  distinction 
between  intention  and  motivation.  For  example,  Jones  hires  Smith  to 
kill  someone.  Smith  commits  the  murder,  but  he  is  caught  and 
confesses  that  he  was  hired  to  do  it.  Question:  Is  Smith  guilty?  If  we 
consider  only  the  motives  involved,  the  employer  is  guilty  because  he 
was  motivated  to  kill,  but  the  gunman  is  not  guilty  because  his 
motive  was  merely  to  earn  money  (  which  is  certainly  a  commendable 
motive  in  a  capitalistic  society).  But  if  we  consider  their  intentions, 
then  both  parties  are  equally  guilty,  for  both  of  them  knowingly 
undertook  to  execute  a  Plan  culminating  in  murder.  The  legal  con- 
fusions arise  when  the  lawyer  begins  to  argue  that  Smith  could  not 
have  intended  to  murder  because  he  had  no  motive.  Only  a  motive, 
he  says  will  create  an  intention.  Lewin  and  his  associates  would 
further  confuse  the  issue  by  arguing  that  an  intention  will  create  a 

2  In  common  speech,  an  additional  requirement  seems  to  be  that  the  Plan  be 
conscious.  The  present  authors  are  willing  to  tolerate  "unconscious  intentions." 
This  seems  to  be  the  position  of  E.  C.  Tolman,  Psychology  vs.  immediate  experi- 
ence, Philosophy  of  Science,  1935,  2,  356-380.  It  is,  of  course,  a  basic  Freudian 
concept.  See  also  G.  E.  M.  Anscombe,  Intention  (Oxford:  Blackwell,  1958). 

Values,  Intentions,  and  the  Execution  of  Plans  ■  6i 


motive.  The  present  authors  take  the  position  that  a  motive  is  com- 
prised of  two  independent  parts:  value  and  intention.  A  value  refers 
to  an  Image,  whereas  an  intention  refers  to  a  Plan. 

Presumably,  a  normal,  adult  human  being  has  constant  access 
to  a  tremendous  variety  of  Plans  that  he  might  execute  if  he  chose  to 
do  so.  He  has  acquired  a  skill  for  swinging  golf  clubs,  in  the  kitchen 
there  is  a  book  with  a  recipe  for  making  a  cake,  he  knows  how  to  get 
to  Chicago,  etc.  As  long  as  he  is  not  using  them,  these  various  avail- 
able Plans  form  no  part  of  his  intentions.  But  as  soon  as  the  order  to 
execute  a  particular  Plan  has  been  given,  he  begins  to  speak  of  its 
incompleted  parts  (insofar  as  he  knows  them)  as  things  he  intends 
to  do. 

Therein  resides  a  crucial  difference  between  a  chain  of  actions 
and  a  Plan  of  action.  When  a  chain  is  initiated  with  no  internal  rep- 
resentation of  the  complete  course  of  action,  the  later  parts  of  the 
chain  are  not  intended.  When  a  Plan  is  initiated,  the  intent  to  execute 
the  later  parts  of  it  is  clear. 

But  where  then  are  values?  An  evaluation  is  a  form  of  empirical 
knowledge  and  so  helps  to  form  the  person's  Image.  But  have  values 
no  special  influence  on  our  Plans?  If  not,  why  should  any  Plan  ever  be 
executed?  To  answer  the  second  question  first.  Plans  are  executed 
because  people  are  alive.  This  is  not  a  facetious  statement,  for  so 
long  as  people  are  behaving,  soTne  Plan  or  other  must  be  executed. 
The  question  thus  moves  from  why  Plans  are  executed  to  a  concern 
for  which  Plans  are  executed.  And  to  cope  with  this  problem  of 
choice  we  do  indeed  need  some  valuational  concepts. 

Just  as  the  operational  phase  of  a  Plan  may  lead  to  action,  so  the 
test  phase  of  a  Plan  may  draw  extensively  upon  an  Image.  Thus,  the 
evaluations  a  person  has  learned  are  available  for  use  in  the  test 
phases  of  the  Plan;  we  assume  that  every  test  phase  in  every  TOTE 
unit  can  have  some  evaluation  function  associated  with  it.  Ordinarily, 
the  operational  phase  of  a  TOTE  should  increase  the  value  of  the 
situation  as  indicated  by  the  test  phase.  But  that  is  by  no  means  a 
necessary  condition  for  executing  the  TOTE.  When  a  Plan  is  complex 
— made  up  of  a  hierarchy  of  subparts — it  may  be  that  some  of  the 
parts  have  negative  values  associated  with  them.  That  is  to  say,  in 
order  to  achieve  a  positive  result  it  may  be  necessary  to  do  something 

62  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


that,  by  itself,  has  a  negative  evaluation.  When  this  happens,  a  person 
who  is  executing  the  Plan  can  rightly  be  described  as  first  intending, 
then  carrying  out,  actions  that  he  considers  to  be  undesirable. 

An  intended  operation  that  will  someday  provide  the  anticipated 
positive  value  for  an  extensive  Plan  of  action  may  be  delayed  almost 
indefinitely  while  a  person  continues  to  execute  preparatory  subplans 
leading  to  outcomes  with  negative  evaluations.  Such  actions  ob- 
viously occur  repeatedly  in  the  lives  of  adult  human  beings — civilized 
society  would  scarcely  be  possible  without  them — yet  they  are  un- 
usually difficult  to  understand  in  terms  of  simple  hedonism  or  simple 
reinforcement  theory  or  any  other  psychological  theory  that  makes 
no  allowance  for  cognitive  structure,  for  an  Image  and  a  Plan. 

It  seems  reasonable  to  think  of  the  test  phases  of  the  more 
strategic  portions  of  a  Plan  as  associated  with  overriding  evaluations. 
Thus,  a  hierarchy  of  TOTE  units  may  also  represent  a  hierarchy  of 
values.  At  the  root  of  the  hierarchy  we  can  imagine  that  there  is  a 
kind  of  prototest  that,  when  satisfied,  carries  a  larger  positive  evalua- 
tion than  could  be  counteracted  by  any  accumulation  of  negative 
values,  or  costs,  from  the  TOTE  units  in  more  tactical  positions.  Of 
course,  when  we  choose  a  Plan  and  begin  to  execute  it  we  may  be 
unaware  of  some  of  the  detailed  tactics  that  will  be  needed  to  carry 
it  through;  necessarily,  therefore,  we  would  be  unaware  of  all  the 
values  associated  with  those  unforeseen  tactics  until  the  Plan  was 
well  along  in  its  execution.  If  the  negative  values  accumulate  until 
they  outweigh  any  conceivable  positive  value  associated  with  the 
prototest,  we  may  discontinue  the  execution  of  the  Plan.  When,  for 
example,  we  walk  out  of  the  dentist's  office  before  we  have  been  in 
the  dental  chair,  some  change  in  values  must  be  inferred.  (Note,  how- 
ever, that  the  intention  may  be  invariant  under  these  value  trans- 
formations. The  intention  to  see  a  dentist  vanishes  only  when  a  new 
Plan  is  executed — it  does  not  gradually  lose  strength  as  the  desire  to 
see  the  dentist  declines. ) 

When  we  say,  "I  need  a  mailbox  in  order  to  mail  this  letter,"  the 
word  "need"  should  not  be  taken  as  expressing  a  dynamic  or  evalua- 
tive property  associated,  either  temporarily  or  permanently,  with 
mailboxes.  Mailing  the  letter  may  be  part  of  an  utterly  hateful  busi- 
ness— any  values,  positive,  negative,  or  neutral,  can  be  attributed 

Values,  Intentions,  and  the  Execution  of  Plans  ■  63 


to  the  letter  or  to  the  mailbox — yet  the  simple  mechanical  fact  would 
remain  true,  namely,  that  Solomon  himself  cannot  put  a  letter  in  a 
mailbox  if  he  does  not  have  a  mailbox.  It  is  important  to  distinguish 
such  mechanical  "needs"  from  dynamic  or  evaluative  needs.  Levvdn 
was  clearly  aware  of  this  problem,  yet  he  did  not  resolve  it.  He  says 
quite  exphcitly  that  the  value  of  an  object  is  not  identical  with  its 
valence.  The  example  he  cites  concerns  a  sum  of  gold  that  might 
represent  a  great  value  for  one  person  without  tempting  him  to  steal 
it,  but  for  another  person  it  might  have  a  strong  valence  prompting 
him  to  steal.  Having  thus  clearly  seen  the  difference  between  values 
and  valences,  however,  he  drops  the  matter  with  the  comment  that 
sometimes  they  are  related  and  sometimes  they  are  independent.  If 
the  concept  of  valence  is  replaced,  as  we  propose,  by  the  concept  of 
specific  criteria  that  must  be  met  before  the  execution  of  a  Plan  can 
continue,  then  there  is  no  reason  to  expect  that  objects  satisfying 
the  criteria  will  always  be  valuable  or  that  they  will  always  satisfy 
needs.  They  may,  or  again,  they  may  not. 

The  reader  will,  we  hope,  forgive  us  our  banalities,  for  some- 
times the  obvious  is  hard  to  see.  The  fundamental,  underlying 
banality,  of  course,  is  the  fact  that  once  a  biological  machine  starts 
to  run,  it  keeps  running  twenty-four  hours  a  day  until  it  dies.  The 
dynamic  "motor"  that  pushes  our  behavior  along  its  planned  grooves 
is  not  located  in  our  intentions,  or  our  Plans,  or  our  decisions  to 
execute  Plans — it  is  located  in  the  nature  of  life  itself.  As  William 
James  says  so  clearly,  the  stream  of  thought  can  never  stop  flowing. 
We  are  often  given  our  choice  among  several  different  Plans,  but  the 
rejection  of  one  necessarily  imphes  the  execution  of  some  other.  In 
sleep  we  are  about  as  planless  as  we  can  get. 

In  this  renunciation  of  the  dynamic  properties  of  Plans,*  how- 

*  In  discussing  this  point  with  some  of  our  colleagues  we  have  encountered 
the  reaction  that  we  have  not  really  renounced  dynamic  properties  in  the  Plan, 
but  rather  that  we  have  actually  explained  them.  If  so,  it  is  certainly  an  odd 
definition  of  "dynamic."  The  "explanation"  is  simply  that,  so  long  as  it  stays 
alive,  the  psychobiological  machine  must  continue  to  execute  the  successive  steps 
in  some  Plan.  It  is  our  impression  that  this  is  not  what  most  psychologists  have 
meant  when  they  used  the  term  "dynamic."  As  we  understand  it,  "dynamic"  is 
usually  taken  to  mean  that  the  organism  is  striving  toward  some  state  or  object 
that,  when  achieved,  will  reduce  unpleasant  tensions,  etc.  These  "states,"  "goals," 
"tensions,"  if  they  exist  at  all,  must  be  represented  in  the  Image,  not  in  the  Plan, 
Hence  we  persist  in  speaking  of  our  position  as  a  "renunciation  of  the  djTiamic 
properties  of  Plans." 

64  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


ever,  we  should  not  lose  sight  of  the  fact  that  something  important 
does  happen  to  a  Plan  when  the  decision  is  made  to  execute  it.  It  is 
taken  out  of  dead  storage  and  placed  in  control  of  a  segment  of  our 
information-processing  capacity.  It  is  brought  into  the  focus  of  atten- 
tion, and  as  we  begin  to  execute  it  we  take  on  a  number  of  menial  but 
necessary  tasks  having  to  do  with  gathering  data  and  remembering 
how  far  in  the  Plan  we  have  progressed  at  any  given  instant,  etc. 
Usually  the  Plan  will  be  competing  with  other  Plans  also  in  the 
process  of  execution,  and  considerable  thought  may  be  required  in 
order  to  use  the  behavioral  stream  for  advancing  several  Plans 
simultaneously. 

The  parts  of  a  Plan  that  is  being  executed  have  special  access  to 
consciousness  and  special  ways  of  being  remembered  that  are  neces- 
sary for  coordinating  parts  of  different  Plans  and  for  coordinating 
with  the  Plans  of  other  people.  When  we  have  decided  to  execute 
some  particular  Plan,  it  is  probably  put  into  some  special  state  or 
place  where  it  can  be  remembered  while  it  is  being  executed.  Partic- 
ularly if  it  is  a  transient,  temporary  kind  of  Plan  that  will  be  used 
today  and  never  again,  we  need  some  special  place  to  store  it.  The 
special  place  may  be  on  a  sheet  of  paper.  Or  (who  knows?  )  it  may  be 
somewhere  in  the  frontal  lobes  of  the  brain.  Without  committing 
ourselves  to  any  specific  machinery,  therefore,  we  should  like  to 
speak  of  the  memory  we  use  for  the  execution  of  our  Plans  as  a  kind 
of  quick-access,  "working  memory."  There  may  be  several  Plans,  or 
several  parts  of  a  single  Plan,  all  stored  in  working  memory  at  the 
same  time.  In  particular,  when  one  Plan  is  interrupted  by  the  require- 
ments of  some  other  Plan,  we  must  be  able  to  remember  the  inter- 
rupted Plan  in  order  to  resume  its  execution  when  the  opportunity 
arises.  When  a  Plan  has  been  transferred  into  the  working  memory 
we  recognize  the  special  status  of  its  incompleted  parts  by  calling 
them  "intentions." 

The  recall  and  resumption  of  interrupted  tasks  have,  largely  as  a 
result  of  Lewin's  interest,  received  some  attention  in  the  psycholog- 
ical laboratory.  The  studies  are  well  known,  as  is  Lewin's  interpreta- 
tion in  terms  of  tension  systems  that  are  reduced  when  the  task  is 
successfully  completed.  Since  both  Lewin's  tension  system  and  our 
working  memory  are  carefuUy  considered  explanations,  they  both 

Values,  Intentions,  and  the  Execution  of  Plans  ■  65 


account  for  most  of  the  observed  phenomena  and  it  is  difficult  to 
find  clear  points  of  contrast  between  them.  (This  difficulty  is  en- 
hanced by  a  wonderfully  free  and  easy  interpretation  by  Lewin  of 
"tension  system.")  But  there  are  a  few  points  on  which  the  two  theo- 
ries can  be  compared,  and  we  shall  concentrate  on  these. 

First,  we  assume  it  is  a  well-known  fact  that  interrupted  tasks 
tend  to  be  resumed  and  tend  to  be  well  remembered.  However,  the 
tasks  must  be  a  little  complicated.  Simple,  repetitious,  continuous 
tasks — marking  crosses  on  a  sheet  of  paper,  stringing  beads,  etc. — 
will  not  usually  be  resumed  and  do  not  stand  out  in  the  subject's 
memory  when  he  is  later  asked  what  tasks  he  performed.  This  ob- 
servation seems  eminently  reasonable  from  either  Lewin's  or  our 
point  of  view.  For  the  present  authors,  the  argument  would  be  that 
such  tasks  require  little  or  no  record  of  what  has  been  and  what  re- 
mains to  be  accomplished,  and  hence  they  have  no  special  repre- 
sentation in  the  subject's  working  memory.  For  Lewin,  the  argument 
was  that  such  tasks  cannot  be  interrupted,  they  can  only  be  halted. 
Therefore,  interruption  does  not  serve  to  continue  or  prolong  a  ten- 
sion system.  So  far,  the  two  views  do  not  quarrel  with  each  other. 
Moreover,  it  is  recognized  that  even  these  continuous  tasks  can  be 
interrupted  if  the  subject  is  told  in  advance  that  the  task  calls  for  a 
given  amount  of  activity.  If  he  is  told,  for  example,  that  his  task  is  to 
put  thirty  beads  on  a  string,  he  can  be  interrupted  before  he  reaches 
that  number.  Both  views  still  agree,  since  we  predict  that  he  will 
remember  the  task  because  he  had  to  count  and  remember  a  number 
in  order  to  keep  his  place,  and  Lewin  predicts  the  same  result  be- 
cause the  task  is  now  interruptable.  But  suppose  that  the  subject  is 
given  a  pile  of  beads  to  string,  told  he  must  put  all  of  them  on  the 
string,  but  not  told  any  specific  number.  Now  the  predictions  will  be 
different.  We  say  there  should  be  no  tendency  to  resume  or  recall  the 
task,  since  memory  function  is  performed  externally  by  the  pile  of 
beads,  not  by  the  subject.  The  Lewinian  view  would  predict  that 
since  a  tension  system  would  remain  undischarged  because  the  task 
was  interrupted,  the  bead-stringing  should  be  more  quickly  resumed 
and  more  frequently  recalled.  We  do  not  have  experimental  data  with 
which  to  settle  the  point,  but  it  appears  to  us  to  be  a  point  on  which 
data  might  help.  We  are  at  least  encouraged  to  see  that  our  view  is 

66  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


not  just  a  rephrasing  of  Lewin's,  since  a  fairly  clear  disagreement 
can  be  formulated. 

Second,  suppose  a  person  intends  to  write  letters  to  five  different 
people.  He  assem.bles  the  writing  materials  and  begins,  but  he  is 
Interrupted  before  he  finishes.  The  question  is,  will  it  make  a  differ- 
ence in  his  tendency  to  resume  the  task  if  he  is  interrupted  in  the 
middle  of  a  letter  rather  than  between  letters?  In  our  view,  it  would 
make  a  difference.  An  interruption  between  letters  leaves  him  with 
no  memory  problem,  so  the  interrupted  Plan  is  not  assigned  any 
special  place  in  his  working  memory  where  it  might  remind  him  to 
finish  the  job.  We  are  not  clear  what  the  correct  prediction  would 
have  been  for  Lewin.  On  the  one  hand,  each  letter  is  a  separate  task 
with  its  own  tension  system  to  be  discharged,  so  he  would  predict 
as  we  do.  But,  on  the  other  hand,  there  might  be  very  little  tendency 
to  resume  under  either  condition,  because  the  completion  of  a  task 
"similar"  to  the  interrupted  one  (the  completion  of  the  first  three 
letters)  is  supposed  to  provide  a  "substitute  consummation"  to  reduce 
the  tension  systems  associated  with  the  other  letters. 

In  our  terms,  wrriting  letters  would  be  called  a  "flexible"  Plan, 
because  its  parts  can  be  performed  in  any  order.  That  is  to  say,  it 
does  not  matter  in  which  order  the  letters  are  written.  Usually,  there 
is  more  working  memory  involved  in  keeping  track  of  inflexible 
Plans,  because  such  Plans  tend  to  become  more  elaborate  and  specific; 
we  therefore  would  make  a  general  prediction  that,  so  long  as 
external  memory  is  not  used,  a  task  that  requires  an  inflexible  Plan 
will  be  resumed  and  recalled  more  frequently  after  interruptions. 

Third,  in  one  experiment  subjects  were  told  on  half  the  inter- 
rupted tasks  that  the  tasks  would  be  resumed  and  on  the  other  half 
that  they  would  not  be  resumed.  This  advance  information  made 
very  little  difference  in  their  tendency  to  recall  interrupted  tasks 
better.  It  was  on  the  basis  of  this  experiment  that  Zeigarnik  con- 
cluded that  the  possibility  of  resumption  had  no  effect  on  recall. 
However,  an  equally  valid  conclusion  might  be  that  verbal  instruc- 
tions given  at  the  time  of  interruption  cannot  change  the  extent  to 
which  working  memory  has  already  been  devoted  to  the  execution 
of  the  Plan.  But  further  experiments  could  be  helpful  in  settling  the 
difference. 

Values,  Intentions,  and  the  Execution  of  Plans  ■  67 


Finally,  "It  is  often  observed,"  Lewin  wrote,^  "that  even  making 
a  written  note  of  an  intention  is  conducive  to  forgetting  it,  though 
according  to  the  association  theory  it  should  reinforce  the  coupling 
between  the  referent  and  the  goal-presentation.  Making  a  note  is 
somehow  a  consummation,  a  discharge."  This  observation  takes  on 
particular  significance  for  us,  of  course,  since  in  our  view  the  use  of 
external  memory  devices  ordinarily  lightens  the  load  on  our  personal 
memories.  The  forgetting,  if  our  observation  is  valid,  would  not  be 
the  result  of  a  consummation  or  a  discharge  of  tension,  but  rather  the 
result  of  freeing  our  working  memory  capacity  for  other  planning 
activities. 

It  was  a  general  observation  in  Zeigarnik's  studies  that  adults 
did  not  participate  as  enthusiastically  as  the  children  and  that  they 
did  not  show  as  strong  a  tendency  to  recall  the  interrupted  tasks. 
It  seems  probable  to  us  that  an  adult  has  several  Plans  of  his  own 
whose  execution  must  be  temporarily  suspended  during  the  experi- 
ment and  that  he  might  be  reluctant  to  lose  track  of  them  for  these 
little  laboratory  games.  Also,  it  seems  probable  to  us  that  an  adult 
would  have  learned  how  to  make  use  of  external  memory  devices  for 
his  Plans  whenever  possible,  and  so  might  not  use  his  internal  work- 
ing memory  in  the  same  way  a  child  would. 

These  considerations  have,  perhaps,  drifted  rather  far  into  the 
details  of  a  particular  line  of  research.  And  the  present  authors  may 
seem  a  bit  too  intolerant  of  Professor  Lewin,  a  man  who  has  con- 
tributed so  much  to  advance  our  understanding  of  the  psychology  of 
the  will.  The  excuse  is  that  Lewin  in  his  early  work  came  very  close 
to  saying  some  of  the  same  things  this  book  is  trying  to  say.  His 
papers  offer  a  challenge — both  in  theory  and  in  observations.  On 
the  majority  of  points  the  present  interpretation  agrees  with  his 
predictions,  but  the  disagreements  in  theory  have  been  emphasized 
in  the  hope  of  stimulating  their  resolution  in  the  laboratory. 

If  an  intention  is,  as  here  described,  the  unfinished  part  of  a 
Plan  that  is  being  executed,  how  could  anyone  forget  what  he  intends 
to  do?  Forgetting  intentions  is  a  commonplace  occurrence,  of  course, 
and  several  psychologists  have  offered  explanations.  It  is  generally 
assumed  that  forgetting  an  intention  is  not  the  same  as  forgetting  a 

5  Rapaport,  op.  cit.,  p.  111. 

68  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


telephone  number,  although  perhaps  the  same  mechanism  may 
occasionally  be  responsible.  Usually,  however,  forgetting  an  intention 
appears  to  have  some  active  quaUty  to  it  that  is  not  involved  in  the 
kind  of  forgetting  Ebbinghaus  studied.  The  classic  work  that  em- 
phasizes an  active  component  in  forgetting  intentions,  of  course,  is 
Freud's  Psychopathology  of  Everyday  Life.  Freud's  emphasis,  natu- 
rally, was  on  the  dynamic  or  evaluative  aspects  of  such  forgetting, 
on  the  repression  of  the  intended  act  by  other  psychic  forces  that 
opposed  it  in  some  way. 

The  most  obvious  thing  to  say  about  a  forgotten  intention  is 
that  the  Plan  that  gave  it  life  was  not  completed.  The  question  that 
is  basic  to  all  others,  therefore,  is  why  one  Plan  was  abandoned  and 
another  pursued  instead.  If  we  try  to  translate  Freud's  dynamic  ex- 
planation into  the  language  of  this  essay,  we  must  say  that  Plans  are 
abandoned  when  their  execution  begins  to  produce  changes  in  the 
Image  that  are  not  as  valuable  as  we  had  expected.  (This  would  be 
consistent  with  the  Freudian  view,  but  it  is  not  the  only  possible  ex- 
planation. )  The  diagnostic  value  of  a  forgotten  intention  is  that  it  so 
often  underscores  a  change  in  Plan  that  might  otherwise  have  gone 
unnoticed.  And  the  change  in  Plan,  in  turn,  provides  a  clue  to  aspects 
of  the  Image  that  might  not  ordinarily  be  accessible  to  introspection. 
We  could,  of  course,  examine  the  conditions  that  cause  us  to  be  un- 
aware of  the  fact  that  we  have  changed  our  Plans,  but  presumably  the 
conditions  would  be  essentially  those  that  psychoanalysts  tell  us  pro- 
•  duce  repression.  Thus  we  accept  the  notion  that  dynamic  changes  in 
the  Image — especially  in  the  evaluative  aspects  of  the  Image — exert 
close  control  over  the  Plans  we  try  to  execute.  Altering  the  planner's 
Image  is  a  major  dynamic  mechanism  for  altering  his  Plan,  and  thus 
for  altering  his  behavior.  Social  psychologists  who  have  considered 
the  problems  of  persuasion  have  generally  agreed  that  the  best  tech- 
niques involve  some  change  in  the  audience's  concepts  or  values. 
But  we  are  here  (as  throughout  most  of  this  book)  concerned  more 
with  the  execution  than  with  the  formation  of  Plans. 

We  can  easily  imagine  other,  nondynamic  conditions  that 
might  lead  one  to  abandon  a  Plan  and  thus  to  forget  an  intention.  The 
working  memory  may  go  awry,  especially  when  the  execution  of  the 
task  has  been  interrupted  for  some  reason.  To  take  an  extreme  ex- 

Values,  Intentions,  and  the  Execution  of  Plans  ■  69 


ample,  the  man  whose  appointment  book  is  destroyed  through  no 
fault  of  his  own  will  have  lost  track  of  numerous  Plans,  both  pleasant 
and  painful.  Remembering  the  Plan  is  most  difficult  when  we  try  to 
do  it  without  external  crutches,  when  the  Plan  is  new  or  transient, 
and  when  the  Plan  is  complicated.  If  the  Plan  is  written  down  in 
detail,  if  it  is  one  we  follow  repeatedly,  or  if  several  consecutive  sub- 
plans  are  involved,  then  our  working  memory  has  an  easier  task.  We 
therefore  assume  that  intentions  would  be  forgotten  more  frequently 
in  the  former  situations  than  in  the  latter,  ceteris  paribus,  for  purely 
mechanical  reasons  that  Ebbinghaus  would  understand  as  well  as 
we  do. 

Presumably  we  are  constantly  revising  our  Plans  after  we  begin 
to  execute  them.  Ordinarily  we  do  not  make  any  special  note  of  these 
changes,  but  merely  execute  the  new  Plan  as  quickly  as  possible.  But 
a  special  problem  arises  with  shared  Plans.  When  you  have  made 
known  your  intentions,  other  people  may  depend  upon  you  to  carry 
them  out.  Thereafter,  changes  in  your  Plans  must  take  into  account 
what  has  been  said.  You  may  change  the  Plan  for  any  of  a  dozen 
reasons  and  then  forget  to  incorporate  into  your  new  Plan  a  subplan 
for  communicating  to  your  friend  about  the  change.  Forgetting  to 
tell  somebody  that  you  have  changed  your  intentions  is  a  very  differ- 
ent process  from  forgetting  your  intentions. 

Still  another  nondynamic  reason  for  forgetting  an  intention 
might  be  that  some  preparatory  step  in  the  Plan  leading  up  to  the 
intended  act  proved  to  be  impossible.  An  applied  mathematician  may 
intend  to  solve  a  problem  by  first  inverting  a  matrix  and  them  com- 
puting certain  quantities,  but  he  discovers  that  the  particular  matrix 
does  not  have  an  inverse.  He  will  forget  his  intention  to  compute  the 
quantities,  but  not  because  he  has  repressed  it  or  found  it  potentially 
dangerous,  etc.  No  doubt  many  intentions  must  be  forgotten  because 
we  are  not  bright  enough  or  strong  enough  to  execute  the  Plans  in 
which  they  were  embedded.  Not  all  Plans  are  feasible. 

Two  general  consequences  of  the  present  argument  are  worth 
brief  comment  before  closing  the  chapter.  First,  more  research  is 
needed  on  the  way  people  use  external  aids  as  memory  devices — 
to  record  their  Plans,  their  intentions,  and  their  progress  in  executing 
their  Plans.  In  our  enthusiasm  for  memorizing  nonsense  syllables  we 

70  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


have  overlooked  the  importance  of  some  of  these  ancillary  kinds  of 
memory.  Memory  for  intentions  should  not  be  the  private  property 
of  clinicians. 

Second,  what  we  call  an  "effort  of  will"  seems  to  be  in  large 
measure  a  kind  of  emphatic  inner  speech.  Much,  probably  most,  of 
our  planning  goes  on  in  terms  of  words.  When  we  make  a  special 
effort  the  inner  speech  gets  louder,  more  dominating.  This  inner 
shouting  is  not  some  irrelevant  epiphenomenon;  in  a  very  real  sense 
it  is  the  Plan  that  is  running  our  information-processing  equipment. 
As  psychologists  we  should  listen  to  it  more  carefully. 

C.  I.  Lewis  says  only  what  is  plainly  open  to  common  sense 
in  the  following  comment : 

Knowledge,  action,  and  evaluation  are  essentially  con- 
nected. The  primary  and  pervasive  significance  of  knowledge  lies 
in  its  guidance  of  action :  knowing  is  for  the  sake  of  doing.  And 
action,  obviously,  is  rooted  in  evaluation.  For  a  being  which  did 
not  assign  comparative  values,  deliberate  action  would  be  point- 
less; and  for  one  which  did  not  know,  it  would  be  impossible. 
Conversely,  only  an  active  being  could  have  knowledge,  and  only 
such  a  being  could  assign  values  to  anything  beyond  his  own 
feelings.  A  creature  which  did  not  enter  into  the  process  of  reality 
to  alter  in  some  part  the  future  content  of  it,  could  apprehend  a 
world  only  in  the  sense  of  intuitive  or  esthetic  contemplation; 
and  such  contemplation  would  not  possess  the  significance  of 
knowledge  but  only  that  of  enjoying  and  suffering.*^ 

In  this  short  paragraph  Lewis  puts  the  problem  of  the  present  dis- 
cussion. It  is  so  obvious  that  knowing  is  for  the  sake  of  doing  and 
that  doing  is  rooted  in  valuing — but  how?  How  in  the  name  of  all 
that  is  psychological  should  we  put  the  mind,  the  heart,  and  the  body 
together?  Does  a  Plan  supply  the  pattern  for  that  essential  connection 
of  knowledge,  evaluation,  and  action?  Certainly  any  psychology  that 
provides  less — that  allows  a  reflex  being  to  behave  at  random,  or 
leaves  it  lost  in  thought  or  overwhelmed  by  blind  passion — can 
never  be  completely  satisfactory. 

^  Lewis,  op.  cit.,  p.  1. 


Values,  Intentions,  and  the  Execution  of  Plans  "71 


CHAPTER  5 


INSTINCTS 


What  are  instincts?  Probably  no  concept  in  psychology  has  had 
a  more  checkered  career  than  this  one,  the  favorite  explanation  for 
all  behavior  during  one  generation  and  the  favorite  theoretical  scape- 
goat during  the  next. 

Some  definitions  of  instinct  have  emphasized  its  conative,  striv- 
ing, goal-directed,  motivational  aspects.  Unfortunately,  how^ever,  the 
driven  quahty  of  instinctual  behavior  always  seems  to  vanish  when 
the  behavior  is  analyzed  closely.  For  example,  a  young  salmon  has 
an  instinct  to  go  down  river  to  the  sea.  One  could  say  that  he  is  driven 
by  an  instinct  to  reach  salt  water.  But  when  the  facts  are  examined 
more  critically  it  turns  out  that  the  salmon  has  a  photokinetic  and 
phototropic  response  to  the  sunlight  that  strikes  him  in  the  shallow 
water  when  his  skin  pigment  is  thin.  Of  course,  one  might  persist  that 
the  fish  is  driven  to  avoid  sunburn,  but  that  concept  seems  com- 
pletely superfluous.  Statements  about  the  "dynamic"  aspects  of  in- 
stincts almost  always  conceal  ignorance  of  the  physiological  processes 
involved. 

Other  definitions  of  instinct  stress  the  inherited,  unlearned, 
innate  character  of  instinctive  behavior.  Animals  isolated  from  their 

Instincts  ■  73 


kind  at  birth  demonstrate  characteristic  patterns  of  activity  that  they 
could  not  have  acquired  through  learning  or  imitation.  But  is  it  the 
behavior,  the  specific  pattern  of  muscular  coordinations,  that  is 
unlearned?  The  difficulties  with  this  definition  are  well  known  to 
anyone  who  has  tried  conscientiously  to  decide  which  parts  of  an 
animal's  behavior  were  learned  and  which  parts  were  inherited.  In 
rats,  for  example,  one  might  expect  to  find  that  copulation  is  an  in- 
stinctive kind  of  behavior.  And  in  some  sense  it  is.  Yet  the  grossness 
of  the  copulatory  behavior  of  a  rat  who  has  not  had  grooming  experi- 
ence demonstrates  clearly  that  some  practice  of  these  instinctual 
responses  is  necessary.  After  struggling  mightily  with  this  fractiona- 
tion of  behavior  into  the  innate  versus  the  acquired,  many  psychol- 
ogists have  abandoned  the  concept  of  instinct  entirely.  As  Frank 
Beach  once  noted,  the  more  carefully  any  particular  species  of  animal 
is  studied,  the  less  one  hears  about  instincts  in  that  species. 

The  position  of  the  present  authors  is  that  the  study  of  instinct 
would  be  much  less  confusing  if  we  said  it  was  the  Plan,  not  the  be- 
havior, that  is  inherited.  The  small  nugget  of  gold  that  has  encour- 
aged psychologists  to  retain  the  concept  of  instinct  in  spite  of  its 
notorious  difficulties  can  be  preserved,  we  think,  by  defining  an  in- 
stinct as  an  inherited,  inflexible,  involuntary  Plan.  When  we  say  a 
Plan  is  involuntary,  we  mean  that  it  cannot  be  changed  depending 
upon  its  consequences  for  the  organism.  When  we  say  a  Plan  is 
inflexible,  we  mean  that  the  component  parts  of  the  Plan  cannot  be 
rearranged  or  reordered.  And  when  we  say  a  Plan  is  inherited,  we 
mean  that  the  Plan  does  not  have  to  be  learned  or  discovered;  the 
actions  involved  may  be  learned  or  unlearned,  but  the  Plan  that  pro- 
vides the  underlying  structure  to  the  actions  is  innate.  In  the  purest 
case  of  instincts,  perhaps,  the  entire  performance  from  general  strat- 
egy down  through  particular  tactics  to  each  individual  twitch  of  a 
muscle  could  be  programmed  in  advance,  but  if  such  an  instinct  ex- 
ists, we  have  never  heard  of  it. 

In  recent  years,  particularly  in  Europe,  there  has  been  a  revival 
of  interest  in  the  problem  of  instinct.  The  new  field  of  ethology  has 
made  available  a  rapidly  growing  collection  of  detailed  observations 
against  which  any  interpretation  of  instinct  can  be  tested.  The  pres- 
ent authors  have  not  read  all  of  this  material,  but  we  have  surveyed 

74  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


the  more  accessible  secondary  sources  in  order  to  determine  whether 
contemporary  research  is  producing  the  kind  of  results  that  the  con- 
cept of  inherited  Plans  had  led  us  to  expect.  The  outcome  of  that 
survey  was  encouraging  and  some  of  the  major  points  are  worth  sum- 
marizing here.^ 

First,  of  course,  we  discovered  that  ethologists  have  much  to 
say  about  the  stimulus  control  of  behavior,  about  the  recognition  by 
the  animal  of  the  conditions  appropriate  for  executing  a  Plan.  Most 
ethologists  use  a  term  invented  by  Konrad  Lorenz — the  innate  releas- 
ing mechanism — to  describe  the  fact  that  a  Plan  is  not  executed 
until  certain  conditions  are  met.  Many  ingenious  studies  have  been 
conducted  in  order  to  determine  exactly  what  perceptual  pattern  is 
necessary  for  the  release  of  a  particular  reaction.  Those  studies  indi- 
cate that  the  test  phase  of  a  TOTE  unit  is  innately  associated  with 
the  appropriate  operate  phase. 

The  phenomenon  that  has  been  called  "imprinting"  provides  an 
interesting  illustration  of  the  relation  between  the  test  phase  and 
the  operational  phase  of  an  innate  Plan.  A  gosling  should  follow  its 
mother.  The  operational  phase  of  this  Plan,  the  walking,  can  be  built 
into  the  gosling  in  advance.  But  until  it  has  been  hatched  a  gosling 
cannot  know  what  its  mother  looks  like.  Therefore  the  test  phase 
cannot  be  completely  established  until  later.  The  "follow  that"  Plan 
of  the  gosling  initially  has  no  built-in  test  to  characterize  an  ap- 
propriate "that."  The  "that"  is  defined  at  a  critical  period  during  the 
gosling's  development  when  it  first  sees  a  moving  object.  This  first 
large  moving  object  that  a  gosling  normally  sees  is  the  goose,  so  the 
Plan  develops  in  an  adaptive  way.  If  the  first  large  moving  object  the 
gosling  sees  happens  to  be  an  ethologist,  however,  some  amusing 
consequences  can  result.  But  the  important  point  is  that  the  gosling 
must  have,  somewhere  in  its  little  Image,  a  picture  of  mother.  Only 
then  can  it  test  to  see  if  a  particular  object  is  the  object  to  be  followed 
or  not. 

Second,  we  were  impressed  by  Tinbergen's  attempt  to  integrate 
the  ethological  research  on  instinctual  behavior  in  terms  of  a  hier- 

1  A  thorough  review  of  the  history  of  the  ideas  and  observations  that  com- 
prise ethology  is  available  in  W.  H.  Thorpe's  Learning  and  Instinct  in  Animals 
(Cambridge:  Harvard  University  Press,  1956). 

Instincts  ■  75 


archy.2  A  hierarchy  is  such  an  important  aspect  of  what  we  have  been 
calhng  a  Plan  that  we  could  not  help  but  feel  encouraged.  For  readers 
who  have  not  looked  at  Tinbergen's  interesting  book  lately  we  can 
mention  briefly  one  of  his  favorite  examples,  the  reproductive  behav- 
ior of  the  male  stickleback.  The  stickleback  is  a  small  and  very  ag- 
gressive fish.  Its  reproductive  instinct  includes  several  different  kinds 
of  behavior.  The  instinct  is  triggered  by  an  increase  in  length  of  the 
days,  which  leads  the  stickleback  to  migrate  to  shallow  water.  There 
he  selects  his  own  territory,  and  visual  stimulation  releases  a  typical 
pattern  of  behavior.  He  settles  in,  starts  to  build  a  nest,  shows  certain 
bodily  changes,  begins  to  react  to  strangers  by  fighting,  etc.  Thus, 
under  the  large  heading  of  "reproductive  instinct,"  Tinbergen  lists 
four  subheads:  fighting,  nest-building,  mating,  and  caring  for  the 
young.  Which  one  of  these  four  will  occur  at  any  particular  time 
depends  upon  the  environmental  conditions  at  that  time.  If  another 
male  stickleback  invades  the  territory,  the  fighting  pattern  will  be 
released.  But  there  are  several  varieties  of  fighting:  chasing,  biting, 
threatening,  etc.  The  type  that  is  released  depends  upon  the  actions 
of  the  invading  male.  Or,  if  no  other  stickleback  is  present  and  the 
male  is  building  the  nest,  there  are  several  different  actions  he  may 
make  depending  upon  temporary  conditions:  digging,  testing  mate- 
rials, boring,  gluing,  etc.  In  this  way  Tinbergen  develops  and  elab- 
orates his  hierarchical  description  into  ever  smaller,  more  discrete 
units. 

The  instinctive  hierarchy  is  usually  described  by  ethologists  in 
terms  of  units  called  "consummatory  acts."  A  consummatory  act  is 
characterized,  so  they  say,  by  a  thoroughly  stereotyped  motor  pattern. 
In  the  case  of  the  reproductive  instinct  of  the  male  stickleback,  the 
consummatory  acts  in  fighting  are  chasing,  biting,  threatening,  flee- 
ing, etc.  The  consummatory  acts  of  mating  include  the  zigzag  dance, 
leading  the  female  to  the  nest,  showing  the  entrance,  quivering, 
fertilizing  the  eggs,  etc.  These  are  acts  that  can  be  recognized  easily 
from  direct  observation  of  the  animal's  behavior.  And  they  usually 
have  a  "self-exhausting"  character — they  "satisfy"  the  animal,  or 

2  N.  Tinbergen,  The  Study  of  Instinct  (Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press, 
1951),  Chapter  V.  We  refer  here  exclusively  to  Tinbergen's  behavioral  descrip- 
tions, not  his  hierarchical  system  of  neural  centers. 

76  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


change  the  conditions  that  initiated  them.  These  consummatory  acts 
would  seem  to  correspond  to  the  inflexible  Plans  we  have  been  look- 
ing for. 

Tinbergen  is  explicit,  moreover,  that  there  is  a  hierarchical 
organization  within  each  consummatory  act.  The  consummatory  act 
is  much  more  complex  than  a  reflex  or  a  tropism;  it  is  a  coordinated 
activity  of  several  parts  of  the  animal's  body,  which  can  in  turn  be 
analyzed  into  movements  of  muscle  groups  and  then,  finally,  into  con- 
tractions of  individual  muscles.  At  the  higher  levels  of  the  hierarchy 
the  various  components  of  the  instinct  can  be  rearranged  rather 
flexibly  depending  upon  the  particular  environmental  circumstances 
that  prevail.  Tinbergen  interprets  this  to  mean  that  the  instinctual 
hierarchy  becomes  progressively  less  flexible  as  it  approaches  the 
level  of  actual  behavior : 

Now  it  seems  that  the  degree  of  variability  depends  en- 
tirely on  the  level  considered.  The  centres  of  the  higher  levels  do 
control  purposive  behavior  which  is  adaptive  with  regard  to  the 
mechanisms  it  employs  to  attain  the  end.  The  lower  levels,  how- 
ever, give  rise  to  increasingly  simple  and  more  stereotyped  move- 
ments, until  at  the  level  of  the  consummatory  act  we  have  to  do 
wdth  an  entirely  rigid  component,  the  fixed  pattern,  and  a  more 
or  less  variable  component,  the  taxis,  the  variability  of  which, 
however,  is  entirely  dependent  on  changes  in  the  outer  world.^ 

In  comparing  Tinbergen's  hierarchical  description  with  the 
hierarchical  organization  that  we  refer  to  here  as  a  Plan,  one  is  struck 
by  the  fact  that  the  higher  levels  in  his  description  are  not  sequential, 
but  merely  classificatory.  Not  until  Tinbergen's  description  reaches 
the  level  of  the  consummatory  acts  does  it  take  on  the  hierarchically 
organized  sequence  characteristic  of  a  Plan.  Thus  we  are  led  to  think 
of  relatively  discrete,  stereotyped,  innate  Plans  for  organizing  actions 
into  a  consummatory  act,  but  those  acts  are  themselves  ordered  in 
time  by  some  other  kind  of  mechanism.  The  alternative  mechanism 
may  be  either  chaining,  if  the  consequences  of  one  act  provide  the 
situation  needed  to  release  the  next,  or  concatenation,  if  the  next  act 
is  released  by  events  that  were  not  regularly  caused  by  the  preceding 
act.  Concatenations  are  flexible,  chains  are  inflexible,  and,  although 

^  Ibid.,  p.  110. 

Instincts  ■  77 


Plans  may  be  flexible,  innate  Plans  are  not  flexible.  Thus  the  larger 
units,  which  are  simply  concatenated,  appear  to  be  variable,  flexible, 
interchangeable  in  order,  but  the  smaller  units,  which  are  chains  and 
Plans,  appear  to  be  rigid,  fixed,  and  inflexible. 

It  is  always  difficult,  of  course,  to  distinguish  behavior  based  on  a 
Plan  from  behavior  based  on  a  chain,  but  a  simple  concatenation  is 
usually  easy  to  distinguish.  However,  organisms  are  often  so  well 
adapted  to  their  natural  environments  that  a  concatenation  may 
give  the  appearance  of  purposive,  intentional  behavior — as  if  the 
environment  itself  could  serve  as  part  of  the  animal's  memory.  It  is 
almost  as  if  the  Plan  were  not  in  the  organism  alone,  but  in  the  total 
constellation  of  organism  and  environment  together.  How  far  one  is 
willing  to  extend  the  concept  of  a  Plan  beyond  the  boundaries  of  an 
organism  seems  to  be  a  matter  of  metaphysical  predilections.  We 
shall  try  to  confine  our  use  of  the  term  to  Plans  that  either  are,  have 
been,  or  could  be  known  to  the  organism,  so  that  we  shall  not  speak  of 
concatenated  behavior  as  part  of  a  Plan  even  when  it  is  highly  adap- 
tive. Nevertheless,  the  physical  continuity  of  the  environment  itself 
can  provide  a  kind  of  integration  of  instinctive  acts.  For  example, 
when  a  stickleback's  nest-building  is  interrupted  by  a  fight,  he  can 
return  to  it  later  and  take  up  where  he  left  off,  because  the  nest 
"remembers"  where  the  interruption  occurred.  Or,  to  phrase  it  differ- 
ently, the  sight  of  the  partially  built  nest  "releases"  the  next  step  in 
building  the  nest.  Thus  the  kind  of  flexibility  that  an  animal  achieves 
in  the  higher,  more  "strategic"  levels  is,  though  adaptive,  still  of  a 
reactive,  concatenated  character  quite  different  from  the  kind  of 
flexibility  that  can  be  achieved  by  an  intelligent  human  being. 

A  third  and  final  point  about  instinctive  Plans  that  becomes 
evident  when  one  reads  the  ethological  reports  is  that  even  the  sim- 
plest animals  are  often  very  clever  about  carrying  on  several  Plans 
simultaneously,  both  in  isolation  and  together.  Of  course,  if  one  con- 
siders each  of  the  consummatory  acts  in  Tinbergen's  hierarchy  of 
the  reproductive  instinct  to  represent  a  different  Plan,  then  the  im- 
mediately preceding  discussion  of  concatenations  can  be  taken  as  a 
description  of  one  way  to  carry  on  several  Plans  at  once.  But  some 
further  examples  may  be  interesting. 

The   digger   wasp   provides   a  carefully   analyzed   illustration. 

78  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


According  to  Tinbergen's  account  of  Baerends's  research,  the  female, 
when  about  to  lay  an  egg,  digs  a  hole,  kills  or  paralyzes  a  caterpillar, 
carries  the  caterpillar  to  the  hole,  deposits  an  egg  on  it  and  stows  it 
away  in  the  hole.  When  the  egg  hatches  and  the  larva  begins  to  con- 
sume its  food,  she  brings  some  moth  larvae.  Then  she  may  bring  six 
or  seven  caterpillars,  after  which  she  closes  the  hole  and  leaves  it 
forever.  Now,  this  Plan  for  laying  an  egg  is  relatively  simple  and  the 
releasers  can  be  patiently  discovered  for  each  part  of  it.  But  an  inter- 
esting feature  is  that  the  digger  wasp  does  not  work  on  just  one  hole  at 
a  time.  Usually  there  are  two  or  even  three  holes,  each  in  a  different 
phase  of  development.  The  state  of  each  of  the  various  holes  releases 
in  her  the  action  appropriate  for  that  hole,  or,  as  one  might  say,  the 
environment  helps  her  to  remember  what  the  next  step  in  the  adap- 
tive concatenation  must  be. 

Another  example  is  the  behavior  of  the  worker  bee  in  the  hive. 
The  worker  responds  largely  to  proprioceptive  tests,  or  releasers, 
and  does  whatever  is  appropriate  for  the  situation  as  it  is  perceived. 
A  cell  that  has  been  started  by  one  bee  can  be  continued  by  any  other 
bee.  Thus  the  hive  follows  a  kind  of  public  plan,  to  which  each  bee, 
even  the  queen,  contributes  its  part  by  the  execution  of  the  individual 
Plans.  In  this  example,  a  number  of  individual  Plans  are  coordinated, 
through  the  releaser  type  of  mechanism,  into  one  larger,  shared 
plan  for  the  hive.  An  even  more  common  instance  of  coordinating 
separate  Plans  into  one  social  plan  must  occur  whenever  two  animals 
come  together  for  mating.  The  public  plans  of  animals,  however,  are 
more  properly  called  "adaptive  concatenations"  rather  than  Plans. 

The  more  one  considers  the  virtues  of  releasers  the  more  respect 
one  feels  for  the  flexibility  they  permit  in  the  adaptations  of  a  rela- 
tively simple  biological  system.  The  range,  variety,  and  complexity 
of  the  tests  that  can  be  used  to  release  the  consummatory  acts  in- 
crease as  we  climb  the  phylogenetic  scale.  For  example,  the  mating 
behavior  of  chimpanzees  is  guided  by  releasers  so  complex  that  they 
can  attain  sophistication  only  through  demonstration.  As  yet,  how- 
ever, the  organization  of  these  more  complicated  patterns  of  instinc- 
tive behavior  in  mammals  has  received  relatively  little  study. 

The  description  of  instincts  that  seems  to  be  currently  accepted 
by  ethologists  has  many  features  that  are  congenial  to  the  thesis  of 

Instincts  •  79 


this  book.  Their  work  emphasizes  that  there  are  configurations, 
Gestalten,  on  the  behavioral  side  of  the  organism  as  well  as  on  the 
perceptual  side— an  emphasis  that  is  essential  for  any  description 
of  instinct  based  on  Plans  rather  than  on  chains  or  mere  concatena- 
tions of  reflexes. 


80  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


MOTOR  SKILLS 
AND   HABITS 


Consider  for  a  moment  the  family  record  player.  It  is  a  machine 
with  a  routine,  or  program,  that  it  follows  whenever  it  is  properly 
triggered.  The  machine  has  a  routine  for  changing  records.  Whenever 
the  appropriate  stimulus  conditions  are  present — for  example,  when 
the  arm  is  near  enough  to  the  spindle  or  when  a  particular  button  is 
pushed — the  routine  for  changing  the  record  is  executed.  There  is 
even  a  "sense  organ"  that  discriminates  between  ten-inch  and  twelve- 
inch  records,  and  there  are  effectors  that  push  the  next  record  into 
place  and  lower  the  tone  arm  gently  into  the  groove  of  the  record. 
The  entire  performance  is  obviously  involuntary,  for  no  matter  how 
we  curse  the  machine  for  failing  to  play  the  record  we  want,  we  will 
not  alter  its  sequence  of  operations.  The  routine  for  changing  records 
is  built  into  the  machine,  locked  in,  and  it  never  guides  the  actions  of 
any  other  machine. 

However,  the  record  that  is  played  by  the  machine  is  also  a 
program.  It  is  a  program  that  controls  the  small  movements  of  the 
stylus  and,  simultaneously,  the  larger  and  audible  movements  of  the 

Motor  Skills  and  Habits  ■  8i 


diaphragm  of  the  loudspeaker.  But  the  record  is  a  communicable 
program.  It  can  be  played  on  any  one  of  a  large  class  of  different 
machines.  Machines  that  can  use  communicable  programs,  that  can 
share  them  with  other  similar  machines,  are  obviously  more  flexible 
than  those  that  cannot.  The  fixed  cycle  of  the  record  changer  makes 
it  far  less  flexible  than  the  phonograph  stylus,  which  can  follow  an 
indefinite  number  of  different  patterns  of  movement.  Communic ability 
is  an  extremely  important  property  that  a  program — or  a  Plan — can 
have.  Communicable  programs  are  not  limited  to  the  mechanical 
world;  the  chromosome  is  an  example  of  a  communicable  program 
in  biological  form.  At  the  behavioral  level,  of  course,  communicable 
Plans  play  the  central  role  in  our  educational  processes. 

Habits  and  skills  are  Plans  that  were  originally  voluntary  but 
that  have  become  relatively  inflexible,  involuntary,  automatic.  Once 
the  Plan  that  controls  a  sequence  of  skilled  actions  becomes  fixed 
through  overlearning,  it  will  function  in  much  the  same  way  as  an 
innate  Plan  in  instinctive  behavior.  The  description  of  the  conditions 
under  which  various  skilled  components  will  be  triggered,  or  released, 
is  much  the  same  in  both  cases.  The  new  problem  that  we  must  con- 
sider when  we  move  from  instincts  to  habits  and  skflls  concerns  how 
learned  Plans  become  automatized. 

When  an  adult  human  being  sets  out  to  acquire  some  new  skill, 
he  usually  begins  with  a  communicable  program  of  instructions. 
Another  person,  either  verbally  or  by  exemplification,  communicates 
more  or  less  schematically  what  he  is  supposed  to  do.  But  just  having 
the  basic  strategy  in  verbal  form  does  not  mean  that  the  learner  can 
correctly  develop  and  elaborate  the  tactics  on  the  first  try  to  execute 
the  Plan.  For  example,  when  a  man  learns  to  fly  an  airplane  he  begins 
by  getting  a  communicable  Plan  from  his  instructor.^  The  Plan — 
or  a  rough,  symbolic  outline  of  its  strategy — is  communicated 
through  some  such  message  as  this : 

1  California  tends  to  bring  out  unusual  behavior,  so  the  authors  were  not 
completely  surprised  when  one  member  began  to  disappear  in  the  late  afternoons 
to  leam  to  fly.  When  challenged,  he  explained  that  he  was,  in  fact,  conducting 
research  on  a  problem  of  concern  to  us  all:  how  movements  are  integrated  into 
larger  units  to  comprise  a  smoothly  running  Plan  of  action.  What  had  seemed  to 
be  neglect  of  duty  turned  out  to  be  selfless  devotion  to  the  common  cause.  In  the 
course  of  his  explanations  a  number  of  examples  were  discussed  that  helped  to 
shape  the  writing  of  this  chapter. 

82  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


To  land  this  plane  you  must  level  off  at  an  altitude  of 
about  ten  feet.  Then,  after  you  have  descended  to  about  two 
feet,  pull  back  on  the  elevators  and  touch  down  as  you  ap- 
proach stalling  speed.  You  must  remember  that  at  touch-down 
the  control  surfaces  are  less  sensitive,  and  any  gust  may  increase 
your  airspeed.  That  may  start  the  plane  flying  again,  so  be  pre- 
pared to  take  corrective  measures  with  the  throttle  and  elevators. 
And  if  there  is  a  cross-wind,  lower  the  wing  on  the  windward 
side,  holding  the  plane  parallel  to  the  runway  with  the  opposite 
rudder. 

That  is  the  strategy  for  landing  airplanes.  When  skillfully  elab- 
orated and  executed  it  will  serve  to  get  pilot  and  craft  safely  back  to 
earth.  It  is  a  short  paragraph  and  could  be  memorized  in  a  few  min- 
utes, but  it  is  doubtful  whether  the  person  who  memorized  it  could 
land  a  plane,  even  under  ideal  weather  conditions.  In  fact,  it  seems 
likely  that  someone  could  learn  all  the  individual  acts  that  are  re- 
quired in  order  to  execute  the  Plan  and  still  be  unable  to  land  success- 
fully. The  separate  motions,  the  separate  parts  of  the  Plan,  must  be 
fused  together  to  form  a  skilled  performance.  Given  the  description 
of  what  he  is  supposed  to  do,  the  student  still  faces  the  major  task  of 
learning  how  to  do  it. 

There  is  a  kind  of  complementarity  between  the  teacher  and 
the  student.  It  is  easy  for  the  teacher  to  describe  the  general  strategy, 
but  difficult  for  him  to  communicate  the  detailed  tactics  that  should 
be  used.  For  the  student,  on  the  other  hand,  each  of  the  muscular 
movements  involved  can  be  made  in  isolation,  but  it  is  difficult  for 
him  to  combine  those  tactical  details  into  a  larger  motor  unit,  into 
a  feedback  mechanism  that  will  effortlessly  guide  his  movements  to 
reduce  the  differences  between  his  intended  and  his  actual  perform- 
ance. In  order  to  be  able  to  execute  the  Plan  by  a  smooth,  controlled 
motor  unit,  the  aspiring  aviator  must  find  many  small,  intercalated 
acts  not  specified  in  the  instructor's  original  description  of  the  Plan. 
The  general  strategy  provided  by  the  teacher  says  nothing  about  the 
activities  of  individual  muscle  groups — the  instructor  "knows"  these 
intercalated  acts  because  he  knows  how  to  fly,  but  they  are  locked 
in,  implicit,  tacit,  rather  than  explicit  and  communicable.  Thus,  we 
get  a  picture  of  the  instructor  working  from  the  strategic  toward  the 
tactical  in  his  efforts  to  communicate  the  Plan,  while  the  student  is 

Motor  Skills  and  Habits  ■  83 


working  from  the  tactical  toward  the  strategic  in  his  efforts  to  carry 
it  out. 

Even  when  an  instructor  does  recognize  a  possible  intercalated 
act,  it  may  actually  be  better  pedagogy  to  let  the  student  invent 
his  own  idiosyncratic  tactics  for  carrying  the  Plan  into  his  muscles. 

On  take-off  the  throttle  should  be  opened  slowly  so  that 
rudder-control  can  be  introduced  smoothly  to  overcome  the 
tendency  of  the  plane  to  turn  as  a  result  of  increased  torque. 
Open  the  throttle  continuously  so  that  it  is  completed  by  the 
time  you  count  to  five;  when  you  reach  three  start  to  apply  some 
right  rudder. 

The  instruction  to  count  is  an  attempt  to  provide  a  more  detailed  in- 
tegration of  the  successive  parts  of  the  Plan  and  it  is  bad  teaching. 
The  student  is,  or  feels,  terribly  tense  and  terribly  busy.  Telling 
him  to  count  to  five  is  almost  certain  to  interfere  with  his  perform- 
ance of  other  parts  of  the  Plan.  Counting  might  work  for  some  people, 
but  for  the  entire  sample  that  we  studied  it  was  a  dismal  failure — he 
found  a  trick  of  his  own  that  he  Hked  far  better.  As  he  pushed  the 
throttle  forward  to  the  panel  he  kept  one  finger  of  the  hand  on  the 
throttle  extended,  and  when  the  extended  finger  hit  the  panel  he  be- 
gan to  apply  the  right  rudder.  This  simple  device  provided  the  feed- 
back that  enabled  him  to  convert  a  sequence  of  discrete  acts  into  a 
coordinated  unit  of  behavior. 

Since  a  learner  must  discover  these  little  tricks  that  can  connect 
the  successive  parts  into  a  smoothly  running  skill,  it  might  appear 
that  he  is  merely  chaining  one  activity  to  the  next,  not  building  a 
hierarchical  Plan.  But  if  the  skill  is  simply  a  chain  of  reflexes,  each 
one  hooked  to  the  next,  then  it  is  difficult  to  understand  why,  in  the 
preceding  example,  the  instructor's  method  of  chaining  was  not  sat- 
isfactory. Unless  there  is  some  over-all  pattern  to  the  skill,  a  pattern 
that  the  instructor  sees  one  way  and  the  student  sees  differently,  why 
would  one  intercalation,  ceteris  paribus,  be  better  "or  worse  than  an- 
other? 

What  would  happen  if  all  the  details  of  a  sequence  were  worked 
out  by  the  coach  and  imposed  with  rigid  insistence  on  the  learner?    j 
If  skills  were  nothing  but  chains  of  reflexes,  a  detailed  account  of  the 
correct  sequence  should  be  an  efficient  way  to  teach  them.  Probably 

84  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


the  most  intensive  effort  to  specify  exactly  what  a  person  must  do 
with  each  movement  is  the  work  of  "motion  study"  experts.  On  an 
assembly  line  in  a  factory  there  may  be  a  task  that  consists  of,  let  us 
say,  assembling  three  washers  on  a  bolt.  The  analysis  of  this  task  into 
"micromotions"  will  specify  the  exact  time  at  which  each  hand  should 
move  and  the  operation  it  should  perform.  For  the  left  hand,  the  in- 
structions may  read  "Carry  assembly  to  bin,"  "Release  assembly," 
"Reach  for  bolt,"  etc.,  while  at  the  same  time  the  right  hand  is  in- 
structed to  "Reach  for  lock  washer,"  "Select  and  grasp  washer," 
"Carry  washer  to  bolt,"  etc.  For  each  of  these  motions  a  fixed  duration 
is  specified.  This  is  about  as  near  as  anyone  can  come  to  writing  pro- 
grams for  people  that  are  as  detailed  as  the  programs  we  write  for 
computing  machines. 

The  description  of  the  task  can  be  transformed  in  various  ways 
in  an  attempt  to  find  a  sequence  of  motions  that  achieves  the  result 
most  efficiently,  with  fewest  movements  and  in  least  time.  The  men 
who  make  this  kind  of  analysis  have  developed  certain  general  rules 
about  how  sequences  of  action  can  be  formed  to  run  off  smoothly  and 
rapidly.  For  example,  the  two  hands  should  begin  and  complete  their 
movements  at  exactly  the  same  time.  Motions  of  the  arms  should  be 
opposite  and  symmetrical.  There  must  be  a  fixed  position  for  all  tools 
and  materials.  And  on  and  on.  Following  these  rules,  motion-study 
engineers  are  able  to  develop  chains  of  responses  that  can  be  executed 
with  nearly  maximal  efficiency.  But,  unfortunately,  workers  may  not 
acquire  the  strategies  possessed  by  the  engineers — they  frequently 
object  to  being  so  tightly  regimented  and  seem  to  feel  that  the  boss 
is  trying  to  exploit  them  unfairly. 

When  people  have  time  to  develop  the  skill  themselves,  that  is 
to  say,  when  they  form  a  Plan  to  guide  the  gross  actions — even  an 
inefficient  Plan — they  find  for  themselves  the  interposed  elements 
that  produce  the  skill.  Finding  these  elements  is  essentially  a  test  of 
the  adequacy  of  the  strategy.  Once  a  strategy  has  been  developed, 
alternative  modes  of  action  become  possible,  and  we  say  that  the  per- 
son "understands"  the  job  that  he  is  to  do. 

In  most  natural  situations,  the  development  of  skills  involves 
the  construction  of  a  hierarchy  of  behavioral  units,  each  unit  guided 
by  its  own  Plan.  This  fact  is  seldom  recognized  in  the  motion-study 

Motor  Skills  and  Habits  ■   85 


analysis,  which  is  rather  puzzling  because  the  hierarchical  character 
of  skills  was  pointed  out  explicitly  by  Bryan  and  Harter  at  least  as 
early  as  1897,  when  they  demonstrated  the  successive  levels  of  skill 
involved  in  telegraphy.^  In  1908  Book  wired  a  typewriter  to  record 
the  time  of  occurrence  of  successive  key-strokes  and  then  collected 
data  while  people  learned  the  "touch  method"  of  typing.  People  first 
memorized  the  positions  of  the  different  letters  on  the  keyboard. 
Then  they  would  go  through  several  discrete  steps:  look  at  the  next 
letter  in  the  material  that  was  to  be  copied,  locate  this  letter  in  their 
image  of  the  keyboard,  feel  around  on  the  actual  keyboard  for  the  key 
corresponding  to  the  remembered  position,  strike  the  key,  and  look  to 
see  if  it  was  correct.  After  a  few  hours  of  practice  these  components 
of  the  Plan  began  to  fit  together  into  skilled  movements,  and  the 
learner  had  acquired  dependable  "letter  habits."  Further  speed  re- 
sulted when  they  began  to  anticipate  the  next  letter  and  build  up 
small  subroutines  to  deal  with  familiar  sequences  like  -ing  and  the. 
By  then  dependable  "word  habits"  were  developing.  Finally,  the  ex- 
perienced typist  read  the  text  several  words  ahead  of  the  letters  he 
was  typing  at  the  moment,  so  that  one  could  say  he  had  developed 
"phrase  habits."  He  learns,  one  might  say,  to  put  feedback  loops 
around  larger  and  larger  segments  of  his  behavior.  This  sequence  of 
stages  in  the  acquisition  of  typing  skill  is  familiar  to  anyone  who 
has  gone  through  it,  who  has  watched  the  units  at  one  level  of  skill 
come  smoothly  together  to  form  units  at  a  higher  level,  until  eventu- 
ally a  skilled  typist  can  concentrate  on  the  message  and  let  the  mus- 
cles take  care  of  the  execution  of  details. 

Typewriting,  however,  is  a  rather  special  case.  The  final  compo- 
nents, the  key  movements,  are  very  discrete  and  atomic.  Probably 
most  of  the  skills  we  have  to  acquire  are  much  more  fluid  in  their 
execution,  but  these  are  correspondingly  more  difficult  for  a  psychol- 
ogist to  collect  data  on. 

We  have  assumed  that  the  human  being  who  is  acquiring  a  new 
skill  is  aware  of  the  strategy  that  he  is  attempting  to  follow.  At  least, 
he  is  aware  of  it  in  the  sense  that  he  can  talk  about  it  or  point  to  ex- 

2  For  a  short  but  representative  summary,  see  R.  S.  Woodworth  and  H. 
Schlosberg,  Experimental  Psychology  (New  York;  Holt,  rev.  ed.,  1954),  pp.  809- 
813. 

86  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


amples  of  it.  It  is  quite  possible,  of  course,  to  build  up  skills  without 
verbalizing  the  strategy,  the  way  a  baby  learns. 

Almost  no  one — including  physicists,  engineers,  bicycle  manu- 
facturers— can  communicate  the  strategy  whereby  a  cyclist  keeps  his 
balance.  The  underlying  principle  would  not  really  be  much  help  even 
if  they  did  know  how  to  express  it:  "Adjust  the  curvature  of  your  bi- 
cycle's path  in  proportion  to  the  ratio  of  your  unbalance  over  the 
square  of  your  speed."  It  is  almost  impossible  to  understand,  much 
less  to  do.  "Turn  your  handle  bars  in  the  direction  you  are  falling," 
we  tell  the  beginner,  and  he  accepts  it  blindly,  not  understanding  then 
or  later  why  it  works.  Many  teachers  impart  no  rule  at  all,  but  per- 
form their  service  by  running  along  beside  the  bicycle,  holding  it  up 
until  the  beginner  "gets  the  idea."  ^  It  is  not  necessary,  fortunately, 
to  know  explicitly  the  rules  that  must  be  observed  by  a  skillful  per- 
former— if  it  were,  few  of  us  would  ever  be  able  to  sit  up  in  our  cra- 
dles. Sometimes  we  can  help  a  learner  do  the  right  thing  for  the  wrong 
reason,  as  when  we  tell  a  skier  to  make  a  left  turn  by  imagining  that 
he  is  putting  his  right  hand  in  his  left  pocket  or  when  we  tell  a  golfer 
to  keep  his  eye  on  the  ball.  But  for  the  most  part  we  must  rely  upon 
inarticulate  guiding  and  demonstrating  until  the  pupil  "catches  on" 
or  "gets  a  feel  for  it." 

Animals  acquire  skills,  of  course,  without  memorizing  verbal 
descriptions  of  what  they  are  supposed  to  do.  When  we  train  an  ani- 
mal to  execute  a  series  of  responses  in  order  to  attain  a  valued  out- 
come, the  strategy  is  not  carried  in  the  animal's  memory.  Only  the 
experimenter  needs  to  know  the  total  Plan.  The  animal  is  required 
merely  to  build  up  the  smooth  transitions  that  chain  one  action  to  the 
next.  That  was  probably  the  goal  of  the  motion-study  experts. 

For  example,  if  we  wish  to  train  an  animal  to  press  a  lever  in 
order  to  get  a  ball,  then  to  push  the  ball  into  a  funnel,  and  after  that 
to  return  to  the  food  magazine  to  be  fed,  we  could  build  up  the  chain 
in  many  different  ways.  Any  of  the  components  could  be  taught  at 
any  time.  Then  when  they  are  put  together  the  consequences  of  one 

3  The  bicycle  is  borrowed  from  Michael  Polanyi,  Personal  Knowledge  (Chi- 
cago: University  of  Chicago  Press,  1958).  Chapter  4  in  that  remarkable  book 
emphasizes  the  importance  of  our  inarticulate  skills  for  all  branches  of  knowl- 
edge and  the  extent  to  which  we  blindly  accept  a  frame  of  reference  that  we 
cannot  justify  when  we  acquire  a  skill. 

Motor  Skills  and  Habits  ■  87 


action  become  the  occasion  for  the  next  action,  and  each  new  seg- 
ment is  released  as  it  becomes  appropriate.  Probably  we  would  choose 
to  build  up  the  chain  of  responses  backwards,  starting  first  with  the 
approach  to  the  food  tray,  then  with  the  ball  down  the  funnel,  etc. 
Many  psychologists  are  quite  skillful  at  training  animals  to  perform 
such  long  and  elaborate  stunts.  But  we  would  argue  that  the  animals 
seldom  acquire  the  total  Plan;  the  strategy  is  in  the  trainer,  or  in  his 
mechanical  substitute,  the  experimental  equipment.  The  animal  has 
learned  a  number  of  different  components  that  enable  it  to  perform 
as  though  it  had  a  larger  Plan.  The  critical  test  occurs  when  some 
particular  outcome  in  the  long  chain  fails  to  occur  on  schedule.  The 
animal  will  not  continue  with  the  next  step.  Tolman  and  his  students 
have  argued  that  rats  are  capable  of  mastering  a  total  Plan  as  well  as 
its  component  parts,  but  a  rat's  skills  in  this  direction  are  difficult  to 
demonstrate  in  a  laboratory  situation.*  In  any  case,  rats  are  so  vastly  : 
inferior  to  human  beings  in  their  ability  to  remember  elaborate  Plans 
that  it  is  difficult  to  see  why  psychologists  have  felt  that  valid  gener- 
alizations about  cognitive  structure  could  be  extended  from  rats  to  i 
men.  A  central  feature  of  the  difference,  of  course,  is  that  men  have 
language  to  communicate  their  Plans  from  expert  to  novice  and  from 
one  generation  to  the  next. 

The  verbal  Plans  with  which  a  beginner  tackles  a  new  job — the 
look-remember-hunt-hit-check  Plan  for  typing,  or  the  move-right- 
rudder-when-extended-finger-touches-panel  Plan  for  taking  off — get 
turned  over  to  the  muscles  that  carry  them  out  when  the  skill  is  ac- 
quired.^ The  verbal  form  of  the  Plan  is  a  learner's  crutch  which  is 

4  The  evidence  indicates  that  rats,  and  probably  most  other  inarticulate 
creatures,  are  much  more  proficient  in  mastering  Plans  when  the  Images  that 
support  them  can  be  spatially  organized.  The  well-known  observation  by  Karl 
Lashley  in  his  Brain  Mechanisms  and  Intelligence  (Chicago:  University  of  Chi- 
cago Press,  1929)  that  rats  that  had  learned  a  maze  could  still  negotiate  it  even 
though  Lashley  had,  by  surgical  operations,  made  it  impossible  for  them  to  use 
the  customary  sequence  of  movements  must  mean  that  new  motor  tactics  could 
be  substituted  into  the  same  general  strategy;  certainly  the  maze  skill  was  not  a 
learned  chain  of  movements.  When  the  organization  cannot  be  represented 
spatially,  however,  as  in  Hunter's  temporal  maze  (see  W.  S.  Hunter,  The  temporal 
maze  and  kinaesthetic  sensory  processes  in  the  white  rat,  Psychobiology,  1920,  2, 
1-17),  the  rat  has  great  difficulty.  Cf.  Donald  T.  Campbell,  Operational  delinea- 
tion of  "what  is  learned"  via  the  transposition  experiment.  Psychological  Review, 
1954,  61,  167-174. 

s  For  a  discussion  of  the  integration  and  symbolization  of  overlearned 
responses,  see  George  Mandler,  Response  factors  in  human  learning.  Psycho- 
logical Review,  1954,  61,  235-244. 

88  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


later  discarded  when  he  learns  to  walk  alone.  The  entire  pattern  of 
movements,  guided  continually  by  perceptual  feedback,  can  then  be 
represented  in  other  Plans  as  if  it  were  a  unitary,  independent  act. 
The  same  procedure  of  welding  these  new  units  together  to  form  still 
larger  skilled  units  may  repeat  at  the  higher  level,  until  eventually 
the  typist  is  planning  whole  paragraphs  or  the  aviator  is  planning 
whole  trips,  secure  that  when  the  time  comes  to  execute  the  Plan  the 
subdivisions  will  be  prepared  to  carry  out  orders  in  a  rapid,  efficient 
manner. 

The  verbahzed  strategies  of  a  beginner  may  achieve  the  same  re- 
sult as  the  involuntary,  habitual  strategies  of  an  expert,  so  there  is 
a  sense  in  which  we  recognize  that  they  are  the  "same"  Plan.  But  the 
beginner's  plan  is  carried  out  in  a  way  that  is  voluntary,  flexible,  and 
communicable,  whereas  the  expert's  version  of  the  Plan  is  involun- 
tary, inflexible,  and,  usually,  locked  in.  One  can  say  that  the  develop- 
ment of  skiU  frees  the  verbal  planner  to  work  with  larger  units  of  the 
Plan. 

The  implication  of  this  attitude  toward  skills  and  habits  is  that 
man  is  assumed  to  be  capable  of  building  up  his  own  "instincts." 
Lower  animals  come  with  strategies  wired  in;  man  wires  them  in 
deUberately  to  serve  his  ov^ti  purposes.  And  when  the  Plan  is  highly 
overlearned,  it  becomes  almost  as  involuntary,  as  resistant  to  change 
depending  upon  its  outcome,  as  if  it  were  innate.  Take  a  skilled  typist, 
who  for  years  has  triggered  off  a  muscular  pattern  for  striking  t,  then 
h,  and  finally  e  whenever  he  wants  to  write  "the."  Offer  him  money 
to  type  a  page  with  the  word  "the"  always  transcribed  as  "hte,"  then 
watch  him  work.  Probably  he  will  not  be  able  to  do  it.  If  he  does,  he 
will  do  it  by  slowing  down,  by  trying  to  reinstate  letter  habits  instead 
of  word  and  phrase  habits,  thus  abandoning  his  usual  Plan  for  typing. 
If  you  put  pressure  on  him  to  work  fast  in  order  to  earn  the  money,  he 
will  certainly  not  be  able  to  inhibit  his  usual  Plan  of  action.  Your 
money  is  quite  safe.  But  one  word  of  caution :  Do  not  let  the  offer  stand 
too  long,  for  habits  are  not  completely  resistant  to  change.  If  you  take 
the  time,  you  can  replace  them  with  new  habits.  Let  him  practice 
enough  and  he  will  build  up  the  action  unit  needed  to  wdn  your 
money. 

A  good  typist  has  constructed  a  set  of  inflexible  strategies  with 

Motor  Skills  and  Habits  ■  89 


most  of  the  properties  of  instincts,  a  fact  that  nonpsychologists  often 
recognize  when  they  speak  of  habitual  actions  as  "instinctive."  The 
human  being  is  frequently  the  victim  of  releasers  for  his  skilled  acts, 
just  as  the  lower  animal  is  for  his  instinctive  acts.  A  trained  athlete, 
for  example,  waits  for  the  starting  gun  before  he  begins  to  execute 
his  Plan  for  running  the  race.  But  he  does  not  have  his  starting  com- 
pletely under  volitional  control,  for  otherwise  he  would  never  make  a 
false  start,  or  "jump  the  gun."  The  human  being's  advantage  lies  in 
the  fact  that  his  releasers  are  more  complicated  and  that,  moreover, 
he  can  usually  determine  the  conditions  under  which  a  releasing 
stimulus  will  be  presented,  whereas  in  the  case  of  the  animal's  in- 
stinctive act  the  trigger  is  usually  simple  and  is  provided  by  an  en- 
vironment that  is  not  under  the  animal's  control. 

The  construction  of  integrated  strategies  for  skilled  acts  through 
long  practice  and  repetition  has  a  further  consequence  for  the  kind  of 
planning  that  the  adult  human  can  do.  The  construction  of  these  sub- 
plans  enables  a  person  to  deal  "digitally"  with  an  "analogue"  process.^ 
The  input  to  an  aviator,  for  example,  is  usually  of  a  continuously 
varying  sort,  and  the  response  he  is  supposed  to  make  is  often  propor- 
tional to  the  magnitude  of  the  input.  It  would  seem  that  the  good  flier 
must  function  as  an  analogue  device,  a  servomechanism.  The  be- 
ginner cannot  do  so,  of  course,  because  his  Plans  are  formulated 
verbally,  symbolically,  digitally  and  he  has  not  yet  learr^ed  how  to 
translate  these  into  the  continuous,  proportionate  movements  he  is  re- 
quired to  make.  Once  the  subplan  is  mastered  and  turned  over  to  his 
muscles,  however,  it  can  operate  as  if  it  were  a  subprogram  in  an  an- 
alogue computer.  But  note  that  this  program,  which  looks  so  contin- 

6  In  the  language  of  computing  machines,  an  analogue  device  is  one  in 
which  the  magnitudes  involved  in  the  computations  are  represented  by  physical 
quantities  proportional  to  those  magnitudes,  e.g.,  by  a  voltage,  a  duration,  an 
angle  of  rotation,  etc.  Thus,  continuous  variation  in  the  input  to  the  machine  will 
result  in  a  correspondingly  continuous  variation  in  the  magnitude  of  the  proc- 
esses that  represent  it  inside  the  machine  and  in  the  output  of  the  machine.  A 
digital  computer,  on  the  other  hand,  represents  the  magnitudes  with  which  it 
works  by  symbols  corresponding  to  discretely  different  states  of  the  machine,  e.g., 
by  a  relay  that  is  closed  or  open,  or  a  dial  that  can  assume  any  one  of  ten  posi- 
tions, etc.  Thus  there  is  no  simple  resemblance  between  the  input  to  a  digital 
computer  and  the  processes  that  represent  that  input  inside  the  machine.  If  you 
multiply  by  vmting  the  numbers  on  paper,  you  are  using  a  digital  procedure.  If 
you  multiply  by  using  a  slide  rule,  you  are  using  an  analogue  procedure.  See  John 
von  Neumann,  The  Computer  and  the  Brain  (New  Haven:  Yale  University  Press, 
1958). 

90  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


uous  and  appropriately  analogue  at  the  lower  levels  in  the  hierarchy, 
is  itself  a  relatively  stable  unit  that  can  be  represented  by  a  single 
symbol  at  the  higher  levels  in  the  hierarchy.  That  is  to  say,  planning 
at  the  higher  levels  looks  like  the  sort  of  information-processing  we 
see  in  digital  computers,  whereas  the  execution  of  the  Plan  at  the 
lowest  levels  looks  like  the  sort  of  process  we  see  in  analogue  com- 
puters. The  development  of  a  skill  has  an  effect  similar  to  providing 
a  digital-to-analogue  converter  on  the  output  of  a  digital  computing 
machine.  (It  may  also  be  true  that  the  perceptual  mechanism  pro- 
vides an  analogue-to-digital  input  for  the  higher  mental  processes, 
but  we  shall  not  explore  that  possibility  here.)  When  an  action  unit 
has  become  highly  skilled  it  can  be  executed  directly  without  being 
first  expressed  in  a  digital,  or  verbal,  form,  and  even  wdthout  focal 
awareness.'^ 

A  reader  who  resents  such  crudely  mechanistic  analogies  and 
hypotheses  has  the  authors's  sympathy,  but  it  is  difficult  to  know  how 
to  express  more  accurately  the  difference  between  the  strategic  and 
tactical  levels  of  skilled  and  habitual  Plans.  The  argument  could,  of 
course,  be  phrased  in  neurological  terms  that  might  sound  a  bit  less 
offensive.  The  cerebellum,  for  example,  which  has  been  considered 
the  regulator  and  integrator  of  voluntary  movements,  may  play  the 
role  of  the  digital-to-analogue  converter.  In  a  discussion  of  the  cere- 
bellum as  a  feedback  mechanism,  T.  C.  Ruch  commented  that  "slow- 
ness of  voluntary  movement  is  characteristic  of  cerebellar  patients 
and  of  normal  individuals  executing  unpracticed  movements."  ^  The 
problem  for  most  theories  of  the  neural  basis  of  skilled  movements  is 
that  the  skilled  movements  run  off  so  very  rapidly  that  there  is  Uttle 
time  for  proprioceptive  feedback  from  one  movement  before  another 
must  occur.  Any  simple  conception  in  terms  of  feedback,  or  error- 
correcting,  circuits  must  cope  with  the  relatively  slow  transmission 
rates  that  are  possible  over  neural  paths.  Ruch  suggests  that  "a  time- 
tension  pattern  of  muscle  contraction"  is  instituted,  projecting  into 

"^  Pavlov's  well-known  distinction  between  a  first  signal  system,  concerned 
wdth  directly  perceived  stimuli,  and  a  second  signal  system,  devoted  to  verbal 
elaborations,  seems,  insofar  as  we  understand  it,  to  parallel  the  present  distinc- 
tion between  analogue  and  digital  systems.  See  Brian  Simon,  ed..  Psychology  in 
the  Soviet  Union  (Stanford:  Stanford  University  Press,  1957). 

8  T.  C.  Ruch,  Motor  systems,  in  S.  S.  Stevens,  ed..  Handbook  of  Experimental 
Psychology  (New  York:  Wiley,  1951),  Chapter  5,  p.  204. 

Motor  Skills  and  Habits  ■  91 


the  future,  and  then  he  notes  that  for  such  "planning  movements" 
the  nervous  system  would  have  to  have  some  way,  presently  unknown, 
of  storing  impulses  for  fixed  delays. 

The  cerebral-cerebellar  circuit  may  represent  not  so  much 
an  error-correcting  device  as  a  part  of  a  mechanism  by  which  an 
instantaneous  order  can  be  extended  forward  in  time.  Such  a 
circuit,  though  uninformed  as  to  the  consequences,  could,  so  to 
speak,  "rough-in"  a  movement  and  thus  reduce  the  troublesome 
transients  involved  in  the  correction  of  movement  by  output-in- 
formed feedbacks.^ 

These  suggestions  correspond  remarkably  well  to  the  kind  of  hier- 
archical Plans  we  have  been  considering  here,  particularly  if  we  can 
consider  Ruch's  "instantaneous  order"  as  an  instruction  generated  by 
a  digital  device  and  issued  to  an  analogue  device  for  the  execution  of 
planned  movements.  A  Plan,  either  stored  in  or  transferred  to  the 
cerebellum,  would  provide  the  roughed-in  movement  in  advance  of 
its  actual  execution. 

With  proper  scientific  caution,  Ruch  comments  that  such  anal- 
ogies between  neural  systems  and  servo  systems  are  "essentially 
allegorical."  Yet  it  is  difficult  to  see  how  we  can  get  along  without 
them.  The  first  thing  we  must  know  about  any  machine  we  might 
want  to  study  is  that  it  really  is  a  machine,  and  the  second  is  a  shrewd 
guess  as  to  what  it  is  supposed  to  do.  Given  that  much  guidance,  it  is 
then  possible  to  analyze  in  proper  scientific  spirit  how  the  parts  work 
to  accomplish  their  purpose.  But  without  a  guess  to  guide  him,  the 
scientist  may  waste  his  beautifully  precise  descriptions  on  irrelevant 
aspects  of  the  problem.  It  is  in  that  spirit  that  one  ventures  a  guess 
that  the  cerebellum  is  a  machine  to  provide  analogue  Plans  for  reg- 
ulating and  integrating  muscular  coordinations,  that  is  to  say,  that 
the  cerebellum  is  a  critical  component  in  a  digital-to-analogue  con- 
verter on  the  output  of  the  neural  system  for  processing  information. 

In  the  chapters  that  follow  there  will  be  little  discussion  of  the 
analogue  levels  of  action  until  Chapter  14.  It  will  be  assumed  that 
skills  and  habits  can  be  represented  digitally  as  a  sort  of  motor  vocab- 
ulary. It  may  be  well,  therefore,  to  summarize  what  we  have  said 

9  Ibid.,  p.  205. 

92  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


about  instincts  and  skills :  Both  skills  and  instincts  are  on-going  pat- 
terns of  action,  directed  toward  the  environmental  conditions  that 
activate  and  guide  them  and  organized  hierarchically  into  action  units 
with  more  than  one  level  of  complexity.  The  authors  contend  that 
these  characteristics  cannot  be  understood  in  terms  of  a  theory  of 
behavior  based  solely  on  chains  of  reflexes  or  simple  S-R  connections; 
some  theoretical  machinery  at  least  as  elaborate  as  the  TOTE  hier- 
archies envisioned  here  would  seem  to  be  indispensable. 

We  turn  now  to  more  complicated  behaviors  in  which  the  ma- 
nipulation of  symbols,  especially  verbal  symbols,  becomes  a  critically 
important,  though  often  covert,  component. 


Motor  Skills  and  Habits  ■  93 


CHAPTER  7 


THE   INTEGRATION 
OF    PLANS 


Most  people  in  our  culture  try  to  carry  on  several  Plans  at  the 
same  time.  Mrs.  Jones  has  a  recurrent  Plan  for  keeping  her  house 
running  that  she  revises  and  executes  daily.  She  also  has  a  nonre- 
current Plan  to  visit  her  sister  in  Baltimore.  And  she  is  collaborating 
in  a  shared  Plan  to  get  her  neighbor  elected  sheriff.  With  all  of  these 
Plans  (and  more)  running  at  one  time,  her  problem  is  to  perform 
those  acts  that  simultaneously  advance  the  greatest  number  of  them. 
Thus,  Mrs.  Jones  may  decide  to  drive  to  town,  get  her  hair  done  be- 
fore she  leaves  to  see  her  sister,  pick  up  the  election  posters  at  the 
print  shop,  and  buy  the  week's  groceries.  One  trip  to  town  serves  to 
advance  three  Plans  at  once. 

Psychologists  recognize  that  people  do  things  because  several 
"motives"  are  working  together,  and  they  have  discussed  the  phenom- 
enon in  terms  of  "summation"  and  the  "multiple  causation  of  be- 
havior," etc.  But  they  have  done  very  little  to  advance  our  under- 
standing of  it  beyond  the  level  any  intelligent  layman  must  achieve 
in  order  to  get  through  a  modern  day  in  a  modern  city.  How  do  we 

The  Integration  of  Plans  ■  95 


coordinate  several  Plans  into  the  single  stream  of  behavior  that  we 
have  available?  How  do  we  judge  whether  some  new  Plan  is  com- 
patible with  what  we  are  already  doing  or  whether  it  will  be  impos- 
sible to  assimilate  it  into  our  other  Plans?  How  are  our  multiple  Plans 
related  to  the  multiple  roles  we  must  play  in  society?  How  does  the 
ability  to  reconcile  'and  coordinate  different  Plans  develop  in  chil- 
dren? How  can  we  learn  to  relate  all  our  Plans  to  the  hands  of  the 
clock? 

It  would  help  a  great  deal  if  we  had  a  general  language  specially 
designed  for  talking  about  Plans. ^  Such  a  language  would,  presum- 
ably, give  us  a  convenient  notation  for  such  aspects  as  flexibility  of 
Plans,  the  substitution  of  subplans,  conditional  and  preparatory  sub- 
plans,  etc.  For  example,  it  does  not  particularly  matter  in  what  order 
Mrs.  Jones  chooses  to  run  her  errands  when  she  gets  to  town.  The 
three  subplans  can  be  permuted  in  order,  and  so  we  say  that  this  part 
of  her  Plan  is  flexible.  But  she  cannot  permute  the  order  of  these  with 
the  subplan  for  driving  to  town,  or  for  driving  home.  That  part  of  the 
Plan  is  inflexible.  Some  subplans  are  executed  solely  for  the  purpose 
of  creating  the  conditions  under  which  another  subplan  is  relevant. 
Such  preparatory  or  mobilizing  subplans  cannot  be  freely  moved 
about  with  respect  to  the  other  subplans  that  they  anticipate.  Another 
important  dimension  of  freedom  that  should  be  analyzed  is  the  inter- 
changeability  of  subplans.  Mrs.  Jones  can  drive  to  town  over  a  variety 
of  equivalent  routes.  The  variety  is  limited  only  by  the  condition  that 
they  terminate  when  one  of  her  three  alternative  destinations  is 
reached,  since  only  then  would  the  next  part  of  her  Plan  become 
relevant.  Given  a  satisfactory  Plan  and  a  statement  of  the  flexibility 
and  substitutability  of  its  subplans,  we  should  then  be  able  to  generate 
many  alternative  Plans  that  are  also  satisfactory.  And  we  should  like 
to  have  ways  for  deciding  which  combinations  of  Plans  are  most 
efficient  (in  some  appropriately  loose  sense  of  "efficient"). 

^  The  information-processing  languages  developed  by  Newell,  Shaw,  and 
Simon  are  one  solution,  of  course,  but  what  we  are  thinking  of  here  would  be  a 
more  abstract  and  general  sort  of  calculus — something  that  would  deal  with  in- 
structions at  about  the  same  level  of  generality  as  that  on  which  propositional 
logic  deals  with  descriptive  statements.  We  have  given  a  smaU  amount  of  thought 
to  the  problem,  but  are  not  persuaded  that  anything  less  complex  than  a  com- 
puter language  could  be  developed.  The  reader  who  would  like  to  pursue  the 
question  further  can  find  a  rich  source  of  data  and  ideas  in  Roger  G.  Barker  and 
Herbert  F.  Wright,  Midwest  and  Its  Children  (Evanston:  Row,  Peterson,  1954), 


96  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


It  is  not  always  obvious,  especially  to  the  person  concerned, 
whether  or  not  two  Plans  are  compatible.  We  once  knew  a  very  intelli- 
gent man  who  spent  years  trying  to  write  an  introductory  physics 
text  in  the  form  of  a  novel  so  that  more  people  would  read  it.  A  great 
deal  of  work  went  into  his  project  before  he  was  able  to  convince  him- 
self that  the  Plan  for  writing  a  physics  text  could  not  be  coordinated 
with  the  Plan  for  writing  a  novel.  Or,  again,  for  years  physicists  as- 
sumed that  the  position  and  the  velocity  of  a  particle  could  be  meas- 
ured simultaneously  to  any  required  degree  of  accuracy.  The  man 
who  discovered  that  the  Plans  for  making  these  two  measurements 
simultaneously  were  incompatible  produced  a  revolution  in  our  con- 
ception of  the  physical  universe.  The  discovery  that  two  Plans  are 
incompatible  may  require  great  intelligence  and  may  completely  re- 
vise the  Image. 

We  see,  therefore,  that  a  person  who  is  caught  between  con- 
fhcting  Plans  is  in  a  somewhat  different  situation  from  the  person 
caught  between  conflicting  motives.  He  is  almost  necessarily  unaware 
that  his  Plans  conflict,  whereas  he  may  be  painfully  conscious  of  his 
incompatible  desires.  There  is  almost  certain  to  be  a  large  penumbra 
of  confusion  surrounding  the  incompatible  Plans;  the  person  seems 
to  be  deliberately  frustrating  himself,  but  cannot  discover  why.  He 
knows  something  is  wrong,  but  cannot  discover  what  it  is.  The  two 
Plans  may  be  isolated  from  one  another  in  such  a  way  that  it  never 
occurs  to  the  person  to  contrast  one  with  the  other.  In  severe  cases 
the  result  may  be  a  "dual  personality." 

The  problem  of  conflicting  Plans  is  most  difficult  when  the  two 
Plans  are  quite  pervasive  and  the  total  abandonment  of  either  one  of 
them  is  impossible.  This  kind  of  conflict  is  common  among  neurotic 
patients.  A  frequent  example  is  provided  by  the  person  who  has  ac- 
cepted two  Plans  of  life,  one  from  his  mother  and  the  other  from  his 
father.  Either  Plan  might  be  executed  separately,  and  often  both  Plans 
can  be  executed  simultaneously.  But  it  may  happen  that  the  pattern 
supplied  by  the  mother  conflicts  with  that  supplied  by  the  father.  For 
example,  the  mother  may  give  a  Plan  that  requires  personal  independ- 
ence, whereas  the  father  supplies  a  Plan  that  demands  he  be  author- 
itarian. When  he  tries  to  execute  both  of  these  Plans  simultaneously 
he  cannot  discover  any  acts  that  advance  them  both  at  the  same  time. 

The  Integration  of  Plans  ■  97 


Indecision,  vacillation,  or  inaction  may  be  the  result,  so  that  neither 
Plan  is  executed.  Or  he  may  struggle  to  free  himself  from  one  Plan 
or  the  other,  to  identify  with  one  parent  or  the  other.  If  the  person 
tries  to  free  himself  from  the  maternal  pattern,  his  rejection  of  ma- 
ternal love  may  cause  a  crisis  in  character:  ethical  guilt.  If  he  tries  to 
abandon  the  Plan  supplied  by  his  father,  his  rejection  of  the  paternal 
edict  may  cause  a  crisis  in  conduct:  moral  guilt.  In  any  situation 
where  a  successful  Plan  suddenly  becomes  useless,  the  reluctant 
desertion  of  that  Plan  is  accompanied  by  strong  emotions.  But  more 
about  this  in  Chapter  8. 

It  should  be  noted  in  passing  that  the  task  of  integrating  several 
Plans  into  a  single  stream  of  behavior  must  be  accomplished  by  the 
same  organism  that  is  forming  and  executing  the  several  different 
Plans.  If  successive  Plans  are  merely  concatenated  by  chance  happen- 
ings in  the  person's  environment,  there  is  no  problem.  But  if  he  co- 
ordinates them  intelligently,  there  must  be  some  kind  of  mechanism 
for  doing  it.  And,  presumably,  that  mechanism  will  itself  be  of  the 
same  general  form — a  TOTE  hierarchy — that  we  have  described  al- 
ready. The  new  feature,  however,  is  that  the  "objects"  that  this  co- 
ordinating TOTE  hierarchy  tests  and  operates  upon  are  themselves 
TOTE  hierarchies.  That  is  to  say,  we  must  have  Plans  that  operate 
upon  Plans,  as  well  as  Plans  that  operate  upon  information  to  guide 
motor  behavior.  This  fact  introduces  a  degree  of  complexity  that  we 
shall  try  to  discuss  in  later  chapters. 

The  problem  of  coordinating  several  Plans  into  a  single  stream 
of  action  is  difficult  enough,  but  consider  how  much  more  difficult 
things  can  become  when  several  people  try  to  work  together,  when 
they  try  to  execute  a  public  plan  based  upon  some  public  image.  A 
public  plan  exists  whenever  a  group  of  people  try  to  cooperate  to  at- 
tain a  result  that  they  would  not  be  willing  or  able  to  achieve  alone. 
Each  member  takes  upon  himself  the  performance  of  some  fragment 
of  the  public  plan  and  incorporates  that  fragment  into  his  individual, 
personal  Plans.  If  the  public  plan  is,  for  instance,  to  build  new  swings 
on  the  community  playground,  then  Jones  must  agree  to  get  the 
materials  and  have  them  delivered.  Smith  must  agree  to  clear  away 
the  old  swings.  Brown  must  agree  to  put  up  the  new  swings,  and 
Cohen  must  agree  to  collect  contributions  from  the  neighbors  to  pay 

98  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


for  it.  Taken  separately,  none  of  these  activities  would  make  much 
sense.  Only  as  part  of  a  larger,  shared  plan  do  they  have  any  meaning. 

Of  course,  each  of  the  four  men  involved  in  the  shared  plan  may 
get  helpers  and  subdivide  his  part  of  the  plan  even  further.  In  this 
way  we  would  find  that  the  community  had  constructed  a  "tree,"  a 
hierarchy  of  plans  analogous  to  the  hierarchical  Plans  we  have  dis- 
cussed in  single  individuals.  At  the  trunk  of  the  tree  are  a  few  people 
who  plan  the  strategy  for  the  entire  group.  At  the  tips  of  the  limbs  are 
the  many  workers  who  carry  out  the  tactics  of  their  own  subplans. 
We  Americans  spend  a  great  deal  of  our  time  coordinating  and  par- 
ticipating in  just  this  kind  of  social  planning. 

As  soon  as  "social  planning"  is  mentioned,  of  course,  a  host  of 
associations  rush  to  mind.  There  is,  for  example,  the  traditional  de- 
bate over  the  role  of  the  government  as  a  source  of  social  plans. 
Should  the  state  lay  out  our  social  plans  for  us  in  five-year  install- 
ments, or  should  we  trust  that  some  natural  equilibrium  will  result 
from  the  interaction  of  our  private  Plans?  In  a  simple  situation  a 
planner  may  be  able  to  get  all  the  alternatives  in  hand  and  collect 
enough  information  to  make  intelligent  decisions.  But  when  the  sit- 
uation begins  to  become  at  all  complex — long  before  anything  so 
formidable  as  a  government  is  considered — the  human  planners  will 
find  their  tasks  impossible.  In  large  organizations,  therefore,  it  is  un- 
avoidable that  much  of  the  apparent  direction  is  an  unplanned  re- 
sultant of  innumerable  individual  Plans. 

Some  shared  plans  are  temporary,  one-shot  affairs,  whereas 
others  are  recurrent  and  relatively  enduring.  The  plan  to  put  new 
swings  on  the  playground  is  nonrecurrent;  it  will  be  discarded  as 
soon  as  it  has  been  executed.  On  the  other  hand,  most  business  or- 
ganizations perform  the  same  task  over  and  over,  repeatedly.  A  man- 
ufacturer continually  buys  raw  materials,  converts  them  into  a  fin- 
ished product,  and  tties  to  sell  the  product  at  a  profit.  The  plan  is  not 
discarded  after  it  is  once  successfully  performed.  There  is  a  conse- 
quent permanence  to  the  various  subplans  of  these  on-going  enter- 
prises, and  people  have  time  to  acquire  special  skills  and  special 
knowledge  about  particular  parts  of  the  enterprise.  The  division  of 
labor  and  of  responsibility  that  is  possible  and  efficient  under  these 
circumstances  defines  a  set  of  social  roles.  The  concept  of  role  is 

The  Integration  of  Plans  ■  99 


indispensable  to  the  sociologist  and  the  social  psychologist  when  they 
attempt  to  understand  relatively  complicated  kinds  of  human  con- 
duct. We  will  not  survey  role  theory  here,  but  merely  comment  in 
passing  that  a  person's  role  in  any  group  should  be  defined  in  terms 
of  the  Plans  that  he  is  expected  to  execute  in  that  group.  ("Role"  is 
one  of  those  wonderful  concepts  apparently  able  to  tolerate  any  num- 
ber of  alternative  definitions,  so  one  more  should  cause  no  trouble.) 
Each  of  us  plays  numerous  roles  in  different  groups,  and  the  majority 
of  the  Plans  we  individually  execute  have  their  origins  in  our  social 
commitments. 

Social  planning  provides  an  interesting  area  to  study  the  nature 
of  plans  and  their  execution.  In  the  first  place,  social  plans  are  inter- 
esting because  they  are  the  source  of  so  much  of  our  individual  ac- 
tivity. And,  in  the  second  place,  shared  plans  are  such  simon-pure 
examples.  That  is  to  say,  human  institutions  exist  primarily  for  the 
purpose  of  executing  plans  that  their  members,  as  individuals,  would 
be  unable  or  unwilling  to  execute.  When  the  plans  that  form  their 
raison  d'etre  are  taken  away — finished,  frustrated,  outlawed,  out- 
grovsm,  completed,  whatever — the  group  may  disband.  Sometimes 
they  may  hold  reunions  to  swim  in  an  ocean  of  emotion,  but  then 
they  have  become  social  groups  with  corresponding  changes  in  the 
plans  they  execute.  But  many  planless  groups  disappear  and  are  never 
heard  from  again.  In  this  respect  groups  are  like  computers,  90  per- 
cent plan  and  10  percent  image.  Individuals,  on  the  other  hand  are 
about  75  percent  Image  and  25  percent  Plan.- 

Still  a  third  source  of  interest  in  shared  plans  is  their  easy  ac- 
cessibility. A  shared  plan  must  be  communicated  to  the  members  of 
the  group  and  hence  it  can  also  be  communicated  to  a  scientific  ob- 
server. In  dealing  with  the  privately  planned  actions  of  an  individual 
there  may  be  constant  uncertainty  about  the  Plan  that  he  is  following, 
since  he  may  be  unable  or  unwilling  to  disclose  it.  In  the  social  con- 
text, however,  the  Plan  that  must  be  executed  by  an  individual  is 
often  prescribed  in  great  detail  because  an  attempt  has  been  made  to 
obtain  optimal,  not  just  satisfactory,  performance  from  him.  In  that 
case  a  variety  of  interesting  problems  can  arise. 

-  These  percentages  are  reliable  to  no  decimal  places,  based  as  they  are  on 
no  figures  more  quantitative  than  a  figure  of  speech. 

100  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


Finally,  public  plans  are  interesting  because  they  are  often  so 
terribly  important.  They  are  important  for  the  social  units  that  exe- 
cute them.  Survival  may  hang  in  the  balance.  And  they  are  important 
to  the  individuals  who  participate  in  their  execution,  since  they  deter- 
mine many  of  the  particular  opportunities,  accomplishments,  and 
frustrations  that  will  shape  the  person's  life. 

The  present  authors  are  convinced  that  one  of  the  most  signif- 
icant arenas  for  the  development  and  exploitation  of  a  science  of  hu- 
man planning  is  provided  by  the  shared  plans  incorporated  in  nearly 
every  human  institution.  Indeed,  we  think  we  perceive  the  develop- 
ment of  such  a  science  in  the  field  of  business  administration.  March 
and  Simon  have  viewed  this  work  through  opinions  that  are  attractive 
to  us.^  In  the  event  that  anyone  should  mistakenly  assume  that  the 
science  of  administration  will  be  a  simple,  obvious  system  based  on 
two  or  three  axioms  and  intelligible  to  every  successful  businessman, 
we  invite  him  to  examine  the  hst  of  206  variables,  all  relevant  and 
important,  that  March  and  Simon  require.  In  so  complex  a  wonder- 
land we  are  grateful  to  be  able  to  refer  to  the  work  of  others. 

The  integration  and  coordination  of  plans,  both  individually  and 
socially,  is  an  important  aspect  of  the  general  problem  of  planning. 
We  should  not  leave  the  topic  without  first  pointing  out  the  signifi- 
cance of  clocks  and  calendars  for  coordination.  Both  space  and  time 
enter  into  our  Plans  in  pervasive  ways.*  Spatial  considerations  are 
obviously  important  because  activities  that  we  intend  to  pursue  so 
often  have  characteristic  places  where  they  are  feasible  and/or  rele- 
vant. Temporal  considerations  are  slightly  more  subtle,  perhaps.  If 
we  had  only  a  single  Plan  to  consider,  there  might  be  little  need  to 
worry  about  time;  the  execution  of  the  Plan  could  take  whatever 
length  of  time  it  required.  But  when  Plans  compete,  it  is  our  time  that 
they  compete  for.  We  must  establish  rules  concerning  priorities,  rules 
about  when  a  Plan  can  be  pursued  and  how  long  before  it  must  be 
dropped,  either  temporarily  or  permanently,  for  the  execution  of  a 

3  James  G.  March  and  Herbert  A.  Simon,  Organizations  (New  York:  Wiley, 
1958).  We  should  warn  the  reader  that  what  we  speak  of  here  as  a  Plan  is  re- 
ferred to  by  March  and  Simon  as  a  program,  and  what  they  refer  to  as  planning 
is  only  a  part  of  what  we  would  include  in  the  complete  process  of  constructing, 
coordinating,  and  executing  Plans. 

*  See  Edward  T.  Hall,  The  Silent  Language  (New  York:  Doubleday,  1959), 
for  a  comparison  of  our  uses  of  time  and  space  with  their  uses  in  other  cultures. 

The  Integrativn  of  Plans  ■   loi 


more  important  Plan.  When  we  attempt  to  coordinate  our  Plans  with 
the  Plans  of  others,  the  clock  comes  into  its  own  as  the  petty  dictator 
of  our  lives.  Criteria  of  space  and  time  must  therefore  be  built  into 
the  test  phases  of  almost  every  Plan  to  determine  where  and  when 
any  Plan  will  be  relevant  and  feasible.  Time  and  space,  clocks  and 
keys,  become  dimensions  of  everything  we  do. 

Americans,  we  are  told,  are  the  most  diligent  servants  of  time. 

The  American  never  questions  the  fact  that  time  should  be 
planned  and  future  events  fitted  into  a  schedule.  He  thinks  that 
people  should  look  forward  to  the  future  and  not  dwell  too 
much  on  the  past.  His  future  is  not  very  far  ahead  of  him.  Re- 
sults must  be  obtained  in  the  foreseeable  future — one  or  two 
years,  or,  at  the  most,  five  or  ten.  Promises  to  meet  deadlines 
and  appointments  are  taken  very  seriously.  There  are  real  penal- 
ties for  being  late  and  for  not  keeping  commitments  in  time. 
From  this  it  can  be  surmised  that  the  American  thinks  it  is 
natural  to  quantify  time.  To  fail  to  do  so  is  unthinkable.  The 
American  specifies  how  much  time  it  will  require  to  do  every- 
thing.^ 

Such  is  the  verdict  of  an  anthropologist.  These  words  should  re- 
mind us  that  planning  may  be  a  purely  American  characteristic,  not 
a  universally  human  one.  But,  useful  as  such  warnings  are,  we  have 
decided  to  ignore  this  one.  Planning  is  a  function  we  have  seen  span 
whatever  boundaries  separate  Americans  from  the  digger  wasp  and 
the  computing  machine.  It  is  not  the  fact  that  Americans  plan  that 
makes  them  different  from  their  fellow  men.  It  is  the  way  Americans 
plan  and,  particularly,  the  respect  Americans  show  for  their  shared 
plans  that  distinguish  them  from  men  who  live  in  other  cultures.  In 
its  broader  aspects,  we  would  argue,  planning  is  not  an  American 
idiosyncracy.  It  is  an  indispensable  aspect  of  the  human  mind. 

Nonetheless,  a  cautious  reader  should  not  overlook  the  Ameri- 
can origins  of  this  book  on  the  psychology  of  Plans. 

5  Ibid.,  pp.  172-173.  Essentially  the  same  opinion  of  the  temporal  aspects  of 
American  life  was  reached  by  Kurt  Lewin  (see  Resolving  Social  Conflicts  [New 
York:  Harper,  1948],  pp.  13-14)  and  by  Florence  Kluckhohn  (see  Dominant  and 
variant  value  orientations,  in  C.  Kluckhohn,  H.  A.  Murray,  and  D.  M.  Schneider, 
Personality  in  Nature,  Society,  and  Culture,  2nd  edition  [New  York:  Knopf,  1955], 
Chapter  21,  pp.  342-357). 


102  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


CHAPTER  8 


RELINQUISHING 
THE   PLAN 


The  discussion  of  public  plans  in  the  preceding  chapter  ignores 
rather  flagrantly  a  crucial  problem  of  good  administration :  How  do 
you  persuade  people  to  give  up  a  segment  of  their  lives  in  order  to  ex- 
ecute the  common  plan?  Regular  cash  payments  have  proved  to  be  a 
satisfactory  method  in  our  culture,  but  even  that  will  usually  not 
suffice  to  make  a  person  execute  the  public  plan  with  all  the  enthu- 
siasm and  intelUgence  he  would  lavish  upon  a  Plan  of  his  own.  The 
problem  of  persuasion  (or,  in  other  contexts,  seduction)  has  long 
fascinated  some  of  our  greatest  psychologists. 

In  view  of  the  difficulties  so  commonly  encountered  in  persuad- 
ing other  people  to  execute  our  plans,  it  is  quite  significant  to  note 
that  there  is  one  situation  where  another  person  becomes  fanatically 
intent  on  doing  what  we  tell  him.  He  becomes  so  cooperative,  in  fact, 
that  it  is  a  full-time  job  just  to  keep  him  from  hurting  himself  in  our 
interests.  The  situation  is,  of  course,  hypnosis. 

One  of  the  seven  wonders  of  psychology  is  that  so  striking  a 
phenomenon  as  hypnosis  has  been  neglected.   Some  psychologists 

Relinquishing  the  Plan  ■   103 


literally  do  not  believe  in  it,  but  consider  it  a  hoax,  an  act  put  on  by  a 
cooperative  stooge.  The  majority  of  psychologists  admit  that  hyp- 
nosis is  an  actual  phenomenon,  but  they  have  not  worked  with  it  and 
do  not  quite  trust  anyone  who  has.  Unfortunately,  in  spite  of  its  re- 
markable effects,  few  psychologists  have  any  very  good  idea  what 
hypnosis  is  or  what  to  use  it  for.  Two  of  the  present  authors  have 
shared  this  suspicious  attitude,  and  thus  arrive  at  the  task  of  writing 
on  the  subject  with  an  embarrassing  lack  of  firsthand  experience. 
It  is  important  to  say  at  the  outset,  therefore,  that  considerable  reli- 
ance has  been  placed  on  the  excellence  of  a  recent  review  by  Weitzen- 
hoffer.^  His  monograph  defines  the  topic  for  the  purposes  of  the  pres- 
ent discussion. 

Let  us  begin  with  a  flat-footed  announcement  of  what  the  source 
of  hypnotic  phenomena  must  be  and  then  proceed  to  examine  some 
of  the  reported  phenomena  in  detail.  The  present  conception  of  hyp- 
nosis is  quite  simple.  It  is  based  on  a  naive  faith  that  the  subject 
means  what  he  says  when  he  teUs  us  that  he  surrenders  his  wdll  to 
the  hypnotist.  Is  there  any  reason  to  doubt  him?  It  is  just  as  good  a 
theory  as  any  of  the  others  that  have  been  proposed. 

The  trouble  with  such  a  theory,  of  course,  is  that  no  one  knows 
what  the  will  is,  so  we  are  scarcely  any  better  off  than  before.  The 
only  effect  is  to  shift  the  focus  of  the  difficulty.  Now  the  trouble  is  not 
that  we  lack  a  good  theory  of  hypnosis,  but  that  we  lack  a  good  theory 
of  the  will.  And  that  is  the  point  at  which  the  arguments  of  the  present 
book  become  relevant. 

Suppose  that  under  ordinary  conditions  a  waking  person  is  con- 
stantly constructing  and  revising  more  or  less  coherent  Plans  for  his 
own  behavior.  Suppose  that  some  of  these  Plans  are  visualized,  some 
are  felt  kinesthetically,  etc.,  but  the  more  elaborate  voluntary  Plans 
involve  a  self-conscious  exploitation  of  language.  Inner  speech  is  the 
kind  of  stuff  our  wills  are  made  of.  When  we  will  to  do  something, 
we  may  imagine  doing  it  and  we  repeat  our  verbal  command  to  our- 
selves, subvocally,  as  we  concentrate  on  the  task.  It  is  a  familiar  fact, 
emphasized  by  nearly  aU  behavioristic  psychologists  since  J.  B.  Wat- 
son, that  most  of  our  planned  activity  is  represented  subjectively 

iAndr6  M.  WeitzenhofFer,  General  Techniques  of  Hypnotism  (New  York: 
Gnine  and  Stratton,  1957). 

104  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


as  listening  to  ourselves  talk.  The  hypnotized  person  is  not  really  do- 
ing anything  different,  with  this  exception :  the  voice  he  Ustens  to  for 
his  Plan  is  not  his  own,  but  the  hypnotist's.  The  subject  gives  up  his 
inner  speech  to  the  hypnotist. 

It  is  not  sufficient  to  say  merely  that  a  hypnotized  subject  is 
listening  to  Plans  formulated  for  him  by  the  hypnotist.  Any  person 
watching  the  pair  of  them  at  work  would  also  be  listening  to  the  same 
Plans  but  would  not  feel  the  same  compulsion  to  carry  them  out. 
What  is  the  difference  between  normal  listening  and  hypnotized  hs- 
tening? 

It  is  assumed  that  a  waking  person  hears  the  suggested  Plans 
and  then  either  incorporates  them  or  rejects  them  in  the  planning  he 
is  doing  for  himself.  But  a  hypnotized  subject  has  stopped  making  his 
own  Plans,  and  therefore  there  can  be  no  question  of  coordination,  no 
possible  translation  from  the  hypnotist's  version  to  his  own.  The  hyp- 
notist's version  of  the  Plan  is  the  only  one  he  has,  and  so  he  executes 
it.  The  basic  assumption  here,  as  in  other  chapters,  is  that  he  must 
execute  some  Plan  all  the  time.  Of  course,  the  subject  is  capable  of 
elaborating  the  Plan  that  the  hypnotist  gives  him,  just  as  he  would 
normally  supply  the  tactics  to  elaborate  some  strategy  of  his  own. 
But  the  hypnotist's  Plan  takes  precedence  over  any  Plans  of  his  own. 

So  the  question  becomes :  How  does  a  person  stop  making  Plans 
for  himself?  This  is  something  each  of  us  accomplishes  every  night 
of  our  lives  when  we  fall  asleep.  Stopping  is  not  always  easy,  as  any- 
one who  has  suffered  from  insomnia  will  attest,  but  most  of  us  man- 
age to  do  it  without  too  much  difficulty.  It  would  be  natural  to  sup- 
pose that  the  same  procedure  would  work  when  a  person  wanted  to 
turn  off  his  own  inner  speech  in  order  to  become  hypnotized.  He 
would  try  to  create  the  same  conditions  under  which  he  usually  falls 
asleep.  He  would  make  the  room  dark  and  quiet.  He  would  sit  or  lie 
down  in  a  relaxed,  comfortable  position.  (These  conditions  which  we 
consider  necessary  for  sleep  are  not  universally  required.  It  would  be 
interesting  to  see  if  cultural  differences  in  sleeping  habits  were  cor- 
related with  differences  in  the  induction  of  hypnosis.  ^  The  person 
might  try  to  stop  thinking  about  his  own  Plans  by  giving  his  inner- 
speech  machine  something  dull  and  stupid  to  do,  like  counting  sheep 
or  concentrating  on  some  small  detail.  He  would  try  to  discourage 

Relinquishing  the  Plan  "105 


himself  from  thinking  fitfully  of  what  is  going  to  happen  next,  what 
people  will  think  of  him,  how  long  he  has  been  here,  where  he  is  in 
relation  to  other  objects  in  the  room,  etc.  He  would,  in  short,  try  to 
relax  and  stop  talking  to  himself.  And  that  is  exactly  what  the  stand- 
ard hypnotic  procedures  ask  him  to  do.  In  hypnosis,  however,  he  does 
not  fall  asleep,  because  he  finds  that  there  is  a  substitute  Plan  pro- 
vided by  the  operator's  voice,  and  so  the  operator's  Plans  begin  to  be 
played  out  on  the  subject's  nervous  system  as  though  they  were  his 
own. 

An  alternative  procedure  for  inducing  hypnosis  is  for  the  oper- 
ator to  give  the  subject  difficult  and  conflicting  instructions  at  a 
fairly  rapid  rate,  so  that  the  subject's  own  planner  becomes  confused. 
Instead  of  coasting  to  a  halt,  it  becomes  overloaded  and  quits.  In  this 
crisis  the  Plans  offered  by  the  hypnotist  may  be  accepted  as  a  wel- 
come relief  from  confusion.  This  technique,  however,  requires  more 
skill  than  do  the  standard  methods. 

Undoubtedly  there  is  more  to  the  process  of  inducing  hypnosis 
than  this  description  includes,  otherwise  every  student  who  became 
confused  or  fell  asleep  during  a  lecture  would  find  himself  hypno- 
tized. In  order  to  substitute  his  voice  for  the  person's  own,  a  hypnotist 
must  provide  Plans,  not  just  comments  or  descriptive  statements, 
and  these  Plans  should  be  coordinated  as  well  as  possible  with  the 
subject's  perceptions  and  movements  in  order  to  facilitate  the  illusion 
that  they  are  coming  from  within,  rather  than  from  another  person. 
Many  of  the  tricks  that  good  hypnotists  use  can  be  understood  in  this 
light. 

It  should  be  fairly  obvious  by  now  that  speech  plays  a  critical 
role  in  this  conception  of  hypnosis  and  that  it  might  be  quite  disturb- 
ing to  these  ideas  if  a  subject  in  a  deep  trance  were  fluent  verbally. 
On  this  interesting  point  the  present  authors  are  handicapped  by  inex- 
perience and  must  rely  on  Weitzenhoffer.  First,  in  describing  what  a 
hypnotized  person  looks  like  he  says : 

The  subject  has  a  strong  disinclination  to  talk.  It  is  often 
necessary  to  address  him  several  times  before  obtaining  an 
answer.  Sometimes  it  is  necessary  to  order  him  to  answer  ques- 
tions. Even  then  the  subject  often  favors  nods  and  shakes  of 
the  head  over  words.  When  conversation  of  a  sort  has  been  es- 

io6  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


tablished,  the  subject  is  usually  found  to  show  a  lack  of  spon- 
taneity and  initiative.  His  speech  tends  to  be  low  in  volume  and 
rather  flat  and  expressionless,  he  mumbles  his  answers  and 
must  be  ordered  to  speak  louder  and  more  distinctly.  At  other 
times  the  speech  of  the  subject  can  be  best  described  as 
"thick."  - 

Later,  in  discussing  the  various  phenomena  that  can  be  demonstrated 
under  hypnosis,  Weitzenhoffer  raises  the  problem  of  enabling  a 
hypnotized  subject  to  talk  without  awakening.  He  says : 

Many  hypnotized  subjects  will  readily  answer  questions, 
repeat  suggestions  and  even  hold  complex  conversations,  with- 
out coming  out  of  the  trance.  However,  some  wake  up  or  their 
trance  state  lightens  considerably,  the  minute  they  are  made  to 
talk.  This  often  can  be  prevented  by  the  simple  expedient  of  giv- 
ing suggestions,  prior  to  making  the  subject  talk,  to  the  effect 
that,  although  he  is  deeply  asleep,  he  will  be  able  to  hear  your 
voice  distinctly,  to  talk  to  you  without  awakening  and  to  answer 
all  of  your  questions.  Then  ask  him  a  few  simple  questions 
such  as  his  age,  his  name,  etc.,  and  give  further  suggestions  to 
the  effect  that  he  can  do  this  wdthout  waking.  This  procedure  is 
particularly  important  of  course  in  therapeutic  work,  where  anxi- 
ety-provoking questions  must  be  asked  sooner  or  later.  It  is 
then  that  the  subject  or  patient  is  most  likely  to  become  dehyp- 
notized.  In  therapy  a  much  longer  period  should  be  spent  asking 
relatively  innocuous  questions,  and  slowly  moving  to  anxiety- 
provoking  questions.^ 

The  fact  that  many  hypnotized  subjects  hold  complex  conversations  is 
puzzling,  although  various  ad  hoc  explanations  could  be  devised.  If 
the  present  view  has  any  merit,  the  subject's  speech  poses  an  impor- 
tant problem  for  further  study.  Is  it  possible  for  him  to  use  language 
in  a  planning  function  while  he  is  in  the  trance?  On  the  whole,  these 
descriptions  are  approximately  what  one  would  expect  if  the  subject 
had  turned  off  his  inner  speech  when  he  stopped  making  his  own 
Plans.  Moreover,  it  seems  likely  that  the  subject's  lack  of  facial  ex- 
pressions is  also  a  symptom  of  his  reluctance  to  communicate. 

Obviously,  a  hypnotized  subject  does  not  relinquish  all  his  ca- 
pacity for  planning.  It  is  still  necessary  for  him  to  supply  tactics  for 

2  Ibid.,  p.  211. 

3  Ibid.,  p.  353. 

Relinquishing  the  Plan  ■   107 


executing  the  strategy  laid  down  by  the  hypnotist.  K  his  cessation  of 
planning  were  to  extend  to  the  point  where  he  could  not  even  work  out 
the  step-by-step  details  of  the  hypnotist's  Plans,  then  we  would  expect 
to  find  him  in  a  state  of  stupor,  or  torpor,  from  which  he  could  not  be 
stirred.  Indeed,  such  states  have  been  observed  and  are  called  vari- 
ously "animal  hypnotism,"  the  "Braid  effect,"  the  "plenary  trance," 
etc.  Differences  among  these  various  states  of  immobilization  are 
subtle  and  will  not  be  discussed  here.  It  is  sufficient  to  know  that  im- 
mobilization can  occur,  as  though  the  termination  of  self-planning 
were  really  complete.  It  should  also  be  noted  that  some  subjects  do 
not  respond  by  acting  out  suggestions  when  they  are  hypnotized, 
but  still  have  very  strong  and  vivid  hallucinations  which  they  observe 
more  or  less  passively.  Those  subjects  who  sit  passively  would  seem 
to  require  fewer  resources  for  self -planning  than  subjects  who  begin 
to  act  as  if  their  hallucinations  were  true  perceptions. 

It  is  generally  recognized  that  hypnotic  subjects  differ  wddely  in 
the  degree  of  hypnotism  they  can  achieve.  Several  scaling  proce- 
dures have  been  developed  for  measuring  the  depth  of  hypnosis,  and 
they  seem  to  have  fairly  high  reliability.  It  is  necessary  to  give  some 
account  of  these  different  levels  in  terms  of  the  point  of  view  taken 
here. 

In  order  to  account  for  the  levels  of  hypnosis,  let  us  assume  that 
there  are  several  different  kinds  of  Plans  that  are  normally  executed 
in  the  waking  state  and  that  these  can,  with  some  small  degree  of  in- 
dependence, be  given  up  individually.  Most  important,  of  course,  is 
the  kind  of  planning  by  inner  speech  that  sets  the  voluntary  strategy 
for  so  much  that  we  do.  It  is  the  capture  of  this  planning  function 
that  marks  the  passage  of  a  subject  into  a  trance  state.  But  there  must 
be  still  other  planning  functions  that  are  performed  more  or  less  auto- 
matically as  a  kind  of  "housekeeping."  They  are,  so  to  speak,  parts  of 
every  Plan  we  make,  and  they  serve  to  settle  various  details  once  and 
for  all  without  the  necessity  for  fresh  decisions  on  each  new  Plan. 
These  general-purpose  routines  will  become  clearer  from  a  few  sam- 
ples. 

The  normally  awake  person  must  have  a  more  or  less  involun- 
tary mechanism  that  takes  care  of  his  bodily  posture,  his  tonus,  his 
orientation  in  space.  If  the  Plan  containing  these  instructions  were 

io8  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


terminated,  the  subject  would  simply  collapse.  Since  the  tendency  for 
subjects  to  collapse  when  they  are  told  to  relax  is  so  great,  the  hyp- 
notist must  give  them  a  special  command  not  to  fall  out  of  their 
chairs.  He  says,  in  short,  what  the  person  would  say  to  himself:  keep 
the  posture-plan  working. 

Another  kind  of  Plan  that  will  normally  be  executed  more  or  less 
automatically  is  the  tagging  of  our  experience  with  verbal  labels  and 
the  storing  of  it  in  memory.  The  labels  serve  the  same  function  as  do 
addresses  in  a  calculating  machine.  When  the  label  is  recalled  it  is 
possible  to  go  to  that  address  and  find  the  record  of  the  experience. 
Now,  it  is  possible  to  cripple  this  part  of  the  machinery  in  two  obvious 
ways,  one  in  terms  of  storage  and  the  other  in  terms  of  retrieval  pro- 
cedures. The  amnesias  that  are  so  easily  produced  in  hypnosis,  and 
which  frequently  occur  spontaneously  in  deep  trances,  would  seem 
to  involve  the  suspension  of  those  Plans  that  are  necessary  in  order 
to  store  or  retrieve  information. 

Some  of  the  most  dramatic  effects  in  hypnosis,  however,  would 
seem  to  result  from  the  suspension  of  "stop-rules."  Any  device  that  is 
supposed  to  follow  literally  a  given  program  of  instructions  must  be 
told  under  what  conditions  it  should  begin  and  under  what  conditions 
it  should  give  up.  A  waking  person  who  finds  some  planned  action  im- 
possible will  quickly  stop  and  devise  an  alternative  Plan.  A  hypno- 
tized subject  cannot  do  this  and  so  may  struggle  with  increasing 
tension,  single-mindedly  intent  on  executing  the  only  Plan  the  hypno- 
tist has  provided.  One  of  the  most  common  stop-rules,  no  doubt,  con- 
cerns how  much  pain  we  are  willing  to  tolerate  before  we  abandon 
a  particularly  painful  Plan.  Presumably,  the  TOTE  units  must 
normally  include  somewhere  in  their  test  phase  an  implicit  rule  say- 
ing, "If  the  pain  exceeds  an  amount  X,  stop  and  transfer  control  to 
Y."  We  think  the  anesthesias  that  are  so  familiar  a  feature  of  hypno- 
sis can  be  understood  as  a  result  of  the  omission  of  these  tests  when 
the  subject  is  no  longer  constructing  his  own  Plans. 

In  this  connection  it  may  be  relevant  to  recall  an  incident  re- 
lated by  a  psychologist  who  had  recently  gone  through  basic  training 
in  the  Army.  He  was  told  to  run,  so  he  and  the  other  trainees  began 
running.  After  going  on  as  long  as  he  could  he  finally  stopped,  puffing, 
"1  can't  go  on  any  more."  At  this  point  he  was  ordered  to  continue 

Relinquishing  the  Plan  "109 


running  until  he  was  told  to  stop  or  until  he  fell  on  his  face.  If  he 
fell,  there  was  a  doctor  who  would  immediately  take  care  of  him.  And 
so  he  began  running  again.  After  a  short  period  he  lost  all  voluntary 
control.  He  looked  down  and  saw  somebody's  legs  pumping  away  un- 
der him  and  was  mildly  surprised  to  notice  that  they  were  attached  to 
his  own  body.  He  had  learned  that  his  "physiological  limit"  was  a 
good  deal  further  on  than  he  would  voluntarily  have  set  it.  And  he 
had  learned  that  it  was  safe  to  relinquish  to  his  officers  the  task  of 
determining  what  was  humanly  possible. 

What  we  accept  as  the  limits  of  human  endurance  are  usually 
well  on  the  safe  side  of  irreversible  tissue  damage.  Under  hypnosis, 
when  the  stop-for-pain  rule  can  be  relaxed  or  even  eliminated,  it  is 
possible  to  bear  children,  endure  surgery,  etc.,  without  any  apparent 
pain.  The  change  in  the  stop-rule,  plus  the  amnesia  for  the  painful 
situation,  provide  all  the  psychological  protection  that  can  be 
derived  from  any  anesthetic. 

It  is  also  hkely  that  stop-rules  can  be  changed  in  the  opposite 
direction,  as  weU.  The  suggestions  that  the  subject  cannot  move  cer- 
tain parts  of  his  body  would  seem  to  be  exactly  the  reverse  of  the  sug- 
gestions that  he  can  continue  to  move  them  after  he  would  normally 
have  stopped. 

Still  another  kind  of  ancillary  Plan  that  can  be  suspended  in- 
volves perceptual  reality-testing.  There  has  been  much  written  by 
psychologists  about  how  a  person  can  tell  his  perceptual  images  from 
his  imaginative  images.  By  and  large,  criteria  of  vividness  have  not 
proved  satisfactory.*  The  basic  difference  between  the  two  types  of 
images  concerns  the  conditions  under  which  they  wall  change.  The 
imaginative  image  can  be  altered  by  an  act  of  will,  by  creating  a  Plan 
for  changing  the  image  into  something  else  and  then  executing  the 
Plan.  Such  subjective  Plans  normally  have  remarkably  little  effect  on 
perceptual  images.  However,  perceptual  images  can  usually  be 
modified  by  moving  or  adjusting  the  receptor  organs  themselves.  Thus 
it  seems  likely  that  as  children  we  must  all  learn  a  set  of  subplans  for 
testing  the  plasticity  of  our  images,  for  distinguishing  between 
imagination  and  perception.  These  are  normally  included  as  part  of 

*  See,  for  example,  C.  W.  Perky,  An  experimental  study  of  imagination, 
American  Journal  of  Psychology,  1910,  21,  422—452.  She  demonstrated  rather 
conclusively  that  images  cannot  be  distinguished  from  perceptions  on  purely 
introspective  grounds. 

no  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


the  test  phase  of  all  our  TOTE  units.  In  hypnosis,  however,  these 
reality-testing  Plans  can  be  temporarily  suspended  so  that  the  subject 
has  vivid  hallucinations  which  he  is  unwilling  to  admit  are  not  true 
perceptions.  This  stage  of  visual  hallucinations  should  accompany 
the  blank  stare  (eye  movements  not  used  to  test  the  image)  that  is 
so  characteristic  of  the  deep  hypnotic  trance. 

Perhaps  grammatical  habits  should  also  be  put  among  the  ancil- 
lary Plans.  That  is  to  say,  the  rules  of  formation  and  transformation 
of  sentences  may  be  so  thoroughly  habitual  that  they  can  be  retained 
even  when  the  subject  has  given  up  his  usual,  spontaneous  inner 
speech  and  is  using  his  grammatical  habits  merely  to  implement  and 
elaborate  Plans  provided  by  a  hypnotist.  Grammatical  skills  are  dis- 
cussed more  fully  in  Chapter  11. 

A  variety  of  other  hypnotic  phenomena  seem  to  us  to  be  intelligi- 
ble in  these  terms,  for  example :  ( 1 )  When  a  hypnotist  stops  talking 
to  his  subject  we  should  expect  to  see  the  subject  lapse  into  quiet  im- 
mobility, or  fall  asleep,  or  become  dehypnotized.  (2)  Posthypnotic 
suggestions  are  Plans — made  well  in  advance  for  the  subject  by 
the  hypnotist  and  carried  unconsciously  until  the  time  when  the  test 
phase  is  satisfied  and  the  Plan  is  executed.  (3)  Since  the  subject  is 
awake,  we  would  expect  his  brain  waves  to  be  like  those  of  waking 
people.  (4)  The  subject  must  trust  the  hypnotist,  but  no  kind  of  love 
or  transference  situation  is  necessary  to  establish  the  phenomenon. 
(5)  Any  drugs  that  would  interfere  with  speech  should  make  a  person 
easier  to  hypnotize,  which  seems  to  be  the  case.  Thus  we  can  proceed 
through  a  list  of  phenomena  that  are  characteristic  of  hypnosis  with- 
out finding  any  that  seem  to  contradict  the  relatively  simple  hypothe- 
sis we  have  advanced. 

The  major  implication  of  this  conception  of  hypnosis  is  not  so 
much  the  explanation  provided  for  hypnotic  phenomena  as  it  is  the 
intimate  connections  that  are  implied  among  volition,  inner  speech, 
and  normal,  waking  consciousness.  It  is  not  too  improbable,  we 
feel,  that  consciousness  is  in  some  essential  way  the  capacity  to 
make  one's  own  Plans  and  that  volition  is  the  capacity  to  execute 
them.  If  so,  then  language,  by  extending  man's  ability  to  Plan,  must 
tremendously  expand  his  consciousness  of  himself  and  his  world 
over  that  available  to,  for  instance,  a  chimpanzee. 

One  virtue  of  this  account  is  that  it  makes  it  obvious  why  a  per- 

Relinquishing  the  Plan  ■    1 1 1 


son  cannot  be  hypnotized  "against  his  will"  and  why  he  can  be  un- 
hypnotized  so  quickly  when  the  hypnotist  tells  him  to  be.  Is  there  any 
way  to  gain  similar  control  over  him  when  he  is  unwOling?  Is  there 
some  way  that  a  person's  resistance  could  be  overcome,  that  he 
could  be  forced  to  relinquish  the  planning  function  to  another  per- 
son? The  question  calls  to  mind  the  notorious  "brain-washing,"  or 
"thought  control,"  procedures  that  have  been  used  with  military  and 
political  prisoners.  The  first  step,  presumably,  would  be  to  make  the 
person  stop  planning  for  himself.  This  might  be  achieved  by  deliber- 
ately frustrating  every  self-made  Plan  that  he  tries  to  execute,  even 
the  Plans  dealing  with  his  most  personal  bodily  functions.  The  object 
is  to  make  him  beheve  that  only  the  Plans  originating  from  his  captor 
can  be  executed.  He  may  be  set  the  task  of  confessing,  but  given  no 
inkling  of  what  it  is  that  he  must  confess.  Whatever  he  confesses  will 
be  wrong,  or  insufficient.  Through  all  of  this  frustration  of  every  self- 
made  Plan,  however,  the  prisoner  hears  repeatedly  a  strong,  clear 
Plan  offered  by  the  thought  reformer  and  corresponding  to  the  re- 
former's own  ideology.  Destroying  one  Plan  is  only  the  prelude  to 
building  up  another.  Of  course,  a  prisoner  may  be  more  than  willing 
to  adopt  the  new  Plan  in  order  to  avoid  the  terror  and  humiliation 
of  his  imprisonment,  but  if  he  does  not  have  an  Image  that  will  sup- 
port the  elaboration  of  the  new  Plan,  his  willingness  is  of  no  avail. 
Along  with  the  surrender  of  his  planning  function,  therefore,  the  sub- 
ject must  develop  a  new  set  of  concepts.  These,  too,  are  presented 
endlessly  in  ways  he  cannot  ignore. 

It  is  amazing  that  such  methods  could  ever  fail,  that  man  who  can 
be  controlled  so  completely  by  other  people  when  he  is  willing 
should  be  so  stubborn  when  he  is  unwilling.  Until  psychologists 
achieve  a  clear  understanding  of  what  "willingness"  consists  of,  how- 
ever, amazement  can  be  the  only  appropriate  attitude.  Whatever  else, 
it  is  clear  that  to  find  oneself  without  any  Plan  at  all  is  a  serious 
matter.  Interpreted  literally,  it  is  impossible,  for  complete  planless- 
ness  must  be  equivalent  to  death.  For  example,  there  are  well- 
documented  cases  of  primitive  people  who  have  violated  some  taboo, 
have  been  isolated  by  their  tribe,  and  have  died  shortly  thereafter. 
It  does  not  seem  to  be  an  exaggeration  to  say  these  people  die  of  plan- 
lessness.  If  such  a  diagnosis  seems  extravagant,  at  least  it  enables  us 

112  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


to  understand  what  a  physician  is  talking  about  when  he  says  a 
patient  died  because  "he  lost  his  will  to  Uve."  Deep  sleep,  anesthesia, 
concussion,  the  plenary  trance  of  hypnosis — these  are  probably  as 
close  to  complete  planlessness  as  we  can  ever  get.  The  catatonic  who 
sits  immobile  is  a  man  without  action,  but  he  is  not  a  man  without 
Plans.  His  immobility  is  itself  a  part  of  the  Plan  he  is  executing. 

Nevertheless,  patients  do  come  to  the  psychiatrist  vdth  the  com- 
plaint that  they  are  unable  to  decide  what  to  do,  that  they  feel  com- 
pletely planless.  This  is  one  of  the  two  large  categories  of  trouble  that 
will  make  people  seek  medical  help  for  their  psychological  ills.  When 
a  person  becomes  acutely  mentally  ill  his  presenting  complaints  are 
almost  always  one  of  two  kinds :  Either  ( 1 )  he  cannot  choose  between 
two  or  more  Plans  whose  execution  would  call  for  incompatible  ac- 
tions; such  problems  were  discussed  in  Chapter  7.  Or  (2)  the  Plans 
that  have  guided  his  actions  until  recently  are  no  longer  relevant  or 
feasible;  some  particular  facet  of  his  life  has  become  planless. 

How  can  it  happen  that  someone  finds  himself  suddenly  without 
any  Plans  for  dealing  with  an  important  segment  of  his  life?  Such  a 
symptom  might  be  a  result  of  brain  damage  produced,  say,  by  a 
series  of  small  strokes.  But  if,  as  is  usually  the  case,  the  person's 
brain  is  apparently  undamaged,  we  must  look  for  more  psychological 
origins.  Perhaps  the  complexities  and  ambiguities  involved  in  the 
situation  are  too  great  for  him  to  understand  or  to  tolerate,  and  his 
planning  mechanism  turns  itself  off  before  it  produces  anything  that 
could  be  executed.  Perhaps  he  was  living  largely  on  borrowed  Plans 
— Plans  determined  by  a  loved  one,  by  children,  by  the  boss — and 
the  source  of  these  Plans  is  suddenly  withdrav^m.  Or  perhaps  he 
completed  the  execution  of  his  Plans,  the  job  is  done,  and  he  is  ready 
to  die  but  can  only  retire.  Or  perhaps  some  haphazard  stroke  of  for- 
tune exploded  him  out  of  his  usual  rut  and  thrust  him  suddenly  into 
a  situation  for  which  he  is  totally  unprepared,  where  his  previous 
Plans  are  completely  useless. 

The  person  who  makes  his  life's  Plans  in  terms  of  concrete 
and  specific  objectives,  in  terms  of  "goals,"  invites  the  disaster  of 
planlessness.  If  the  goal  is  well  defined — to  earn  a  million  dollars, 
to  unify  the  Armed  Services,  to  climb  Mt.  Whatever — he  may  be 
frustrated  by  success  and  left  with  no  Plan  for  the  remainder  of  his 

Relinquishing  the  Plan  "113 


life.  Or  he  may  be  frustrated  by  failure,  by  the  exhaustion  of  every 
possible  Plan  he  can  devise  without  the  attainment  of  the  goal.  It  is 
not  necessary,  however,  to  organize  one's  Plans  in  terms  of  frozen 
and  brittle  terminal  states.  Unlike  good  problems  in  science  or  mathe- 
matics, successful  living  is  not  a  "well-defined  problem,"  and  attempts 
to  convert  it  into  a  well-defined  problem  by  selecting  explicit  goals 
and  subgoals  can  be  an  empty  deception.  As  Gordon  Allport  has 
pointed  out,  it  is  better  to  plan  toward  a  kind  of  continual  'Taecoming" 
than  toward  a  final  goal.^  The  problem  is  to  sustain  life,  to  formu- 
late enduring  Plans,  not  to  terminate  living  and  planning  as  if  they 
were  tasks  that  had  to  be  finished.  This  simple  point  has  been  over- 
looked by  many  psychologists  who  seem  to  take  it  for  granted  that  all 
behavior  must  be  oriented  toward  explicit  goals. 

Given  that  a  person  finds  himself  planless,  for  whatever  reasons, 
what  are  his  reactions?  Whenever  an  enduring  Plan — a  Plan  that  has 
guided  action  for  any  prolonged  period  of  the  person's  life — be- 
comes useless,  irrelevant,  or  not  feasible,  some  characteristic  reac- 
tions ensue:  they  are  pathological  only  in  the  extreme  case.  Plans  that 
are  intended  to  span  long  periods  of  time  build  up  large  "investments" 
of  special  habits  and  skills,  investments  that  might  be  lost  if  the  Plan 
is  never  executed  again.  Moreover,  the  realization  that  an  enduring 
Plan  must  be  changed  at  a  strategic  level  can  cause  a  considerable 
upheaval  in  the  person's  Image  as  well  as  in  his  Plans.  A  rule  that 
most  people  seem  to  learn,  probably  when  they  are  very  young,  is: 
When  in  the  execution  of  a  Plan  it  is  discovered  that  an  intended  sub- 
plan  is  not  relevant  or  is  not  feasible,  the  smallest  possible  substitu- 
tions of  alternative  tactical  subplans  are  to  be  attempted  first,  and  the 
change  in  strategy  is  to  be  postponed  as  long  as  possible.  Whatever 
the  mechanism,  if  the  person  becomes  planless  rather  suddenly, 
marked  mood  swings  are  apt  to  occur:  the  person  is  said  to  be- 
come "emotional."  The  activation  appears  to  result  directly  from  the 
suddenness  in  the  alteration  of  Plans;  the  interpretation  of  the  in- 
crease in  "emotion,"  that  is,  the  way  the  person  feels,  appears  more 
related  to  the  extent  to  which  the  Plans  are  pnmed,  that  is,  whether 
only  tactics  are  affected  or  entire  strategies  have  to  be  abandoned. 

^  Gordon  W.  Allport,  Becoming:  Basic  Considerations  for  a  Psychology  of 
Personality  (New  Haven:  Yale  University  Press,  1955). 

114   ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


One  possible  reaction  is  to  reinstate  the  old  Plan  in  spite  of  the 
fact  that  it  is  no  longer  relevant  or  feasible,  to  continue  to  develop  it, 
transform  it,  and  execute  it  despite  its  inadequacy.  In  its  most  ex- 
treme form,  this  is  the  paranoid  reaction.  The  person  may  go  through 
a  brief  stage  where  the  irrelevance  of  his  Plan  is  crystal  clear  to  him. 
Then  the  paranoid  transformation  sets  in.  This  transformation 
changes  whatever  part  of  the  Image  might  interfere  with  the  execu- 
tion of  the  Plan.  Paranoid  reactions,  if  the  Plans  are  not  obviously 
socially  destructive  and  are  not  too  obviously  irrelevant,  may  go  un- 
detected for  years.  A  paranoid  person  may  even  be  able  to  persuade 
others  that  his  Plans  are  feasible,  so  that  he  is  aided  in  their  execu- 
tion. 

A  second  possibility  is  to  hang  on  to  as  much  of  the  general 
strategy  as  possible  and  consider  making  revisions  only  in  the  tactical 
branches  of  the  Plan.  The  person  may  attempt  to  "act  out"  some  early 
situation,  letting  present  persons  symbolize  earlier  ones  and  attempt- 
ing to  impose  on  them  the  same  strategy  used  earlier,  except  for  nec- 
essary modifications  of  tactics.  In  more  severe  forms,  the  process 
may  be  characterized  as  schizophrenic.  A  sudden  extensive  abandon- 
ing of  tactics,  that  is,  the  pruning  of  a  plan,  seems  to  produce  emo- 
tional excitation  that,  in  the  absence  of  alternative  tactics,  is  felt  by 
the  person  as  depression.  According  to  Sullivan's  scheme,  for  exam- 
ple, a  patient  regresses  to  earlier  and  simpler  (parataxic  and  pro- 
taxic)  modes  of  interaction  and  during  this  part  of  the  process  may 
show  symptoms  of  agitation  (unplanned  action),  as  in  agitated  depres- 
sion or  in  hebephrenia.*^  When  the  process  has  stabilized  and  the 
patient  has  not  developed  new  tactics,  he  is  said  to  suffer  from  a 
chronic  depression,  or,  if  the  regressive  process  has  gone  far  enough, 
he  may  be  classified  as  a  "simple  schizophrenic."  The  seriousness 
and  intensity  of  the  acute  episode  probably  depends  upon  how  rapidly 
the  tactics  are  abandoned. 

A  third  possibility  is  to  give  up  the  strategy,  but  to  hold  on  to 
the  tactics.  Various  habitual  acts,  once  an  important  part  of  the  total 
Plan,  or  of  the  person's  "style  of  life,"  may  have  become  uncon- 
scious, involuntary.  When  the  larger  Plan  is  dropped,  these  frag- 

0  H.  S.  Sullivan,  The  Interpersonal  Theory  of  Psychiatry  (New  York:  Norton, 
1953). 

Relinquishing  the  Plan  ■  115 


ments,  should  they  survive,  may  now  be  inappropriate.  In  extreme 
instances  they  w^ould  constitute  the  stuff  that  compulsions  and  obses- 
sions are  made  of.  The  patient  may  have  a  very  difficult  time  getting 
rid  of  them  or  formulating  his  new  Plans  in  such  a  way  that  the  old 
tactics  are  once  more  relevant  and  useful.  The  survival  of  autonomous 
islands  of  involuntary  Plans  may  well  form  a  part  of  the  clinical  pic- 
ture of  hysteria  and,  when  very  marked,  of  catatonia.  Both  hysteria 
and  catatonia  are  characterized  by  habitual,  ritualistic  patterns  of 
behavior  that  substitute  for  the  development  of  new,  useful  Plans. 

For  whatever  reason,  whether  it  be  a  threat  to  a  person's  Image 
or  intrinsic  to  the  wholesale  abandonment  of  large  segments  of  Plans, 
the  more  or  less  sudden  realization  that  an  enduring  Plan  must  be 
changed  at  a  strategic  level  is  accompanied  by  a  great  deal  of  emo- 
tional excitation.  When  this  excitation  can  find  no  focus  in  either  the 
Image  or  in  action,  the  person  experiences  "anxiety."  The  patient  may 
then  develop  Plans  to  cope  with  the  anxiety  (defense  mechanisms) 
instead  of  developing  new  Plans  to  cope  with  reahty. 

Can  the  execution  of  a  given  Plan  acquire  some  value  in  and  of 
itself?  Considerable  argument  has  led  the  present  authors  tentatively 
to  the  position  that  psychological  theory  will  be  simpler  if  values  are 
restricted  to  the  domain  of  knowledge,  to  the  Image  instead  of  the 
Plan.  How,  then,  can  we  account  for  the  person's  feeling  of  "com- 
mitment," to  use  an  existentialist  term?  How  can  we  explain  his 
suffering  when  an  enduring  Plan  must  be  abandoned?  Giving  up  the 
Plan  must  affect  the  person's  Image  of  himself  in  ways  that  are  diffi- 
cult for  him  to  accept.  Or,  to  express  the  same  notion  somewhat  dif- 
ferently, the  Plan  itself  may  be,  and  usually  is,  represented  in  the 
Image.  The  person's  knowledge  of  himself  includes  the  fact  that  he 
is  capable  of  executing  the  Plan.  Insofar  as  the  Plan  itself  is  sym- 
boUzed  in  the  Image,  its  representation  can  have  some  positive  (or 
negative)  value  associated  with  it.  In  fact,  some  such  assignment  of 
values  to  the  symbols  in  the  Image  that  represent  Plans  would  prob- 
ably be  an  aid  in  the  decision  to  transfer  some  familiar  Plan  to  a 
new  situation,  a  decision  that  forms  a  crucial  part  of  thinking  and  of 
problem-solving  generally. 


ii6  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


CHAPTER  9 


NONDYNAMIC   ASPECTS 
OF   PERSONALITY 


Psychologists  who  devote  their  intellectual  lives  to  the  search 
for  significant  dimensions  of  difference — let  us  dub  them  "clinicians" 
for  short — have  not  given  much  attention  to  the  differences  in  the 
v^^ays  people  make  Plans.  This  neglect  may  have  been  inherited  from 
their  experimental  colleagues.  The  first  experimenters  were  dedicated 
to  the  analysis  of  the  Image,  and  their  favorite  weapon  was  an  inner 
eye  called  "introspection."  Next,  the  behaviorists  expanded  the  sci- 
ence by  focusing  attention  on  the  movements  of  an  organism,  rather 
than  on  its  ideas.  But  Image  and  behavior  became  competitors,  and 
therefore  it  was  not  recognized  that  both  are  important  and  that  they 
need  to  be  linked  by  the  sort  of  planning  function  described  in  these 
pages.  On  both  sides  of  the  argument  the  experimenters  were  search- 
ing for  invariances  that  would  characterize  a  generalized  mind,  or  the 
basic  laws  of  behavior — the  kind  of  differences  among  people  that  a 
clinician  loves  were  just  experimental  errors  in  the  laboratory.  The 
Image  is  a  relatively  stable  structure;  red  is  red  and  circles  are  circu- 
lar, even  when  tilted,  etc.  And  behavior  is  controllable;  when  a  re- 

Nondynamic  Aspects  of  Personality  ■   117 


sponse  is  properly  under  the  control  of  a  reinforcing  stimulus,  you 
cannot  detect  the  differences  among  men,  rats,  birds,  and  fish.  The 
principal  differences  one  finds  when  one  examines  the  Image  or  the 
behavior  of  different  people  involve  their  values  and  reinforce- 
ments. Consequently,  the  clinician  has  been  forced  to  concentrate  his 
attention  on  the  dynamic  aspects  of  psychology,  since  only  there  does 
he  find  the  kind  of  variation  from  one  person  to  the  next  that  is  essen- 
tial if  we  are  to  understand  personality. 

But  is  this  restriction  to  the  Image  or  to  behavior  necessary?  In 
the  present  context,  of  course,  the  question  is  purely  rhetorical.  There 
is  still  another  domain,  the  Plan,  where  people  differ  greatly  and  sig- 
nificantly from  one  another,  where  the  differences  cannot  easily  be 
attributed  to  evaluative  origins,  and  where  we  can  find  a  rich  source 
of  clinical  insights.  Some  psychologists  have  come  very  close  to  this 
domain  when  they  have  discussed  personality  in  terms  of  "style," 
but  it  is  not  clear  that  all  differences  in  style  should  be  reduced  to  dif- 
ferences in  the  kinds  of  Plans  people  use.  In  any  event,  the  study  of 
style  has  not  prospered — it  has  been  a  less  fruitful  topic  than,  for 
example,  needs,  values,  drives,  valences,  etc.  One  difficulty,  no  doubt, 
is  that  the  variations  are  so  great  that  psychologists  have  not  known 
how  to  catch  them  in  their  clinical  and  psychometric  nets.  Whereas 
the  Image  is,  values  excepted,  discouragingly  stable  among  members 
of  similar  cultures,  the  Plan  is  so  variable  that  it  almost  defies  de- 
scription. A  clinician  wants  people  to  be  different,  but  not  that  dif- 
ferent. 

Popular  speech  recognizes  differences  in  values  by  such  sayings 
as,  "One  man's  meat  is  another  man's  poison,"  "There  is  no  account- 
ing for  tastes,"  etc.  We  may  even  accuse  each  other  of  basic  differ- 
ences in  our  Images  with  such  comments  as,  "His  ideas  are  weird," 
"He  doesn't  speak  our  language,"  etc.  But  individuality  is  perhaps 
more  often  captured  by  such  phrases  as,  "John  would  have  handled 
it  differently,"  "Bill  would  have  done  it  like  this,"  "You  never  know 
what  he  will  try  next,"  "They  never  give  up,"  etc.  These  phrases  relate 
to  differences  in  the  way  people  tackle  a  problem  and  carry  it  through. 
In  order  to  follow  up  this  lead  we  might  look  at  some  of  the  obvious 
ways  in  which  Plans  can  differ,  then  try  to  see  if  we  recognize  these 
differences  among  the  people  we  know. 

ii8  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


Source.  Because  Plans  are  communicable  it  is  possible  to  imi- 
tate others,  to  accept  their  Plans,  instead  of  using  your  own.  David 
Riesman  has  laid  particular  stress  on  this  aspect  of  character  and  has 
described  those  who  act  on  their  own  Plans  as  "inner-directed,"  those 
who  act  on  borrowed  Plans  as  "other-directed."  We  shall  not  compete 
with  The  Lonely  Crowd  by  trying  to  elaborate  the  difference  in  these 
pages.  It  is  worth  noting,  however,  that  men  and  women  show  char- 
acteristic differences  in  the  ways  they  prefer  to  tackle  problems: 
whereas  men  when  given  the  chance  tend  to  produce  an  analytic  or 
abstract  Plan  for  solving  the  problem,  women  more  often  begin  by 
seeking  help  from  others.^ 

Span.  Some  Plans  incorporate  events  that  are  expected  to  occur 
months,  years,  even  centuries  in  the  future,  others  are  limited  to  the 
next  few  seconds  or  minutes.  There  are  large  differences  in  the  tem- 
poral scope  of  planning  that  will  occur  in  different  cultures,  but  even 
wathin  a  single  culture  there  are  characteristic  differences  between 
individuals  in  the  extent  to  which  they  worry  about  remote  events. 
Whereas  one  person  may  make  elaborate  Plans  for  the  financial  se- 
curity of  his  grandchildren,  another  may  be  unwilling  to  develop 
Plans  that  extend  much  beyond  his  evening  meal. 

Detail.  Some  people  sketch  in  only  the  general  strategy  of  their 
Plans  before  they  begin  to  execute  them;  others  will  not  decide  to 
execute  any  Plan  until  they  have  elaborated  the  smallest  tactics  wdth 
a  fine  pen.  How  meticulous  you  are  is  probably  a  highly  stable  feature 
of  your  planning.  If  you  must  have  every  detail  worked  out,  you  are 
what  is  usually  referred  to  as  a  compulsive  person.  Of  course,  the 
nature  of  the  Plan  itself  and  also  the  value  of  the  Image  which  the 
Plan's  execution  will  affect  are  both  considerations  in  determining 
how  far  one  should  go  in  "debugging"  a  Plan  before  it  is  executed,  and 
it  might  be  possible  experimentally  to  isolate  some  of  these  factors 
that  determine  Plan  complexity.^ 

1  G.  Alexander  Milton,  Five  studies  of  the  relation  between  sex-role  identifi- 
cation and  achievement  in  problem  solving.  (Technical  Report  3,  contract  Nonr 
609(20),  NR  150-166.)  Departments  of  Industrial  Administration  and  Psychol- 
ogy, Yale  University,  1958. 

-  A  study  by  Walter  Gruen,  Behavioral  correlates  of  some  dimensions  of  the 
cognitive  field,  Journal  of  Personality,  1959,  27,  169-186,  illustrates  the  kind  of 
thing  that  can  be  done.  People  were  given  a  Rorschach  ink-blot  test  and  they  were 
required  to  learn  the  correct  path  through  a  long  and  complicated  stylus  maze. 
During  the  initial  stages  of  learning  the  maze,  the  people  who  had  given  many 

Nondynamic  Aspects  of  Personality  ■   119 


Flexibility.  A  Plan  is  flexible  if  the  order  of  execution  of  its  parts 
can  be  easily  interchanged  without  affecting  the  feasibility  of  the 
Plan.  The  degree  to  which  a  person  would  favor  flexible  Plans  is  prob- 
ably related  to  the  amount  of  detail  he  characteristically  demands, 
but  the  correlation  is  worth  some  empirical  verification.  The  flexible 
planner  might  tend  to  think  of  lists  of  things  he  had  to  do;  the  inflexi- 
ble planner  would  have  his  time  planned  like  a  sequence  of  cause- 
effect  relations.  The  former  could  rearrange  his  lists  to  suit  his  op- 
portunities, but  the  latter  would  be  unable  to  strike  while  the  iron  was 
hot  and  would  generally  require  considerable  "lead-time"  before  he 
could  incorporate  any  alternative  subplans.  The  person  who  charac- 
teristically devises  inflexible  Plans  and  then  refuses  to  interrupt 
them  is  usually  referred  to  as  a  rigid  person.^ 

Speed.  Some  people  Plan  more  rapidly  than  others.  No  doubt  in- 
telligence is  involved  here  to  a  large  extent,  but  that  is  not  all  there  is 
to  it.  Two  people  of  equal  intelligence  might  work  out  Plans  in  equiv- 
alent detail  for  coping  with  the  same  anticipated  situation,  yet  one 
may  arrive  at  his  Plan  immediately,  constructing  it  almost  as  rapidly 
as  he  can  describe  it,  whereas  the  other  must  spend  hours  with  pen- 
cil and  paper.  Planning  is  a  skill,  and  as  with  all  skilled  acts,  some 
people  are  quicker  than  others.* 

Coordination.  Some  people  seem  to  keep  each  Plan  in  a  separate 


"whole  responses"  on  the  Rorschach  were  best  able  to  organize  sequences  of 
correct  moves  in  the  maze  into  larger  units.  As  the  learning  progressed,  however, 
the  people  who  had  given  many  "formal  responses"  (no  mention  of  movement 
or  color,  only  form)  and  "large  detail  responses"  on  the  Rorschach  mastered  the 
maze  perfectly  in  the  shortest  time.  Although  a  projective  test  provides  a  special 
approach  to  the  study  of  personality,  and  although  maze-learning  is  a  reasonable 
test  of  planning  only  by  the  grace  of  reasonable  assumption,  nevertheless,  Gruen's 
results  encourage  the  present  authors  to  believe  that  a  person's  interest  in  detail 
— both  in  his  Images  and  his  Plans — could  be  studied  objectively. 

3  One  way  to  approach  this  aspect  of  personality  has  been  illustrated  by 
A.  S.  Luchins,  Mechanization  in  problem  solving,  Psychological  Monographs, 
1942,  No.  248.  Subjects  who  had  discovered  a  satisfactory  Plan  for  solving  a 
series  of  water-measuring  problems  differed  in  their  ability  to  change  it  when  an 
easier  Plan  became  possible.  Compare  the  review  of  this  work  and  of  other 
studies  of  individual  differences  in  problem  solving:  Donald  W.  Taylor  and 
Olga  W.  McNemar,  Problem  solving  and  thinking,  in  C.  P.  Stone  (ed.).  Annual 
Review  of  Psychology  (Palo  Alto,  Annual  Reviews,  1955,  Vol.  6,  pp.  455-482). 

*  Although  it  may  not  be  directly  relevant,  a  study  by  F.  L.  Wells,  Instruction 
time  in  certain  multiple-choice  tests;  Cases  XCVI-CII,  Journal  of  Genetic  Psy- 
chology, 1950,  267-281,  illustrates  one  way  this  aspect  might  be  studied.  By 
recording  how  long  each  subject  wanted  to  study  the  instructions  before  he 
started  taking  an  ability  test,  Wells  found  consistent  individual  differences  that 
could  not  be  explained  in  terms  of  differences  in  general  ability. 


120  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


compartment,  to  execute  each  Plan  independently  of  all  the  others. 
They  make  three  trips  to  town  in  one  afternoon,  each  trip  connected 
with  the  execution  of  a  different  Plan.  Again,  one  suspects  that  low 
intelligence  may  have  something  to  do  with  the  isolation  of  one 
Plan  from  another,  but  intelligence  is  not  the  whole  story.  It  would 
be  instructive  to  know  whether  the  person  who  has  trouble  coordinat- 
ing his  own  Plans  is  also  the  person  who  has  trouble  coordinating  his 
Plans  with  those  of  other  people. 

Retrieval.  The  kind  of  working  memory  that  people  prefer  to  use 
when  they  are  executing  a  Plan  seems  to  represent  a  characteristic 
difference.  One  person  will  insist  on  writing  things  down,  running 
his  life  from  a  calendar  pad,  whereas  another  person  will  keep  in  his 
own  head  everything  he  intends  to  do.  Also,  some  people  will  become 
very  upset  if  they  lose  track  of  how  far  they  have  progressed  in  the 
execution  of  some  Plan,  but  others  seem  almost  irresponsible,  or 
"flighty,"  in  their  willingness  to  let  one  Plan  drop  absent-mindedly  as 
they  pursue  another. 

Openness.  Some  people  are  very  cagey  about  announcing  what 
their  Plans  are,  whereas  others  feel  quite  free  to  describe  them  to 
anybody  who  inquires  (and,  unfortunately,  even  to  those  who  do  not 
inquire).  An  additional  complication  arises,  of  course,  if  we  consider 
the  fact  that  some  people  freely  describe  Plans  they  will  never  exe- 
cute. 

Stop-orders.  A  rich  source  of  individual  differences  is  connected 
with  the  location  and  kind  of  stop-orders  a  person  will  insert  into  his 
Plans.  A  little  more  than  the  familiar  notions  of  persistence  and 
satiation  ^  is  involved,  however,  because  one  person  may  give  up  be- 
cause time  is  gone,  another  because  no  one  agrees  with  him,  another 
because  he  wants  to  avoid  hurting  himself,  etc.  Here  we  come  very 
close  to  some  of  the  dynamic  properties  of  the  Image  that  will, 
usually  unconsciously,  determine  what  kind  of  outcomes  will  termi- 
nate the  execution  of  the  Plan.  Notice,  incidentally,  that  perseverance 
is  not  necessarily  correlated  with  compulsiveness  in  the  context  of 
the  present  discussions. 

5  See,  for  example,  the  review  by  Kurt  Lewin,  Behavior  and  development  as 
a  function  of  the  total  situation,  in  L.  Carmichael,  ed.,  Manual  of  Child  Psy- 
chology (New  York:  W^iley,  1946),  especially  pp.  824  S. 

Nondynamic  Aspects  of  Personality  ■121 


This  list  could  be  extended  quite  a  bit  further,  no  doubt,  but 
these  should  be  sufficient  to  suggest  what  kind  of  differences  in 
Plans  one  could  look  for  in  a  study  of  personality.  Professional  stu- 
dents of  personality  could  probably  tidy  up  these  ideas  and  organize 
them  in  ways  more  appropriate  to  the  work  that  has  been  done  in  this 
field.  The  present  authors  are  inclined  to  say  that  what  they  are  de- 
scribing here  are  personality  traits  and  that  the  theory  of  personal- 
ity developed  by  Gordon  Allport  is  as  close  to  what  we  have  in  mind 
as  anything  else  we  are  familiar  with.*^  In  order  to  test  the  validity  of 
this  association,  the  reader  is  invited  to  take  a  sample  of  trait  names 
and  to  see  how  many  of  them  can  be  characterized  in  terms  of  Plans. 
The  authors  have  tried  this  exercise  and  have  concluded  that  it  is 
very  easy  to  make  the  translation  from  trait  name  to  some  aspect  of 
planning  in  most  cases,  but  they  may  be  too  prejudiced  to  judge  the 
matter  objectively.  In  any  case,  many  trait  names  have  very  dynamic 
connotations.  For  example,  "dominance"  can  be  either  a  need  to  con- 
trol one's  environment  or  the  trait  of  communicating  one's  Plans  to 
other  people.  "Order"  can  be  considered  as  a  need  for  cleanliness, 
neatness,  balance,  precision,  or  it  can  be  described  as  the  extensive 
use  of  environmental  memory.  And  so  on. 

The  sort  of  trait  theory — if  that  is  what  it  should  be  called — to 
which  a  student  of  Plans  could  subscribe  would  have  to  be  shorn  of 
these  dynamic,  evaluative  overtones.  Values  are  properly  a  part  of  the 
Image  system,  as  has  been  repeatedly  argued  in  these  pages.  This 
distinction  would  lead  to  a  less  evaluative  kind  of  trait  system  than 
clinicians  are  accustomed  to.  And  the  traits  would  not  be  simple  dif- 
ferences in  the  amount  of  some  otherwise  undefined  facet  of  per- 
sonality, but  would  be  attributable  to,  or  derivable  from,  different 
structural  aspects  of  the  person's  Plans.  The  structure  of  Plans 
would  then  be  able  to  stand  as  part  of  the  description  of  a  personality 
on  an  equal  footing  with  the  current  descriptions  of  need  structure. 

6  Gordon  W.  Allport,  Personality:  A  Psychological  Interpretation  (New  York: 
Holt,  1937).  It  should  be  apparent,  however,  that  there  is  no  necessary  connection 
between  an  interest  in  Plans  and  Allport's  trait  theory  of  personality.  Henry 
Chauncey,  of  the  Educational  Testing  Service  in  Princeton,  New  Jersey,  has 
shown  us  an  interesting  personality  test,  the  Myers-Briggs  Type  Indicator,  that 
explores  (among  other  things)  the  extent  to  which  people  like  to  plan  their 
activities  in  advance;  the  test  was  designed  to  get  at  basic  personality  difFer- 
ences,  similar  to  those  proposed  by  C.  G.  Jung,  one  of  which  is  the  extent  to 
which  plans  are  used. 

122  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


Neither  one  is  more  fundamental  or  more  important  than  the  other. 

Having  wandered  this  far  afield,  the  present  authors  will  go  a 
step  farther  and  point  out  that  differences  in  Plans  would  seem  to 
characterize  different  cultures  as  well  as  different  personalities.  There 
does  not  seem  to  be  any  sizeable  body  of  anthropological  literature 
that  one  might  consider  an  adequate  basis  for  analysis,  but  casual  ob- 
servations by  anthropologists  and  sociologists  indicate  that  the  dif- 
ferences are  there  waiting  to  be  described.  A  Persian  businessman, 
we  are  told,  runs  his  affairs  in  a  planless  state  that  would  drive  any 
American  to  distraction.  He  will  order  machinery  before  he  knows 
how  he  can  pay  for  it,  and  he  will  pay  for  it  before  he  makes  any 
plans  for  how  to  use  it.  An  Arab  will  say  that  the  future  is  known 
only  to  God  and  that  it  would  be  impertinent  to  plan  how  it  will  hap- 
pen. A  Navajo  is  bound  to  the  present  and  cannot  consider  promises 
of  future  benefits  as  anything  worth  planning  for.  Latin  Americans 
will  assume  that  other  people  will  enforce  stop-rules  for  them  and 
that  in  matters  of  passion  they  do  not  have  to  control  themselves. 
And  so  on. 

Although  anthropologists  have  not  made  any  more  systematic 
studies  of  planning  than  have  psychologists,  anthropologists  have  had 
something  to  say  about  different  attitudes  toward  time.  The  American 
takes  his  elaborate  system  of  timekeeping  for  granted,  assumes  every- 
one must  conceive  of  time  as  he  does,  and  cannot  understand  why 
people  in  other  cultures  are  so  unconcerned  about  keeping  appoint- 
ments, finishing  the  jobs  they  start,  confining  certain  activities  to 
certain  hours  of  the  day,  etc.  Time  is  much  less  important  in  other 
cultures  than  it  is  in  ours,  and  plans  are  made  and  executed  in  a 
much  more  leisurely,  informal  way.  It  seems  to  us  possible  that 
planning  is  one  of  the  most  important  points  of  contact  between  those 
two  equally  extravagant  concepts,  culture  and  personality. 

The  fact  that  Americans  place  so  high  a  value  on  the  faithful 
execution  of  shared  plans  may  be  part  and  parcel  of  that  "stress  of 
modern  life"  we  hear  so  much  about.  Our  insistence  on  this  point 
may  be  producing  many  character  disorders,  disturbances  that  would 
not  arise  in  another  culture.  Or,  more  likely,  other  cultures  may  be 
better  able  to  tolerate  a  person  whose  style  of  planning  is  unusual 
or  who  fails  to  complete  the  execution  of  shared  plans. 

Nondynamic  Aspects  of  Personality  ■    123 


CHAPTER  10 


PLANS   FOR 
REMEMBERING 


The  usual  approach  to  the  study  of  memorization  is  to  ask  how 
the  material  is  engraved  on  the  nervous  system,  how  the  connections 
between  the  parts  of  it  become  learned,  or  imprinted,  or  strength- 
ened, or  conditioned.  The  usual  answers  have  to  do  with  the  amount 
of  practice,  with  the  beneficent  consequences  of  success,  with  the 
facilitating  or  inhibiting  effects  arising  from  similarity  among  parts 
of  the  materials  or  between  these  materials  and  others,  with  the 
meaningfulness  or  other  sources  of  transfer  of  previous  learning, 
and  so  on.^  No  one  who  knew  the  experimental  data  would  question 
that  all  these  factors  are  important  in  determining  how  fast  and  how 
well  a  person  will  be  able  to  commit  a  particular  string  of  symbols  to 
memory.  The  reason  for  returning  to  this  weU-cultivated  plot  and 
trying  to  crowd  in  another  crop  is  that  an  important  aspect  of  the 
memorizing  process  seems  to  have  been  largely  ignored.  It  has  been 
ignored  because  the  traditions  of,  first,  behaviorism  and,  later,  opera- 

1  The  field  of  psychological  research  that  we  have  in  mind  is  reviewed  in 
John  A.  McGeoch  and  Arthur  L.  Irion,  The  Psychology  of  Human  Learning  (New 
York:  Longmans  Green,  ed.  2,  1952). 

Plans  for  Remembering  "125 


tionism  tended  to  prevent  psychologists  from  speculating  about  sym- 
bolic processes  inside  the  memorizer  and  encouraged  an  organiza- 
tion of  the  field  in  terms  of  what  the  experimenter,  rather  than  the 
memorizer,  was  doing.  Since  the  present  authors  have  here  thrown 
operational  and  behavioral  caution  to  the  winds,  they  are  free  to 
speculate  about  what  the  learner  is  doing  and  to  ignore  (for  the  mo- 
ment) what  the  experimenter  is  up  to.  It  is  the  learner,  not  the  experi- 
menter, who  must  be  explained.  Let  us  focus  attention  on  him,  on  his 
task,  and  on  his  efforts  to  cope  with  it. 

Ordinarily  the  simplest  way  to  find  out  what  a  person  is  doing  is 
to  ask  him.  But  psychologists  have  become  very  chary  about  asking 
people  what  they  are  doing  because,  they  usually  say,  people  really 
do  not  know  what  they  are  doing  and  it  is  just  a  waste  of  time  to  be- 
lieve what  they  tell  you.  This  skepticism  may  indeed  be  justified  in 
many  cases,  especially  those  dealing  with  emotions  and  motivations. 
But  it  seems  foolish  to  refuse  to  listen  to  the  person  under  any  circum- 
stances. What  he  says  is  not  always  wrong.  More  often  what  he  says 
would  provide  a  valuable  clue  if  only  we  were  able  to  understand 
what  it  meant. 

If  you  ask  a  man  who  has  just  memorized  his  first  list  of  non- 
sense syllables  to  tell  you  what  he  did  in  order  to  master  the  list,  he 
wdll  have  quite  a  lot  to  say.  And  he  will  usually  be  eager  to  say  it.  In 
fact,  the  only  part  of  the  task  that  has  any  interest  or  appeal  to  most 
subjects  concerns  the  discovery  and  use  of  a  technique  for  solving 
the  problem.  He  will  say  that  he  was  trying  to  connect  things  up  and 
make  sense  of  them.  Of  course,  you  knew  that  he  had  to  connect 
them  up,  but  how  did  he  make  sense  out  of  the  carefully  chosen  non- 
sense he  was  given?  Well,  it  wasn't  easy,  but  he  did  it.  Now,  that  first 
nonsense  syllable,  BOF,  was  just  plain  remembered  the  way  it  came, 
but  the  second  one  reminded  him  of  "XAJerate,"  the  third  one  turned 
into  "MIBery,"  and  the  fourth  turned  from  ZYQ  to  "not  sick."  So  he 
had  a  kind  of  sentence,  "BOF  exagrates  his  misery  because  he  is 
not  sick,"  instead  of  the  cryptic  BOF,  XAJ,  MIB,  ZYQ,  and  he  could 
imagine  a  hypochondriac  named  BOF  who  continually  complained 
about  his  health.  That  MIBery-misery  association  wasn't  too  good, 
however,  because  for  two  or  three  trials  through  the  Ust  he  remem- 
bered MIS  instead  of  MIB.  But  he  finally  worked  it  out  by  thinking  of 

126  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


"mibery"  as  a  new  word  meaning  "false  misery."  The  fleeting  thought 
that  ZYQ  was  a  strange  way  to  spell  "sick"  was  just  amusing 
enough  to  fix  the  fourth  syllable.  Now  the  fifth  and  sixth  syllables 
went  together,  too.  .  .  .  And  so  the  subject  chatters  on,  spinning  out 
long  descriptions  of  the  various  ideas,  images,  associations,  and 
connections  that  occurred  to  him  during  the  learning.  Is  it  nothing 
but  chatter?  Or  is  this  the  sort  of  data  that  psychologists  ought  to 
study  most  carefully?  Data  about  the  number  of  trials  required  to 
reach  this  or  that  criterion  set  by  the  experimenter  may  be  far  less 
valuable  for  understanding  what  memorization  is  all  about. 

The  attitude  of  most  experimental  psychologists  toward  these 
associative  links  that  a  memorizer  spends  so  much  of  his  time  look- 
ing for  is  illustrated  by  the  following  comment : 

Such  aids  in  memorizing  are  naturally  regarded  with  much 
favor  by  O,  but  E  would  like  to  be  rid  of  them.  They  make  the 
learning  task  less  uniform  and  introduce  variability  and  unrelia- 
bility into  the  quantitative  results.  Besides,  E  wants  to  study  the 
formation  of  new  associations,  not  O's  clever  utilization  of  old 
ones." 

Is  there  some  way  to  interpret  this  comment  so  that  it  does  not  mean 
that  the  experimenter  has  no  interest  in  what  his  subject  is  trying  to 
do?  It  would  appear  that  the  present  authors  hold  a  minority  opinion, 
for  they  believe  that  it  is  better  to  try  to  find  out  what  a  person  is  doing 
than  to  assume  he  is  doing  what  you  want  to  study. 

The  principal  reason  this  kind  of  report  looks  so  hopeless  to  a 
psychologist  is  that  every  subject  tells  a  different  story.  The  associa- 
tions seem  to  be  entirely  random,  or  certainly  idiosyncratic,  and  how 
can  anyone  make  a  science  out  of  things  no  two  of  which  behave  the 
same  way?  It  is  much  easier  to  think  in  terms  of  an  average  subject 
with  normal,  but  unspecified,  associations.  It  may  even  be  better  to 
do  so,  because  introspections  are  notoriously  unreliable  and  because 
there  is  no  assurance  that  these  elaborate  translations  and  groupings 
and  associations  by  the  memorizer  are  really  any  help  at  all.  We 
would  expect  the  properly  cautious  student  of  human  learning  to 

2  Robert  S.  Woodworth  and  Harold  Schlosberg,  Experimental  Psychology 
(New  York:  Holt,  rev.  ed.,  1954),  p.  708. 

Plans  for  Remembering  ■   127 


tell  us  something  like  this :  "The  most  parsimonious  theory  of  human 
learning  is  that  the  continued  repetition  of  a  correct  response,  fol- 
lowed by  reinforcement  or  confirmation,  builds  up  the  excitatory 
potential  for  that  correct  response  while  all  other  response  tendencies 
are  inhibited  or  extinguished.  All  the  talk  the  subject  gives  us  is  just 
that — talk.  It  really  has  nothing  to  do  with  the  more  fundamental, 
probably  unconscious  process  of  laying  down  a  good,  solid  memory 
trace  that  will  lead  reliably  from  the  stimuli  to  the  desired  responses." 
Now,  although  this  approach  may  be  parsiminous,  it  has  since  1885 
made  rote  memorization  one  of  the  dreariest  chapters — psychophys- 
ics  not  excepted — in  experimental  psychology.  The  alternative  ap- 
proach may  be  hopelessly  complicated,  but  at  least  it  is  more  interest- 
ing. 

A  memorizer's  task  in  the  psychological  laboratory  is  to  learn 
how  to  produce  a  particular  sequence  of  noises  that  he  would  never 
make  ordinarily,  that  have  no  significance,  and  that  will  be  of  no  use 
to  him  later.  Rote  serial  memorization  is  a  complicated,  tricky  thing 
to  learn  to  do,  and  when  it  is  mastered  it  represents  a  rather  special 
skill.  The  argument  here  is  that  such  a  skill  could  not  run  itself  off 
successfully  unless  it  were  guided  in  its  execution  by  a  Plan  of  the 
sort  we  have  been  discussing.  What  the  subject  is  telling  us  when 
he  reports  all  the  wild  and  improbable  connections  he  had  to  use  is 
the  way  in  which  he  developed  a  Plan  to  control  his  performance  dur- 
ing the  test  period. 

Now,  it  would  be  extremely  easy  at  this  point  for  us  to  become 
confused  between  two  different  kinds  of  Plans  that  are  involved  in 
rote  memorization.  On  the  one  hand,  the  subject  is  attempting  to 
construct  a  Plan  that  will,  when  executed,  generate  the  nonsense 
syllables  in  the  correct  order.  But  at  the  same  time  he  must  adopt 
a  Plan  to  guide  his  memorizing,  he  must  choose  a  strategy  for  con- 
structing the  Plan  for  recall.  There  are  a  variety  of  ways  open  to  the 
subject  for  memorizing.  One  is  to  translate  the  nonsense  syllables 
into  words,  then  to  organize  the  words  into  sentences  and/or  images, 
even,  if  necessary,  to  organize  the  sentences  and  images  into  a  story 
if  the  length  of  the  list  demands  such  higher-order  planning.  Another 
Plan  the  person  can  use  is  sheer  drill  without  any  translation,  per- 
haps aided  by  rhythmic  grouping,  until  the  list  rolls  out  as  the  let- 

128  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


ters  of  the  alphabet  do.  Or  he  can  play  tricks  with  imagery — imagin- 
ing each  syllable  at  a  different  location  in  the  room,  then  simply  look- 
ing there  and  "reading"  it  when  it  is  needed,  etc.  There  are  a  variety 
of  such  strategies  for  learning,  and  they  should  be  investigated.  But 
it  is  the  impression  of  the  present  authors  that  the  average  person, 
when  confronted  with  a  list  of  nonsense  syllables  for  the  first  time, 
will  do  something  similar  to  the  performance  described  above. 

Unless  a  person  has  some  kind  of  Plan  for  learning,  nothing 
happens.  Subjects  have  read  nonsense  syllables  hundreds  of  times 
and  learned  almost  nothing  about  them  if  they  were  not  aware 
that  they  would  later  be  tested  for  recall.  In  order  to  get  the  list 
memorized,  a  subject  must  have  that  mysterious  something  called  an 
"intent  to  learn."  Given  the  intention,  the  act  follows  by  a  steady, 
slow  heave  of  the  will.  This  proposition  has  provoked  a  certain 
amount  of  exploration  by  memory  psychologists.  The  data  that  have 
been  collected  are  extensive  and  various,  and  only  fools  would  at- 
tempt a  simple  generaUzation  about  them.  The  simple  generaUzation 
of  the  present  authors  is  this:  An  intention  to  learn  means  that  the 
subject  executes  a  Plan  to  form  a  Plan  to  guide  recall.  (See  Chapter  4 
for  a  discussion  of  intention.)  The  intention  does  not  "stamp  in"  or 
"strengthen"  the  associations — it  merely  signifies  that  the  person  will 
search  for  associations  that  he  already  has. 

A  subject  may,  of  course,  form  fragments  of  a  Plan  for  memoriz- 
ing more  or  less  absent-mindedly  and  incidentally,  without  anticipat- 
ing that  they  may  become  useful  to  him  later,  and  in  that  case  he  will 
learn  without  intending  to.  The  important  thing  is  to  have  a  Plan  to 
execute  for  generating  the  recall  responses;  ordinarily,  but  not  in- 
variably, that  Plan  will  not  be  achieved  without  intent  to  learn,  that 
is  to  say,  without  executing  a  metaplan  for  constructing  a  Plan  that 
will  guide  recall.  If  you  ask  a  person  what  words  are  suggested  to  him 
by  various  nonsense  syllables,  and  if  you  let  him  arrange  those 
words  into  sentences,  all  as  part  of  some  unexplained  game  but  with- 
out any  suggestion  that  recall  will  be  tested,  if  you  encourage  him  by 
other  tricks  to  do  all  the  things  he  would  do  in  forming  a  Plan  for  re- 
call, then  you  will  find  that  he  has  inadvertently  learned  a  great  deal 
of  the  material  without  intent  to  learn.  (Without  glancing  back, 
try  to  recall  the  four  nonsense  syllables  used  in  the  example  at  the 

Plans  for  Remembering  ■   129 


beginning  of  this  chapter.)  For  example,  if  you  ask  a  person  merely  to 
notice  whether  the  numbers  on  a  list  suggest  anything  to  him — birth 
dates,  street  addresses,  telephone  numbers — he  will  recall  the  num- 
bers later  just  as  well  as  he  would  have  if  you  had  instructed  him  to 
memorize  them  intentionally.^  It  is  the  execution  of  the  Plan,  not  just 
the  intent  to  execute  it,  that  is  important. 

The  study  of  learning  Plans  should  tell  us  something  about 
how  people  form  Plans  in  general.  The  natural,  naive,  first-impulse 
kind  of  response  to  the  nonsense  syllables  is  to  translate  them  into 
words.  This  suggests  that  a  natural  element  of  nonrecurrent  Plans — 
new  or  temporary,  as  opposed  to  instinctive  or  habitual  Plans — are 
words  and  phrases,  a  suggestion  that  supports  our  speculations  about 
the  general  importance  of  words  in  our  Plans.  Moreover,  people  tend 
to  master  the  material  in  chunks  organized  as  units.  This  fact 
tends  to  become  obscured  by  the  mechanical  methods  of  presentation 
used  in  most  experiments  on  rote  learning,  because  such  methods  do 
not  enable  the  subject  to  spend  his  time  as  he  wishes. 

If  we  listen  carefully  to  the  memorizer's  explanation  of  how  he 
reproduces  a  list  of  nonsense  syllables  in  the  correct  order,  we  note 
that  the  translation  into  words  is  only  the  first  step  in  his  campaign. 
The  second  is  to  group  the  words  into  phrases,  then,  if  necessary,  to 
group  the  phrases  into  stories  or  bizarre  episodes.  This  procedure 
results  in  a  hierarchical  organization  of  the  list.  The  list  turns  out  to 
have,  say,  four  parts,  each  of  which  has  its  own  smaller  parts,  each  of 
which,  perhaps,  consists  of  words  that  suggest  the  nonsense  syllables. 
When  this  hierarchical  structure  is  complete — when  the  Plan  for 
recitation  is  constructed — the  subject  is  able  to  recite  the  syllables 
in  their  correct  order.*  There  would  seem  to  be  no  fundamental 
difference  between  the  way  his  recitation  is  guided  by  a  hierarchical 

3  Irving  J.  Saltzman,  Comparisons  of  incidental  and  intentional  learning 
with  different  orienting  tasks,  American  Journal  of  Psychology,  1956,  69,  274- 
277. 

4  The  importance  of  a  hierarchical  organization  in  serial  memorization  has 
been  pointed  out  in  three  articles  by  George  A.  Miller:  The  magical  number  seven, 
plus  or  minus  two.  Psychological  Review,  1956,  63,  81—97;  Information  and 
memory,  Scientific  American,  1956,  195,  42-46;  and  Human  memory  and  the 
storage  of  information,  IRE  Transactions  on  Information  Theory,  1956,  Vol. 
IT-2,  No.  3,  128-137.  A  more  general  discussion,  however,  can  be  found  in  A.  A. 
Cleveland,  The  psychology  of  chess  and  of  learning  to  play  it,  American  Journal 
of  Psychology,  1907,  18,  269-308. 

130  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


Plan  and  the  way  all  his  other  intentional  behavior  is  guided  by 
hierarchical  Plans. 

Some  questions  of  efficiency  should  be  raised  at  this  point.  Why 
do  we  bother  to  build  up  such  elaborate  hierarchies?  Does  this  not 
add  to  what  we  already  have  to  remember?  A  list  of  N  words  requires 
N— 1  associations  if  we  learn  them  as  a  chain.  If  we  organize  them 
into  groups  and  form  associations  between  those  groups,  we  simply 
add  to  the  number  of  associations  we  need.  Isn't  this  just  a  make- 
work  proposition?  The  efficient  solution  should  be  to  use  as  few 
new  associations  as  possible.  A  suspicious  attitude  toward  these  or- 
ganizing tricks  is  reinforced  by  the  observation  that  experienced 
memorizers  of  nonsense  syllables  say  they  can  drop  out  all  the  trans- 
lating and  grouping  and  imagining,  and  concentrate  directly  upon 
connecting  one  syllable  with  the  next. 

The  question  raises  a  variety  of  problems.  In  the  first  place,  ex- 
perienced memorizers  do  change  their  strategy  for  memorizing.  The 
change  is  prompted,  at  least  in  part,  by  increasing  familiarity  with 
nonsense  syllables,  less  insecurity  and  anxiety  about  the  task,  more 
appreciation  for  the  usefulness  of  rhythmic,  as  opposed  to  seman- 
tic, grouping,  and  by  general  exhaustion  with  the  effort  involved  in 
doing  it  the  way  we  described  above.  The  matter  needs  careful  ex- 
amination, but  it  is  the  authors's  impression  that  even  the  most 
hardened  subjects  never  give  up  the  practice  of  grouping  the  syllables 
into  substrings,  thus  producing  a  kind  of  simple  hierarchy,  or  Plan. 
What  he  gives  up  first  is  the  translation  of  the  nonsense  syllables 
into  words,  which  is  what  the  novice  spends  most  of  his  time  doing. 
It  is  also  interesting  to  note,  however,  that  twenty-four  hours  later 
the  novice  will  remember  the  list  a  good  deal  better  than  will  the 
more  professional  memorizer.^ 

But  we  are  still  left  with  the  fact  of  grouping  and  with  questions 
about  the  necessity  for  this  extra  labor.  The  reason  for  it  seems  to  be 
related  to  the  rather  severe  limitation  of  our  span  of  apprehension. 
The  largest  number  of  digits  the  average  person  can  remember  after 
one  presentation  is  about  seven,  and  if  we  want  to  be  sure  that  he  will 
never  fail,  we  must  reduce  the  number  to  four  or  five.  Thus  it  is  about 

5  Benton  J.  Underwood,  Interference  and  forgetting,  Psychological  Review, 
1957,  64,  49-60. 

Plans  for  Remembering  ■  131 


four  or  five  symbols  (words,  elements,  items,  lists,  things,  chunks, 
ideas,  thoughts,  etc.)  that  will  easily  group  in  consciousness  at  one 
time  as  a  new  list  to  which  we  can  attach  a  new  label.  Even  lists  as 
short  as  the  names  of  the  months  are  organized  into  the  four  seasons. 
The  longest  unorganized  list  that  most  of  us  ever  learn  is  the  alpha- 
bet, and  even  there  one  suspects  that  hierarchical  traces  could  be 
detected  in  a  child's  learning  process,  traces  that  vanish  when  the 
recitation  is,  by  endless  repetition,  transferred  from  a  conscious, 
planned  performance  into  "pure  habit"  so  that  the  mouth  can  speak 
without  guidance  from  above.  As  the  learner  groups  and  renames  the 
elements  in  the  Hst  to  be  memorized,  he  effectively  shortens  the 
length  of  the  list.  It  is  as  though  he  is  trying  to  reduce  the  list  to 
the  number  of  units  that  can  be  held  in  mind  simultaneously,  since  at 
that  point  there  can  be  no  serious  problems  in  executing  the  Plan 
when  the  time  comes  to  translate  it  into  action.  Miller  once  tried  to 
explain  the  informational  economies  of  grouping  and  renaming  in 
the  following  terms : 

Since  it  is  as  easy  to  remember  a  lot  of  information  (when 
the  items  are  information  ally  rich)  as  it  is  to  remember  a  little 
information  (when  the  items  are  information  ally  impoverished), 
it  is  economical  to  organize  the  material  into  rich  chunks.  To 
draw  a  rather  farfetched  analogy,  it  is  as  if  we  had  to  carry  all 
our  money  in  a  purse  that  could  contain  only  seven  coins.  It 
doesn't  matter  to  the  purse,  however,  whether  these  coins  are 
pennies  or  silver  dollars.  The  process  of  organizing  and  reorgan- 
izing is  a  pervasive  human  trait,  and  it  is  motivated,  at  least  in 
part,  by  an  attempt  to  make  the  best  possible  use  of  our  mne- 
monic capacity.*' 

Because  the  particular  tricks  that  each  person  will  use  to  group 
and  rename  the  materials  he  is  attempting  to  remember  are  quite 
variable  and  idiosyncratic,  they  pose  formidable  problems  for  the 
experimentalist.  In  his  attempts  to  solve  them,  the  experimentalist 
might  very  well  turn  into  a  clinician,  for  every  subject  must  be  indi- 
vidually studied  and  his  performance  interpreted  in  terms  of  the 
particular  Plan  that  he  constructed.  In  addition,  there  are  all  of  the 

^  George  A.  Miller,  Human  memory  and  the  storage  of  information,  IRE 
Transactions  on  Information  Theory,  1956,  Vol.  IT-2,  No.  3,  129-137. 

132  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


clinician's  problems  of  discovering  what  the  subject's  Plan  really 
was  when  the  subject  himself  is  not  very  clear  about  it.  But  the  al- 
ternative, lumping  everybody  together  and  pretending  they  are  doing 
the  same  thing,  then  discovering  that  only  a  statistical  theory  will  fit 
the  data,  is  a  pure  example  of  looking  for  the  wallet  only  where  the 
light  is  good.  The  kind  of  memorization  that  we  are  considering  here 
is  a  process  that  goes  on  in  one  nervous  system  at  a  time,  and  the  only 
way  to  study  it  is  to  see  what  each  individual  is  doing.  Only  after  that 
detailed  look  at  each  individual's  strategy  should  we  begin  to  recite 
the  general  features  that  characterize  everyone. 

The  organizing,  or  planning,  operations  in  memorization  are 
perhaps  easier  to  see  and  recognize  when  the  material  to  be  mem- 
orized consists  of  meaningful  discourse,  rather  than  nonsense  syl- 
lables, mazes,  etc.  Imagine  that  you  are  cast  in  a  play  and  that  you 
have  the  job  of  memorizing  your  part.  This  is  a  great  deal  easier  than 
memorizing  nonsense  syllables  because  you  do  not  need  to  search 
for  the  translations  into  words  and  because  the  strings  of  words  fol- 
low, by  and  large,  grammatical  rules  that  you  have  already  learned. 
You  first  note  that  the  play  has  four  acts,  that  you  are  on  in  all  four, 
and  that  your  big  scene  is  in  Act  III.  In  Act  III  you  are  on  at  the  cur- 
tain, and  first  you  talk  to  the  maid  about  having  cocktails  ready  for 
the  guests,  then  there  is  the  fight  with  Caspar,  and  finally  the  big 
love  scene.  In  the  love  scene  there  are  four  attitudes  to  go  through 
successively:  indifference,  interest,  exploration,  and  expression  of 
affection,  ending  with  an  embrace  and  a  kiss.  During  the  indifference 
part,  there  are  about  eight  lines.  In  each  line  are  one  or  more  sen- 
tences. In  each  sentence  are  words,  in  each  word  are  phonemes, 
in  each  phoneme  are  articulatory  movements,  in  each  movement 
are  muscle  twitches.  And  that  is  about  as  far  as  we  can  go.  When  you 
have  memorized  your  part  and  are  ready  for  the  opening  night,  you 
will  have  imposed  just  such  a  hierarchical  structure  on  your  script 
and  you  will  be  able  to  move  around  in  it  without  a  slip.  Your  task 
during  the  performance  will  be  greatly  simplified  by  the  fact  that  you 
are  holding  a  conversation  and  that  the  other  actors  will  be  remem- 
bering the  script  too.  But,  as  every  actor  knows,  there  are  always 
those  deadly  moments  when  someone  skips  ahead  two  pages,  thus 

Plans  for  Remembering  ■   133 


leaving  out  essential  facts  that  the  audience  must  know  in  order  to 
understand  the  play.  Then  the  scramble  begins  to  get  those  missing 
lines  spoken,  somehow,  and  the  most  exciting  part  of  amateur  acting, 
except  for  the  curtain  calls,  is  often  connected  with  this  adventure  of 
trying  to  cover  everything  without  letting  the  audience  know  that 
the  author  did  not  write  it  that  way.  Thus  it  is  possible  to  revise  and 
elaborate  the  Plan  even  after  the  material  has  been  memorized.  (One 
wonders  whether  the  effects  of  skipping  about  during  recitation  might 
not  provide  some  objective  evidence  for  what  the  hierarchical  struc- 
ture really  was.  It  is  essentially  the  technique  used  by  Miiller  and 
Schumann  to  reveal  the  rhythmic  structure  of  a  memorized  list,  and 
by  Thorndike  to  show  the  importance  of  "belonging."  ^) 

When  the  items  to  be  recalled  are  themselves  familiar  words,  the 
learner  is  much  freer  to  devise  ingenious  ways  to  solve  his  problem. 
He  may,  in  fact,  resort  to  mnemonic  devices,  if  he  knows  any.  The 
antagonistic  attitude  of  experimental  psychologists  toward  mnemonic 
devices  is  even  more  violent  than  their  attitude  toward  their  sub- 
ject's word  associations;  mnemonic  devices  are  immoral  tricks  suita- 
ble only  for  evil  gypsies  and  stage  magicians.  As  a  result  of  this 
attitude  almost  nothing  is  known  by  psychologists  about  the  remark- 
able feats  of  memory  that  are  so  easily  performed  when  you  have  a 
Plan  ready  in  advance.  Anecdotes  do  not  contribute  to  science,  of 
course,  but  they  sometimes  facilitate  communication — so  we  shall 
lapse  momentarily  into  a  thoroughly  unscientific  vein. 

One  evening  we  were  entertaining  a  visiting  colleague,  a  social 
psychologist  of  broad  interests,  and  our  discussion  turned  to  Plans. 
"But  exactly  what  is  a  Plan?"  he  asked.  "How  can  you  say  that  mem- 
orizing depends  on  Plans?" 

"We'll  show  you,"  we  replied.  "Here  is  a  Plan  that  you  can  use 
for  memorizing.  Remember  first  that : 

^  For  a  description  of  the  work  of  Miiller  and  Schumann,  see  Robert  S. 
Woodworth,  Experimental  Psychology  (New  York:  Holt,  1938),  pp.  28-30.  Wood- 
worth's  discussion  of  memory  describes  numerous  studies  showing  the  importance 
of  organizational  factors  in  memorization  and  is  probably  the  root  source  of  the 
present  authors'  dissatisfaction  with  much  of  the  contemporary  work  in  this 
field.  "Belonging"  as  an  aid  to  remembering  was  first  discussed  by  E.  L.  Thorn- 
dike  in  The  Fundamentals  of  Learning  (New  York:  Teachers  College,  Columbia 
University,  1932). 

134  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


one  is  a  bun, 
two  is  a  shoe, 
three  is  a  tree, 
four  is  a  door, 
five  is  a  hive, 
six  are  sticks, 
seven  is  heaven, 
eight  is  a  gate, 
nine  is  a  line,  and 
ten  is  a  hen." 

"You  know,  even  though  it  is  only  ten-thirty  here,  my  watch  says 
one-thirty.  I'm  really  tired,  and  I'm  sure  I'll  ruin  your  experiment." 

"Don't  worry,  we  have  no  real  stake  in  it."  We  tightened  our 
grip  on  his  lapel.  "Just  relax  and  remember  the  rhyme.  Now  you  have 
part  of  the  Plan.  The  second  part  works  like  this :  when  we  tell  you  a 
word,  you  must  form  a  ludicrous  or  bizarre  association  with  the  first 
word  in  your  Hst,  and  so  on  wdth  the  ten  words  we  recite  to  you." 

"Really,  you  know,  it'll  never  work.  I'm  awfuUy  tired,"  he  re- 
plied. 

"Have  no  fear,"  we  answered,  "just  remember  the  rhyme  and 
then  form  the  association.  Here  are  the  words: 

1.  ashtray, 

2.  firewood, 

3.  picture, 

4.  cigarette, 

5.  table, 

6.  matchbook, 

7.  glass, 

8.  lamp, 

9.  shoe, 

10.  phonograph." 

The  words  were  read  one  at  a  time,  and  after  reading  the  word,  we 
waited  until  he  announced  that  he  had  the  association.  It  took  about 
five  seconds  on  the  average  to  form  the  connection.  After  the  seventh 

Plans  for  Remembering  ■   135 


word  he  said  that  he  was  sure  the  first  six  were  already  forgotten.  But 
we  persevered. 

After  one  trial  through  the  list,  we  waited  a  minute  or  two  so 
that  he  could  collect  himself  and  ask  any  questions  that  came  to 
mind.  Then  we  said,  "What  is  number  eight?" 

He  stared  blankly,  and  then  a  smile  crossed  his  face,  "I'll  be 
damned,"  he  said.  "It's  lamp.'  " 

"And  what  number  is  cigarette?" 

He  laughed  outright  now,  and  then  gave  the  correct  answer. 

"And  there  is  no  strain,"  he  said,  "absolutely  no  sweat." 

We  proceeded  to  demonstrate  that  he  could  in  fact  name  every 
word  correctly,  and  then  asked,  "Do  you  think  that  memorizing  con- 
sists of  piling  up  increments  of  response  strength  that  accumulate  as 
the  words  are  repeated?"  The  question  was  lost  in  his  amazement. 

If  so  simple  a  Plan  can  reduce  the  difficulty  of  memorizing  by  a 
discriminable  amount,  is  it  not  reasonable  to  suppose  that  subjects 
in  a  memorization  experiment  would  also  try  to  develop  a  Plan?  Of 
course,  they  do  not  have  a  ready-made  Plan  of  the  kind  just  described. 
It  takes  subjects  some  time  and  some  effort  to  construct  Plans  that 
will  work  for  the  sort  of  materials  that  we  like  to  use  in  psychologi- 
cal experiments.  In  tests  of  immediate  memory,  for  example,  sub- 
jects seldom  try  any  mnemonic  tricks — with  only  one  presentation 
of  the  material,  there  is  little  time  to  develop  a  Plan  and  little  need 
for  it,  since  the  material  will  never  be  seen  again.  But  without  a  Plan 
of  some  sort,  the  subject  will  never  be  able  to  recite  a  long  list. 

W.  H.  Wallace,  S.  H.  Turner,  and  C.  C.  Perkins  of  the  University 
of  Pennsylvania  have  found  that  a  person's  capacity  for  forming  as- 
sociations is  practically  unlimited.^  They  presented  pairs  of  English 
words  to  their  subjects,  who,  proceeding  at  their  own  pace,  formed  a 
visual  image  connecting  the  two  words.  The  list  of  paired  associates 
was  given  only  once.  Then  the  subjects  were  given  one  member  of 
each  pair  and  asked  to  write  the  other.  Starting  with  lists  of  twenty- 
five  pairs  they  worked  up  to  lists  of  700  pairs  of  words.  Up  to  500 
pairs,  the  subjects  were  remembering  about  ninety -nine  percent;  at 

8  Wallace  H.  Wallace,  Stanley  H.  Turner,  and  Cornelius  C.  Perkins,  Pre- 
liminary Studies  of  Human  Information  Storage,  Signal  Corps  Project  No.  132C, 
Institute  for  Cooperative  Research,  University  of  Pennsylvania,  December  1957. 

136  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


700  pairs  it  dropped  to  ninety-five  percent.  Ordinarily  the  subjects 
used  about  twenty-five  seconds  to  form  the  association,  but  when 
they  had  become  more  experienced  they  could  work  accurately  with 
less  than  five  seconds  per  pair.  The  subjects  were  not  selected  for 
their  special  abilities;  they  were  ordinary  people,  conveniently  avail- 
able for  the  experiment.  Freed  of  the  necessity  to  translate  the  items 
into  familiar  form,  freed  of  the  necessity  to  organize  them  by  a  Plan 
into  a  fixed  sequence,  freed  of  the  necessity  to  work  at  a  mechanically 
fixed  pace,  the  subjects  had  nothing  to  do  but  sit  there  and  form  con- 
nections— and  they  did  it  almost  without  error  until  both  they  and 
the  experimenters  ran  out  of  patience.  What  is  more,  little  had  been 
forgotten  two  or  three  days  later. 

But  what  of  the  traditional  picture  of  an  association  as  some- 
thing to  be  constructed  slowly  through  frequent  contiguity  and 
strengthened  repeatedly  by  reinforcement?  Slowly  waxing  and 
waning  associations  may  be  useful  to  characterize  a  conditioned 
salivary  reflex,  but  they  are  not  characteristic  of  human  verbal  learn- 
ing. Irvin  Rock  has  succeeded  in  demonstrating  that  in  learning 
paired  associates  there  is  no  increment  in  associative  strength  until 
the  first  correct  response  occurs,  and  that  thereafter  the  association 
remains  fully  available  to  the  learner.^  Thus,  the  memorization  of  a 
list  of  paired  associates  is  not  delayed  if,  every  time  a  pair  is  not  re- 
called, a  new  pair  is  substituted  in  its  place.  In  fact,  subjects  do  not 
even  notice  that  a  substitution  has  been  made.  The  association  is  not 
formed  until  the  trial  on  which  the  learner  has  time  to  consider  the 
pair  of  items;  then  it  is  formed  and  remembered  throughout  the  re- 
mainder of  the  learning. 

Observations  such  as  these  suggest  that  it  is  not  storage,  but 
retrieval,  that  is  the  real  bottleneck  in  verbal  learning.  Building  the 
connections  seems  to  be  far  simpler  than  finding  them  later.  A  new 
association  leading  from  A  to  B  becomes  merely  one  of  many  asso- 
ciations leading  from  A  to  something  else.  The  time  and  effort  that 
goes  into  a  job  of  memorization  is  devoted  to  ensuring  that  there  will 
be  some  way  to  get  access  to  the  particular  association  we  want  when 

®  Irvin  Rock,  The  role  of  repetition  in  associative  learning,  American  Journal 
of  Psychology,  1957,  70,  186-193;  Irvin  Rock  and  Walter  Heimer,  Further  evi- 
dence of  one-trial  associative  learning,  American  Journal  of  Psychology,  1959, 
72,  1-16. 

Plans  for  Remembering  ■   137 


the  time  comes  to  revive  it.  In  this  view  of  the  problem,  the  mem- 
orizer's  task  is  quite  similar  to  a  librarian's.  In  a  large  library  it  is  es- 
sential to  have  books  labeled  by  a  code  and  filed  on  a  shelf  according 
to  that  code.  If  a  book  is  moved  accidentally  to  another  shelf,  it  may 
remain  lost  for  years.  The  librarian  must  mark  the  volumes,  place 
them  on  the  shelves  in  the  correct  places,  enter  cards  into  the  central 
directory  under  two  or  three  different  schemes  of  reference — all  that 
labor  adds  nothing  to  the  information  or  entertainment  contained  in 
the  book,  but  merely  ensures  that  it  may  be  possible  to  locate  the 
book  when  its  contents  are  relevant. 

Memorizing  is  much  too  complex  to  lie  open  to  such  a  simple 
analogy.  The  memorizer  is  more  hke  a  librarian  who  writes  all  his 
own  books  and  is  his  own  reading  public.  The  point  of  the  metaphor 
is  simply  that  there  is  a  great  deal  more  to  a  memory — either  in  a  li- 
brary or  a  cranium — than  the  simple  hooking  of  things  together  two 
at  a  time.  Let  us  imagine  that  this  hooking  operation  is  available 
and  that  it  is  as  cheap  and  easy  as  it  would  have  to  be  to  support  the 
discursive  human  intellect.  What  do  we  do  with  it?  Given  that  we 
can  nail  two  boards  together,  how  do  we  build  a  house? 


138  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


CHAPTER  11 


PLANS   FOR  SPEAKING 


How  much  emphasis  to  place  on  language  has  always  been 
something  of  a  problem  for  psychologists.  On  the  one  hand,  it  is  obvi- 
ous that  men  are  quite  different  from  other  animals  and  that  most 
of  the  differences  have  their  origin  in  man's  verbal  behavior.  It  is 
difficult  to  realize  the  full  extent  to  which  our  mental  accomplish- 
ments as  human  beings  are  evoked  in  us  by  learning  to  speak.  But,  on 
the  other  hand,  the  suggestion  that  men  are  very  different  seems  like 
an  anthropocentric  retreat  to  pre-Darwinian  dogmatism  and  medie- 
val mysticism.  How  is  it  possible  to  recognize  man's  unique  accom- 
plishments without  violating  the  concept  of  evolutionary  continuity 
from  animals  to  man? 

One  solution  to  this  dilemma — and  perhaps  it  is  the  simplest — 
is  to  argue  that  words  are  just  like  other  responses,  only  more  so.  For 
instance : 

The  essence  of  words  is  that  they  summarize  many  past  ex- 
periences into  a  manageable  unit;  that  is,  they  produce  or  repre- 
sent a  temporal  integration  of  many  diverse  experiences.  The 
use  of  words  as  a  tool  of  thinking  or  reasoning  or  problem- 
solving,  therefore,  means  that  a  huge  number  of  past  experi- 

Plans  for  Speaking  ■    139 


ences  are  being  effective  in  determining  present  behavior.  Lan- 
guage, or  verbal  mediating  responses,  represents  an  instance  of 
extremely  efficient  central  integration  with  which  we,  as  edu- 
cated human  adults,  are  especially  familiar.  But  language  does 
not  seem  to  introduce  any  really  new  psychological  process;  it 
may  be  thought  of,  rather,  as  an  instrumental  means  or  tech- 
nique which  enormously  increases  the  speed  and  efficiency  of 
processes  already  present  to  some  extent  in  nonverbalizing  ani- 
mals.^ 

In  short,  language  is  nothing  but  an  extremely  complicated  in- 
stance of  behavioral  processes  that  might  better  be  studied  in  their 
simpler  manifestations  in  animals.  Some  psychologists,  however, 
carry  this  line  of  reasoning  a  step  further  and  insist  that  it  must  be 
studied  with  animals.  They  argue  that  unless  you  can  phrase  your 
questions  about  man  in  such  a  way  that  the  same  questions  could  be 
asked  of  animals,  you  have  not  gotten  to  the  heart  of  your  problem. 
Thus,  for  example,  they  are  willing  to  study  brightness  discrimina- 
tion in  man  because  the  same  experiment  can  be  conducted  with  ani- 
mals, but  they  will  not  ask  a  man  to  estimate  numerical  magnitudes 
of  brightness  because  no  one  knows  how  that  instruction  could  be 
given  to  a  dumb  beast.  If  words  are  needed  to  impart  the  instructions, 
so  the  argument  runs,  we  cannot  know  whether  the  results  are  gen- 
erated by  the  subject's  history  of  verbal  conditioning  or  by  the 
stimulus  magnitudes  he  is  asked  to  estimate.  Unless  an  inarticulate 
animal  can  be  used  as  the  subject,  the  experiment  is  certain  to  run 
aground  on  the  treacherous  shoals  of  introspection  from  which  psy- 
chology has  only  too  recently  escaped. 

1  Henry  W.  Nissen,  Axes  of  behavioral  comparison,  in  A.  Roe  and  G.  G. 
Simpson,  eds..  Behavior  and  Evolution  (New  Haven:  Yale  University  Press, 
1958).  Similar  sentiments  have  been  expressed  by  many  other  American  students 
of  animal  behavior.  However,  Russian  psychologists  have,  by  and  large,  been 
keenly  aware  of  the  extent  to  which  speech  supports  novel  psychological  proc- 
esses in  human  beings.  See,  for  example,  A.  R.  Luria  and  F.  la.  Yudovich,  Speech 
and  the  Development  of  Mental  Processes  in  the  Child.  (Trans.,  Joan  Simon) 
(London:  Staples,  1959).  Those  authors  write  (p.  11-12)  that,  "Study  of  the 
child's  mental  processes  as  the  product  of  his  intercommunication  with  the 
environment,  as  the  acquisition  of  common  experiences  transmitted  by  speech, 
has,  therefore,  become  the  most  important  principle  of  Soviet  psychology  which 
informs  all  research.  .  .  .  Intercommunication  with  adults  is  of  decisive  im- 
portance because  the  acquisition  of  a  language  system  involves  a  reorganisation 
of  aU  the  child's  basic  mental  processes;  the  word  thus  becomes  a  tremendous 
factor  which  forms  mental  activity,  perfecting  the  reflection  of  reahty  and 
creating  new  forms  of  attention,  of  memory  and  imagination,  of  thought  and 
action." 

140  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


The  psychologists  who  make  this  argument  are,  of  course,  a 
small  minority.  But  they  are  a  tough-minded  group  who  are  hard  at 
work  proving  that  psychology  can  be  an  experimental  science.  They 
know  what  data  look  like,  they  have  high  standards  for  what  they 
will  accept  as  evidence,  and  one  violates  their  prejudices  at  one's  own 
risk.  In  this  matter,  however,  they  have  drawn  the  boundaries  of  sci- 
entific acceptability  too  narrowly.  Consider  their  proposition :  "A  psy- 
chological process  has  not  been  fully,  scientifically  understood  until 
it  has  been  analyzed  into  component  parts  that  can  be  studied  experi- 
mentally in  animals."  One  feels  intuitively  that  there  is  something 
profoundly  backward  in  such  an  approach  to  the  study  of  man — noth- 
ing we  ask  about  animals  would  have  the  slightest  interest  to  anyone 
except  in  terms  of  standards  imposed  by  the  articulate,  discursive 
intellect  of  man.  The  proposition  is  a  challenge  to  search  for  ex- 
ceptions— to  search  for  some  problem  of  human  significance  that 
psychologists  must  understand,  but  one  that  cannot  be  studied  experi- 
mentally in  animals.  Or,  to  phrase  the  challenge  in  terms  of  the  pre- 
ceding quotation,  is  there  any  new  and  important  psychological  proc- 
ess that  is  introduced  by  language  and  that  cannot  be  thought  of  as  a 
technique  to  increase  the  efficiency  of  inarticulate  processes? 

No  doubt  there  are  many  uniquely  human  problems  we  might 
choose,  but  the  issues  are  illustrated  sufficiently  well  by  the  problem 
of  death.  Man  is  the  only  animal  that  knows  he  is  going  to  die. 
Should  this  be  considered  as  a  new  and  important  psychological 
process  introduced  by  language?  Or  is  it  just  an  improvement  on 
nonverbal  processes?  A  man  can  make  his  death  a  part  of  his  Plans, 
as  when  he  buys  life  insurance  policies  or  draws  a  will,  or  he  can  even 
devise  and  execute  a  Plan  that  intends  his  own  death.  Indeed,  we  oc- 
casionally hear  it  said  that  a  truly  rational  man  would  commit  suicide 
immediately.  But  whatever  one's  evaluation  of  life,  it  must  be  ad- 
mitted that  the  expectation  of  death  provides  a  persistent  theme  in  our 
art  and  literature,  that  it  creates  our  estate-planning  and  life-in- 
surance industry,  that  it  motivates  us  to  support  our  medical  and 
public  health  authorities,  that  it  is  the  foundation  for  much  of  our 
religion,  that  the  fear  of  death  is  to  the  old  what  lust  is  to  the  young — 
in  short,  the  anticipation  of  death  influences  our  behavior  in  many 
pervasive  ways.  In  order  to  understand  human  behavior  and  human 

Plans  for  Speaking  ■    141 


institutions,  therefore,  it  is  necessary  to  know  something  about  the 
way  men  look  forward  to  their  own  deaths  and  prepare  for  the  Hfe 
they  anticipate  after  death.  But  in  order  to  study  this  important  psy- 
chological phenomenon  we  must,  according  to  the  proposition  we  are 
considering,  reduce  it  to  "component  parts  that  can  be  studied  experi- 
mentally in  animals."  Could  we  impart  to  a  rat  the  knowledge  that  his 
death  is  inevitable?  We  can  teach  an  animal  to  recognize  certain 
signs  and  to  perform  certain  tricks,  but  the  knowledge  that  all  living 
creatures  are  mortal  seems  to  be  reserved  for  man  alone.  The  antici- 
pation of  death  cannot  be  studied  with  animals;  therefore,  according 
to  the  proposition,  the  effects  on  behavior  of  the  anticipation  of 
death  cannot  be  studied  scientifically.^  The  boundaries  of  science 
must  be  broader  than  that! 

In  the  past,  whenever  psychologists  have  encountered  meth- 
odological strictures  against  studying  something  that  interested 
them,  it  was  the  stricture  they  gave  up,  not  their  interest.  Presumably, 
that  attitude  will  continue  and  psychologists  will  persist  in  asking 
questions  about  human  beings  that  would  not  be  appropriate  or  even 
intelligible  if  directed  toward  animals.  Let  us  hope  so,  for  human 
speech  has  provided  man  with  a  new  mechanism  of  evolution  that  in 
a  few  brief  centuries  has  set  him  apart  from  all  other  animals.  The 
jealous  guardian  of  Darwinian  continuity  merely  blinds  himself  to 
the  obvious  facts.  Almost  nothing  we  could  say  about  the  psychologi- 

"  Which  may  help  to  explain  why  the  matter  has  been  so  neglected  by  psy- 
chologists. (See  I.  E.  Alexander,  R.  S.  Colley,  and  A.  M.  Alderstein,  Is  death  a 
matter  of  indifference?  Journal  of  Psychology,  1957,  43,  277-283).  The  anticipa- 
tion of  death  is  something  of  a  special  problem  for  healthy-minded  reflex  theo- 
rists in  any  case.  With  a  purely  inductive  conception  of  knowledge,  it  must  be 
difficult  to  understand  how  the  conditioning  provided  by  25,000  dawns  could 
lead  to  anything  but  the  conviction  of  immortality.  It  might  be  explained  away  in 
terms  of  the  conditioning  provided  by  the  deaths  of  acquaintances,  were  it  not 
for  the  fact  that  our  society  shields  us  so  carefully  from  the  emotionally  disturb- 
ing sight  of  a  dead  body.  (See  D.  O  Hebb  and  W.  R.  Thompson,  The  social  sig- 
nificance of  animal  studies,  in  G.  Lindzey,  ed..  Handbook  of  Social  Psychology, 
Vol.  1  [Cambridge:  Addison-Wesley,  1954],  p.  557.)  Most  of  our  acquaintances 
disappear  sooner  or  later,  but  in  modern  societies  we  do  not  see  them  die  except 
in  unusual  circumstances — war,  catastrophe,  or  the  like.  Where  could  anything 
so  morbid  as  the  anticipation  of  one's  own  death  take  root  and  grow  until  it  be- 
came one  of  the  fundamental  truths  of  our  mental  life?  (See  Sylvia  Anthony,  The 
Child's  Discovery  of  Death  [New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace,  1940].)  In  neglecting 
this  problem,  psychologists  conform  to  a  general  taboo  on  death  that  must  be 
alnaost  as  strong  in  our  society  today  as  was  the  taboo  on  sex  during  the  Victorian 
era.  (See  S.  Freud,  Beyond  the  Pleasure  Principle  [London:  Hogarth  Press, 
1950].) 

142  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


cal  importance  of  language  could  be  too  extravagant — the  specula- 
tions in  Chapter  8  about  the  mechanism  of  hypnosis  should  suggest 
how  crucial  the  present  authors  consider  speech  to  be  in  controlling 
all  the  psychological  processes  in  a  human  being. 

The  most  important  benefit  we  obtain  from  our  capacity  to  rep- 
resent things  and  events  in  verbal  form,  of  course,  is  the  capacity  to 
share  in  and  profit  from  the  experience  of  others,  living  and  dead. 
As  a  consequence,  the  Image  we  construct  extends  much  farther  than 
the  bounds  of  our  own  experience  and  incorporates  the  conclusions 
of  the  great  thinkers  and  explorers  who  have  preceded  us  and  have 
helped  to  shape  our  conception  of  the  universe  and  of  ourselves. 
But  we  also  benefit  from  communicable  Plans  as  well  as  from 
communicable  Images.  Skills  are  normally  tacit,  but  by  careful 
analysis  and  investigation  we  are  often  able  to  discover  the  principles 
underlying  them  and  to  formulate  verbal  instructions  for  communi- 
cating the  skills  to  someone  else.  Our  cultural  heritage  includes  know- 
ing hoiu  as  well  as  knowing  ivhat.  To  explore  these  matters  with  the 
attention  they  deserve,  however,  would  require  a  general  psychology 
of  knowledge — a  far  more  ambitious  project  than  the  present  authors 
are  prepared  to  undertake. 

A  project  of  more  reasonable  proportions  for  a  scientist  to  con- 
sider concerns  the  description  of  the  speech  skill  itself,  divorced  from 
the  cultural  role  that  the  skill  fulfills  or  the  content  that  the  skill  may 
enable  us  to  convey.  That  is  to  say,  instead  of  considering  how  speech 
is  used  to  accomplish  other  things,  let  us  consider  in  this  chapter 
how  linguistically  acceptable  sequences  of  sounds  are  themselves 
planned  and  executed. 

At  the  motor  extremities  of  the  speech  act,  of  course,  are  the 
marvelously  delicate,  swift,  and  synchronized  movements  of  the 
tongue,  teeth,  lips,  and  velum.  These  coordinations  comprise  the  sub- 
ject matter  of  physiological  phonetics  and  of  phonology — although 
their  study  is  fascinating,  they  do  not  raise  psychological  issues  of 
the  type  we  are  considering  in  these  pages.  Let  us  move  upward  in 
the  hierarchical  organization  of  the  speech  skill,  therefore,  until  we 
come  to  more  molar  units  organized  by  a  relatively  more  strategic 
part  of  the  Plan.  That  is  to  say,  let  us  move  up  into  the  level  that 
might  loosely  be  termed  "grammatical." 

Plans  for  Speaking  ■   143 


We  propose,  now,  to  wander  briefly  into  the  domain  of  modem 
linguistics.  The  authors  do  not  desire,  nor  are  they  competent,  to 
summarize  hnguistic  science.^  Instead,  we  shall  select  the  work  of  a 
single  linguist  and  follow  it  slavishly.  Our  selection  is  based  upon  the 
fact  that  this  linguist  seems  to  agree  so  well  with  our  own  ideas  about 
how  human  behavior  in  general,  not  merely  in  speech,  is  organized. 
(The  agreement  is  not  accidental,  since  many  of  our  own  ideas  were 
stimulated  by  his  example.)  The  linguist  whose  ideas  we  shall  ex- 
ploit is  Noam  Chomsky,  and  the  ideas  are  presented  summarily  in  his 
monograph.  Syntactic  Structures.^  From  considerations  of  grammar 
and  syntax  we  hope  to  be  able  to  gather  some  impression  of  how 
complicated  the  planning  device  must  be  in  order  to  generate  gram- 
matical sentences.  This  result  should  provide  a  sort  of  lower  bound 
for  the  complexity  of  the  human  planning  equipment  in  general,  for 
nonverbal  as  well  as  for  verbal  planning. 

Sentences  must  be  uttered  one  word  at  a  time.  Does  that  fact 
imply  that  they  form  a  simple  chain?  That  is  to  say,  is  the  next  word 
in  the  sentence  chosen  exclusively  on  the  basis  of  preceding  words? 
Or,  is  it  chosen  on  the  basis  of  words  that  will  follow  as  well  as  words 
that  have  preceded  it?  Certainly  introspection  tells  us  we  have  very 
definite  expectations  about  what  we  are  going  to  say — our  choice  of 
words  depends  upon  much  more  than  the  history  of  our  utterance. 
We  have  a  Plan  for  the  sentence,  and  as  we  execute  it  we  have  rela- 
tively clear  impressions  of  what  we  are  going  to  say.  William  James 
described  it  far  better  than  we  can : 

And  has  the  reader  never  asked  himself  what  kind  of  a 
mental  fact  is  his  intention  of  saying  a  thing  before  he  has  said 
it?  It  is  an  entirely  definite  intention,  distinct  from  all  other  in- 
tentions, an  absolutely  distinct  state  of  consciousness,  therefore; 
and  yet  how  much  of  it  consists  of  definite  sensorial  images, 
either  of  words  or  of  things?  Hardly  anything!  Linger,  and  the 
words  and  things  come  into  the  mind;  the  anticipatory  intention, 
the  divination  is  there  no  more.  But  as  the  words  that  replace  it 
arrive,  it  welcomes  them  successively  and  calls  them  right  if 
they  agree  with  it,  it  rejects  them  and  calls  them  v^ong  if  they 

s  An  excellent  introduction  to  the  problems  and  methods  of  linguistics  can 
be  found  in  H.  A.  Gleason,  An  Introduction  to  Descriptive  Linguistics  (New  York: 
Holt,  1955). 

*  Noam  Chomsky,  Syntactic  Structures  (The  Hague:  Mouton,  1957). 

144  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


do  not.  It  has  therefore  a  nature  of  its  own  of  the  most  positive 
sort,  and  yet  what  can  we  say  about  it  without  using  words  that 
belong  to  the  later  mental  facts  that  replace  it?  The  intention 
to  say  so  and  so  is  the  only  name  it  can  receive.  One  may  admit 
that  a  good  third  of  our  psychic  life  consists  in  these  rapid  pre- 
monitory perspective  views  of  schemes  of  thought  not  yet  articu- 
late.= 

James  is  describing  a  state  of  consciousness  associated  with  an  in- 
tention to  execute  a  Plan.  The  Plan  of  the  sentence,  it  seems,  must  be 
determined  in  a  general  way  even  before  it  is  differentiated  into  the 
particular  words  that  we  are  going  to  utter. 

Introspection  is  a  fickle  mistress,  as  every  psychologist  knows  all 
too  well.  Before  trying  to  invent  some  elaborate,  anticipatory  device 
for  thinking  about  everything  simultaneously,  one  should  first  ex- 
plore the  simpler  possibilities.  Let  us  try,  therefore,  to  ignore  our  in- 
trospections, to  forget  the  discussion  of  Plans,  and  to  pretend  that  the 
next  word  in  our  utterance  will  depend  only  upon  the  words  that  have 
led  up  to  it,  but  not  upon  any  Plan  for  the  words  that  may  follow  it.  A 
nonanticipatory  grammar  would  be  exceedingly  simple  and,  since  the 
mathematics  of  those  systems  has  been  carefully  studied  under  the 
general  topic  of  "Markov  processes,"  we  would  immediately  know  a 
great  deal  about  the  level  of  complexity  of  the  sentence  generator 
itself.^  Moreover,  such  a  grammar  would  permit  a  very  simple  cor- 
respondence between  language-as-the-talker-generates-it  and  lan- 
guage-as-the-listener-receives-it.  The  listener  can  know  only  the  past 
words  of  the  sentence;  he  must  make  probabilistic  inferences  about 
its  future  developments.  One  might  argue  that,  since  the  Ustener 
seems  to  need  this  probabilistic,  "Markovian"  equipment  anyhow,  it 
would  be  economical  to  let  him  use  it  when  he  stops  hstening  and 
starts  talking.  But  Hfe,  unfortunately,  is  not  always  as  simple  as  we 

sw^illiam  James,  The  Principles  of  Psychology,  Vol.  I  (New  York:  Holt, 
1890),  p.  253. 

6  The  use  of  Markov  processes  to  describe  the  message  source  is  taken  from 
C.  E.  Shannon,  A  mathematical  theory  of  communication,  Bell  System  Technical 
Journal,  1948,  27,  379^23.  These  ideas  were  made  the  basis  of  a  grammatical 
theory  by  Charles  F.  Hockett,  A  Manual  of  Phonology,  Indiana  University  Publi- 
cations in  Anthropology  and  Linguistics,  Memoir  11,  1955.  Some  of  the  structural, 
or  nonstochastic,  aspects  of  these  message  sources  are  described  by  Noam 
Chomsky  and  George  A.  Miller,  Finite  state  languages,  Information  and  Control, 
1958,  1,  91-112. 

Plans  for  Speaking  "145 


think  it  should  be.  It  turns  out  that  introspection  is  right,  that  purely 
historical  models  of  the  sentence  source  are  too  simple  to  account  for 
the  facts.  The  difficulties  are  instructive  to  anyone  who  would  try 
to  use  simple  stochastic  chains  of  behavioral  events  as  a  general  de- 
scription of  human  behavior/ 

There  are  two  lines  of  argument  calculated  to  dissuade  one  from 
using  a  left-to-right  model  of  the  sentence  planner.  One  line  is  to  show 
that  it  would  be  impossible  to  learn  a  language  in  that  way.  The  other 
illustrates  grammatical  constructions  that  such  a  message  source 
could  not  produce. 

Suppose  that  we  would  like  to  learn  how  to  generate  and  recog- 
nize all  grammatical  sentences  up  to  some  fixed  length,  say,  twenty 
words.  Information  theorists  tell  us  that  English  sentences  carry 
about  five  bits  per  word  on  the  average,^  so  we  can  guess  that  there 
must  be  about  2^°°  different  strings  twenty  words  long  that  we  should 
learn  how  to  cope  with.  It  seems  reasonable  to  assume  that  each  of 
these  2^°°  different  sequences  would  leave  the  system  in  a  different 
internal  state.  In  order  to  incorporate  the  ability  to  generate  a  particu- 
lar one  of  these  strings  of  words  into  our  planner — to  create  one  of 
the  2^°°  different  internal  states  that  would  be  required — the  planner 
would  have  to  hear  the  string  at  least  once.  That  is  to  say,  our  left- 
to-right  generator  has  no  grammatical  rules  other  than  the  ones  that 
say,  "Having  produced  the  words  X  up  to  this  point,  you  must  choose 
your  continuation  from  the  set  {Y}."  In  order  for  a  child  to  learn 
all  of  the  rules  of  this  left-to-right  variety  that  would  be  required  for 
the  generation  of  perfectly  acceptable  sentences  of  twenty  words  or 
less,  he  would  have  to  hear  the  rule,  or  hear  instances  of  it  from 
which  the  rule  would  be  derived.  Thus  there  seems  no  alternative 
but  to  insist  that  a  child  must  hear  2^°°  sentences  before  he  can 
speak  and  understand  Enghsh.  That  is  about  10^°  sentences.  In  order 
to  appreciate  how  ridiculous  this  condition  is,  recall  the  fact  that 

7  Eugene  Galanter  and  George  A.  Miller,  Some  comments  on  stochastic 
models  and  psychological  theories,  in  K.  J.  Arrow,  S.  Karlin,  and  P.  Suppes,  eds.. 
Proceedings  of  the  First  Stanford  Symposium  on  Mathematical  Methods  in  the 
Social  Sciences  (Stanford:   Stanford  University  Press,  1960  [in  press]). 

s  This  is  a  conservative  estimate  based  on  Shannon's  data  for  letters.  See 
C.  E.  Shannon,  Prediction  and  entropy  of  printed  EngUsh,  Bell  System  Technical 
Journal,  1951,  30,  50-64.  Repeated  by  N.  G.  Burton  and  J.  C.  R.  Licklider,  Long- 
range  constraints  in  the  statistical  structure  of  printed  English,  American  Jour- 
nal of  Psychology,  1955,  68,  650-653. 

146  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


there  are  only  about  3.15  X  10"  seconds  per  century.  In  short,  the 
child  would  have  to  hear  about  3  X  10-"  sentences  per  second  in 
order  to  be  exposed  to  all  the  information  necessary  for  the  planner 
to  produce  sentences  according  to  these  left-to-right  rules  of  grammar, 
and  that  is  on  the  assumption  of  a  childhood  100  years  long  with  no 
interruptions  for  sleeping,  eating,  etc.,  and  perfect  retention  of  every 
string  of  twenty  words  after  one  presentation!  Just  a  little  calculation 
will  convince  anyone  that  the  number  of  internal  states  needed  in  a 
left-to-right  system  explodes  before  the  system  is  capable  of  dealing 
with  anything  as  complicated  as  a  natural  language,  and  that  some 
other  kind  of  sentence  generator  must  be  used. 

Even  if  there  were  time  to  learn  it  all,  the  system  we  have  im- 
agined would  not  generate  the  set  of  sentences  that  native  speakers 
of  English  recognize  as  grammatical.  We  set  the  upper  limit  at  length 
20 — we  had  to  set  it  somewhere — but  there  are  many  grammatical 
sentences  longer  than  20  words  that  the  Markovian  process  could  not 
generate  and,  conversely,  the  Markovian  process  would  generate 
many  strings  longer  than  20  words  that  would  not  be  grammatical 
sentences.  The  model  says  something  like  this:  Memorize  verbatim 
all  grammatical  sentences  and  segments  of  sentences  of  20  words 
or  less  in  length,  and  then  make  longer  utterances  by  fitting  together 
these  20-word  segments  in  all  possible  ways.  If  the  rules  for  generat- 
ing sentences  were  represented  in  this  form  in  somebody's  brain, 
there  would  be  grammatical  sentences  longer  than  20  words  that  he 
would  not  be  able  to  recognize.  If  we  raise  the  length  to,  say,  30  or  40 
words,  the  task  of  learning  the  language  becomes  progressively  more 
inconceivable  and  in  the  limit,  when  we  demand  that  a  child  must 
memorize  all  sentences  of  every  length,  the  notion  reaches  the  ex- 
tremes of  absurdity.  It  is  like  learning  the  number  system  by  memo- 
rizing all  possible  sequences  of  digits.  To  memorize  the  infinite  num- 
ber of  grammatical  sentences  is  to  by-pass  the  problem  of  grammar 
completely. 

The  model  is  so  unnatural  that  one  is  encouraged  to  search  for 
a  counterexample,  a  proof  that  a  Markovian  word  generator  with  a 
finite  number  of  internal  states  could  not  produce  the  set  of  all  gram- 
matical sentences.  The  counterexample  for  left-to-right  grammars 
consists  of  showdng  that  sentences  can  be  grammatically  embedded 

Plans  for  Speaking  ■    147 


inside  other  sentences.^  Consider  the  sentence,  "The  man  who  said 
X  is  here."  Now  we  can  substitute  for  X  the  sentence,  "Either  Y,  or  I 
quit."  Let  Y  be  the  sentence,  "If  Z,  then  it  will  rain."  And  so  we  can 
continue  indefinitely.  Note  that  in  each  case  there  is  a  grammatical 
dependency  extending  across  the  sentence  to  be  inserted.  In  the  first, 
man  and  is  are  related  and  are  separated  by  X.  In  the  second,  either 
and  or  are  related  and  are  separated  by  Y.  In  the  third  if  and  then  are 
related  and  are  separated  by  Z.  And  so  on.  In  more  abbreviated  nota- 
tion, we  have  S  =  aXa',  then  X  =  bYb',  then  Y  =  cZc',  etc.,  so  that 
when  the  sentence  Plan  is  executed  we  obtain  S  =  ahcZc'h'a'.  In  short, 
English  grammar  permits  us  to  construct  an  indefinitely  long  se- 
quence of  these  nested  dependencies.  (Such  sentences  are  hard  to 
understand,  of  course,  but  it  is  only  human  weakness,  not  grammar, 
that  militates  against  them.)  The  problem  is,  however,  that  we  can- 
not generate  such  sentences  with  a  purely  historical,  left-to-right, 
type  of  message  source.  Since  there  can  be  an  indefinitely  large  num- 
ber of  nested  dependencies  (no  rule  of  grammar  prohibits  them),  all 
of  which  must  be  remembered  in  the  right  order  and  simultaneously, 
the  left-to-right  sentence  generator  must  have  an  indefinitely  large 
memory,  that  is,  an  indefinitely  large  number  of  internal  states.  But 
indefinitely  large  memories  are  not  currently  available,  in  biological 
systems  or  elsewhere,  so  the  left-to-right  system  must  be  unable  to 
form  certain  grammatical  sentences. ^°  Q.E.D.  Chains  of  words  will 
not  suffice. 

s  N.  Chomsky,  Three  models  for  the  description  of  language,  IRE  Transac- 
tions on  Information  Theory,  1956,  Vol.  IT-2,  No.  3,  pp.  113-124;  On  certain 
formal  properties  of  grammars,  Information  and  Control,  1959,  137-167. 

10  Victor  Yngve  has  noted,  in  A  model  and  an  hypothesis  about  language 
structure,  Proceedings  of  the  American  Philosophical  Society  (in  press),  that 
grammatical  sentences  must  be  generated  by  human  beings  who  have  a  limited 
span  of  immediate  memory;  although  there  is  no  grammatical  rule  that  limits 
the  number  of  nested  dependencies  in  an  English  sentence,  there  are  psychologi- 
cal limits.  Sentences  with  several  nested  dependencies  are  not  ungrammatical, 
yet  they  are  generally  avoided  in  ordinary  usage.  Yngve  illustrates  the  problem 
with  The  House  that  Jack  Built:  "This  is  the  dog  that  the  cow  tossed"  and 
"This  is  the  cat  that  the  dog  worried"  can  be  combined  into  a  single  sentence, 
"This  is  the  cat  that  the  dog  that  the  cow  tossed  worried,"  a  sentence  with  one 
dependency  (cow  tossed)  nested  inside  another  (dog  worried).  Now,  however, 
if  we  add  a  third  sentence,  "This  is  the  rat  that  the  cat  killed,"  the  triple  com- 
pound becomes,  "This  is  the  rat  that  the  cat  that  the  dog  that  the  cow  tossed 
worried  killed."  One  more  step  in  the  nursery  rhyme  produces  "This  is  the  malt 
that  the  rat  that  the  cat  that  the  dog  that  the  cow  tossed  worried  killed  ate," 
and  grammar  has  clearly  run  riot;  four  dependencies  nested  in  tliis  fashion  are 
totally  unintelligible.   In  order  to  avoid  such  difficulties,  we   do  not   construct 

148  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


Without  laboring  the  point  further,  let  us  assume  that  a  message 
source  can  know  something  about  what  it  is  going  to  say  as  well  as 
about  what  it  has  already  said.  Let  us  imagine  a  scheme  in  which 
the  whole  sentence  is  manipulated  as  a  unit  and  it  is  gradually  de- 
veloped according  to  a  Plan — from  the  inside  out,  so  to  speak.  Let 
us  symbolize  the  whole  sentence  by  the  letter  S.  One  of  the  first 
rules  of  the  grammar  will  be  that  S  can  be  rewritten  as  NP  +  VP, 
where  we  can  think  of  NP  as  a  noun  phrase  and  VP  as  a  verb  phrase. 
This  rule  we  would  write  as 

(Fl)  S >NP  +  VP, 

where  the  arrow  indicates  that  the  symbol  S  can  be  rewritten  as 
NP  +  VP  in  the  derivation  of  the  eventual  utterance.  To  expand  the 
noun  phrase  into  an  article  and  a  noun,  we  might  write 

(F2)  NP >  T  +  Noun, 

and  to  expand  the  verb  phrase  into  a  verb  and  a  noun  phrase  we 
might  write 

(  F3  )  VP >  Verb  +  NP. 

(In  a  complete  grammar,  of  course,  there  would  have  to  be  several 
alternative  ways  to  expand  NP  and  VP,  but  we  wish  to  keep  this  ex- 
ample as  simple  as  possible.)  We  have  enough  English  grammar  to 
complete  the  illustration,  so  let  us  add  a  few  rules  about  vocabulary: 

(F4)  T         >  SL,  the. 

(F5)  Noun >  boy,  ball,  stick. 

(F6)  Verb    >  hit. 

Now  turn  the  grammatical  machine  loose  and  see  what  it  pro- 
duces. In  order  to  get  it  started,  feed  it  an  S — tell  it  to  speak.  The 
only  thing  it  can  do  with  S  is  to  apply  rule  Fl  to  it.  The  result  is  dia- 
grammed in  Figure  6.  Next,  we  might  expand  either  NP  or  VP,  so 
suppose  we  use  F2  first  and  obtain  Figure  7.  We  continue  in  this  way 


sentences  in  the  nested  form;  we  leave  them  open,  so  to  speak,  for  future 
elaborations  presently  unspecified:  "This  is  the  cow  that  tossed  the  dog  that 
worried  the  cat  that  killed  the  rat  that  ate  the  malt  that  lay  in  the  house  that 
Jack  buUt."  Consideration  of  why  the  nested  construction  is  so  cumbersome, 
whereas  the  open-ended  construction  can  be  understood  by  small  children, 
leads  one  to  a  conviction  that  whenever  possible  the  sentence  is  planned  so 
that  it  can  be  tactically  elaborated  in  the  order  in  which  it  will  be  uttered; 
the  future  of  the  sentence  is  stored  in  immediate  memory  in  as  brief  and  stra- 
tegic a  form  as  possible.  Elaborating  the  tactical  details  of  the  Plan  in  the  order 
they  are  needed  serves  to  minimize  the  demands  on  the  speaker's  temporary 
memory. 

Plans  for  Speaking  ■    149 


NP        +         VP       By  rule  Fl. 

FIGURE  6.  First  step  in  the  formation  of  a  sentence 


VP       By  rule  Fl. 


T        +    Noun  By  rule  F2. 

FIGURE  7.  The  result  of  two  steps  in  the  formation  of  a  sentence 


T       +      Noun  Verb     +      NP 


T     +      Noun 
FIGURE  8.  Analysis  of  a  sentence  into  its  immediate  constituents 


until  finally  we  have  produced  the  structure  shown  in  Figure  8.  At 
this  point  we  are  ready  to  use  the  vocabulary  rules  and  so  turn 

T  +  Noun  +  Verb  +  T  +  Noun 
into  any  one  of  a  small  variety  of  different  sentences : 

A  boy  hit  the  ball, 

The  stick  hit  a  boy. 

The  ball  hit  a  ball, 
and  so  on.  The  machine  is  not  very  eloquent,  but  then,  it  is  not  a 
very  elaborate  machine. 

It  can  be  shown  that  sentence  generators  of  this  type  have  no 
trouble  at  all  vidth  the  nested  dependencies  that  are  so  embarrassing 
for  the  left-to-right  planner.  All  that  is  needed  are  rules  of  the  form 

S >  aXa  and  X >  bXb  and  X >  cXc,  etc.  Such  rules  can  settle 

the  future  and  the  past  simultaneously  and  leave  the  growing  tip 
of  the  sentence  in  the  middle,  rather  than  at  the  extreme  right.  Thus 
it  is  possible  to  answer  one  line  of  argument  used  against  simple  Mar- 
kovian  sources. 

The  other  complaint,  however,  that  the  number  of  rules  required 
must  not  be  too  great  to  be  learned  in  a  finite  childhood,  is  still  not 
met.  Of  course,  only  a  few  rules  are  needed  to  generate  some  sen- 
tences in  the  example  above,  but  that  proves  nothing.  Not  until  one 
begins  to  work  seriously  at  the  task  of  constructing  an  English  gram- 
mar using  only  rules  of  this  type  does  it  become  apparent  what  the 
problems  are.  Chomsky  has  discussed  these  in  some  detail  and  we 
shall  not  pursue  them  here.  It  is  sufficient  for  us  that  some  very  great 
economies  can  be  effected  in  the  statement  of  the  grammar  if  we  per- 
mit ourselves  to  use  a  slightly  more  complicated  kind  of  rule  that 
enables  us  to  rearrange  as  weU  as  to  rewrite.  These  more  complicated 
rules  are  rules  of  transformation,  rather  than  rules  of  formation. 

One  of  the  simplest  examples  is  the  transformation  that  carries 
active  constructions  into  passive  constructions :  "John  ate  the  apple" 
is  transformed  into  "The  apple  was  eaten  by  John."  If  the  formal 
properties  of  this  transformation  are  examined,  it  will  be  clear  that 
the  permutation  involved  cannot  be  accomplished  by  the  simpler 
type  of  rules.  Another  common  transformation  is  negation:  "I 
will  go"  becomes  "I  won't  go,"  "I  can  go"  becomes  "I  can't  go,"  "I 
have  gone"  becomes  "I  haven't  gone."  The  negation  is  carried  by 

Plans  for  Speaking  ■   151 


-n't,  which  acts  as  an  affix  on  the  auxiliary  verb.  But  notice  what  hap- 
pens when  there  is  no  auxihary  verb:  "I  go"  becomes  "I  don't  go." 
Since  there  is  no  auxiliary  to  which  -n't  can  be  affixed,  the  word  do  is 
introduced  in  order  to  carry  it — a  practice  that  has  earned  do  a  very 
bad  reputation  for  irregularity,  but  which  follows  rather  simply  from 
a  transformational  form  of  grammar.^^  Notice  that  the  transforma- 
tion required  to  produce  questions  has  the  same  problem.  The  gen- 
eral formula  for  the  transformation  is  that  abc  becomes  bac.  Thus, 
"I  will  go"  becomes  "Will  I  go?"  and  "I  can  go"  becomes  "Can  I  go?" 
and  "I  have  gone"  becomes  "Have  I  gone?"  etc.  But  the  rule  cannot 
apply  directly  to  the  sentence  "I  go,"  and  therefore  it  is  necessary  to 
introduce  the  do  transformation  here  as  in  the  case  of  negation.  Then 
"I  go"  can  become  "I  do  go,"  in  which  form  it  can  yield  either  the 
negation  or  the  question,  either  "I  don't  go"  or  "Do  I  go?"  We  see, 
therefore,  that  the  do  transformation  has  a  rather  general  role  to 
play  in  the  grammar  of  English. 

These  examples  should  suffice  to  suggest  the  nature  of  the  gram- 
matical transformations  that  we  use  to  rearrange  our  simpler  state- 
ments. Other  transformations  include  those  that  combine  two  sen- 
tences into  one  by  joining  them  with  and  or  or  and  that  enable  us  in 
various  ways  to  build  up  long,  complex,  compound  sentences. 

The  general  picture  of  sentence  generators  that  emerges  from 
this  analysis,  therefore,  is  that  we  have  a  rather  simple  system  for 
generating  sentences  like,  "A  boy  hit  a  stick"  (Chomsky  calls  these 
"kernel  strings").  On  top  of  that  we  have  a  system  of  transforma- 
tions that  operate  upon  the  kernel  strings  to  combine  them  or  per- 
mute them,  etc.,  into  the  endless  variety  of  grammatical  sentences. 
With  such  a  theory  it  should  be  possible  to  do  a  fairly  good  job  of 
speaking  English  grammatically  with  less  than  100  rules  of  forma- 
tion, less  than  100  transformations,  and  perhaps  100,000  rules  for 

11  An  interesting  case  of  "opposite  speech" — all  positive  statements  made  in 
negative  form,  all  negative  statements  made  as  positive  assertions — has  been 
described  by  J.  Laffal,  L.  D.  Lenkoski,  and  L.  Ameen,  "Opposite  speech"  in  a 
schizophrenic  patient,  Journal  of  Abnormal  and  Social  Psychology,  1956,  52, 
409^13.  The  patient  could  interchange  "yes"  and  "no,"  of  course,  without 
altering  the  structure  of  the  rest  of  the  sentence.  But  he  would  say,  "I  do  go" 
rather  than  "I  go,"  thus  revealing  the  double  transformation  of  negation — "I  go" 
becomes  "I  don't  go,"  which  then  becomes  "I  do  go."  In  grammar,  apparently, 
two  negative  transformations  are  not  quite  the  same  as  none  at  all,  for  the  do 
is  left  as  a  trace  of  the  affix  it  had  been  introduced  to  carry. 

152  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


vocabulary  and  pronunciation.  Even  a  child  should  be  able  to  master 
that  much  after  ten  or  fifteen  years  of  constant  practice. 

One  of  the  most  interesting  features  of  Chomsky's  analysis  is 
that  it  provides  for  ambiguities.  For  example,  "Flying  planes  can  be 
dangerous"  is  recognized  as  ambiguous  by  speakers  of  English.  There- 
fore, the  grammar  must  provide  two  different  Plans  for  generating  it. 
According  to  one  Plan  it  is  a  variant  form  of  "Flying  planes  are 
dangerous,"  and  according  to  the  other  Plan  it  is  related  to  "Flying 
planes  is  dangerous."  Most  people  are  blissfully  unaware  of  how 
many  sentences  are  ambiguous  in  this  way.  When  the  ambiguity  is 
noticed  it  becomes  a  rich  source  of  humor,  a  kind  of  grammatical  pun. 

Note  that  the  person  must  be  aware  of  the  underlying  structure 
of  the  sentence  in  order  to  understand  it  or  to  know  how  to  apply 
various  transformations  to  it.  "They  are  cooking  apples"  has  one 
structure  if  it  means  "My  friends  are  cooking  apples,"  but  a  different 
structure  if  it  means'  "Those  apples  are  good  only  for  cooking,  not  for 
eating."  If  the  person  has  in  mind  the  structure:  (They)  [{are  cook- 
ing) (apples)],  then  he  can  apply  a  passive  transformation  to  it  and 
so  obtain  "Apples  are  being  cooked  by  them."  But  if  the  person  has  in 
mind  the  structure  (They)  [(are)  (cooking  apples)],  then  the  passive 
transformation  is  not  relevant.  If  the  complete  hiearchy,  and  not  just 
the  terminal  string  of  words  organized  by  the  hierarchy,  were  not 
represented  cognitively,  we  would  not  know  which  transformations 
could  be  applied  to  it,  and  we  would  not  be  able  to  recognize  the  in- 
trinsic ambiguity  of  the  utterance. 

The  ability  of  the  grammar  to  reproduce  this  kind  of  ambiguity 
is  strong  evidence  for  the  adequacy  of  the  grammatical  formulation. 
One  wonders  how  far  this  kind  of  test  of  a  theory's  adequacy  can  be 
extended  beyond  the  purely  linguistic  domain.  For  example,  two 
people  who  have  memorized  a  string  of  symbols  may  recite  them  in 
exactly  the  same  way,  yet  they  may  have  quite  different  mnemonic 
Plans.  An  adequate  theory  should,  hopefully,  provide  for  both  Plans. 
At  the  present  time,  however,  no  theory  of  verbal  learning  is  anywhere 
near  this  level  of  sophistication. 

There  is  a  great  deal  about  sentence  generation  left  unexplained 
by  this  theory  of  grammar.  If  speaking  were  a  game,  then  grammar 
would  tell  us  what  moves  were  legal,  but  not  what  moves  were  wise. 

Plans  for  Speaking  ■   153 


We  cannot  yet  say  how  a  talker  selects  the  content  of  his  utterances. 
But  even  within  the  relatively  narrow  scope  of  syntactics  it  is  clear 
that  people  are  able  to  construct  and  carry  out  very  complicated 
Plans  at  a  relatively  rapid  pace.  This  human  ability  may  be  unique  to 
human  speech,  but  that  seems  unlikely. 

A  study  of  grammatical  systems  is  a  particularly  interesting 
way  to  approach  the  study  of  human  Plans.  The  material  is  plentiful 
and  relatively  limited  in  type,  it  is  easily  described  in  writing,  sev- 
eral alternative  theories  (that  is,  grammars)  can  be  compared,  reason- 
able intuitive  agreement  can  be  reached  about  acceptable  and  un- 
acceptable sequences  of  responses,  etc.  With  all  these  advantages, 
the  scientific  description  of  verbal  behavior  (by  linguists,  of  course, 
not  by  psychologists)  is  far  advanced  over  any  other  area  of  behav- 
ioral description  and  so  provides  a  glimpse  of  what  other  behav- 
ioral theories  may  look  like  eventually.  Karl  Lashley  once  remarked : 

I  have  devoted  so  much  time  to  discussion  of  the  problem  of 
syntax  not  only  because  language  is  one  of  the  most  important 
products  of  human  cerebral  action,  but  also  because  the  prob- 
lems raised  by  the  organization  of  language  seem  to  me  to  be 
characteristic  of  almost  all  other  cerebral  activity.  There  is  a 
series  of  hierarchies  of  organization;  the  order  of  vocal  move- 
ments in  pronouncing  the  words,  the  order  of  words  in  the  sen- 
tence, the  order  of  sentences  in  the  paragraph,  the  rational  order 
of  paragraphs  in  a  discourse.  Not  only  speech,  but  all  skilled 
acts  seem  to  involve  the  same  problems  of  serial  ordering,  even 
down  to  the  temporal  coordination  of  muscular  contractions  in 
such  a  movement  as  reaching  and  grasping.  Analysis  of  the 
nervous  mechanisms  underlying  order  in  the  more  primitive  acts 
may  contribute  ultimately  to  the  solution  of  even  the  physiology 
of  logic.^^ 

This  raises  the  question  of  whether  Lashley,  or  the  present  au- 
thors, would  endorse  the  ancient  argument  that  the  laws  of  grammar 
are  the  laws  of  thought,  and  whether  they  would  support  the  more 
modern  version  advanced  by  Benjamin  Lee  Whorf,  who  wrote  that 
"the  forms  of  a  person's  thoughts  are  controlled  by  inexorable  laws 
of  pattern  of  which  he  is  unconscious.  These  patterns  are  the  un- 

12  Karl  S.  Lashley,  The  problem  of  serial  order  in  behavior,  in  Lloyd  A. 
JefFress,  ed..  Cerebral  Mechanisms  in  Behavior,  The  Hixon  Symposium  (New 
York:  WUey,  1951),  pp.  121-122. 

154  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


perceived  intricate  systematizations  of  his  own  language — shown 
readily  enough  by  a  candid  comparison  and  contrast  with  other  lan- 
guages, especially  those  of  a  different  linguistic  family,"  ^^  The  ques- 
tion raises  issues  that  extend  far  beyond  the  proper  bounds  of  this 
discussion,  but  perhaps  it  is  possible  to  clarify  the  situation  some- 
what by  saying  that  the  position  advocated  here  does  not  commit  the 
authors  one  way  or  the  other  with  respect  to  the  "Whorfian  hypothe- 
sis." It  is  not  only  English  grammar  that  is  built  around  hierarchical 
Plans  and  their  various  transformations — the  grammar  of  every  lan- 
guage is  constructed  in  that  way,  so  a  speaker's  thought  processes 
cannot  be  in  any  way  unique  on  that  account.  Moreover,  if  the  specu- 
lations of  the  present  authors  are  correct,  nearly  all  of  man's  behav- 
ior is  similarly  organized.  We  might  speak  metaphorically  of  a  gen- 
eral grammar  of  behavior,  meaning  that  the  grammar  of  a  language 
was  only  one  example  of  a  general  pattern  of  control  that  could  be 
exemplified  in  many  other  realms  of  behavior.  But  to  say  that  the 
formal  structure  of  the  laws  of  grammar  is  similar  to  the  structure  of 
the  laws  of  thought  is  very  different  from  saying  that  the  laws  of 
grammar  are  the  laws  of  thought,  or  that  your  thought  must  re- 
main forever  shackeled  to  the  conjugations  and  declensions  of  your 
native  tongue. 

How  language  is  used  for  giving  instructions,  for  descriptions, 
for  asking  questions,  for  making  love,  for  solving  problems,  for  mak- 
ing Plans,  or  organizing  Images  raises  so  many  different  psychologi- 
cal problems,  each  unique  and  special  for  each  unique  and  special 
use  of  language,  that  no  simple  generalizations  can  cover  them  all. 
The  way  language  enters  into  each  of  these  situations  can  be  de- 
termined only  by  studying  the  situations.  The  grammatical  Plan,  as 
we  have  said  before,  specifies  only  the  legal  moves  in  the  social  game 
of  communication.  The  reasons  for  playing  that  game,  however,  can- 
not be  deduced  from  its  rules. 

Let  us  close  this  chapter  with  a  summary  attempt  to  bring  these 
linguistic  observations  closer  to  the  general  thesis  of  the  present  vol- 
ume: 

13  B.  L.  Whorf,  Language,  Thought,  and  Reality,  J.  B.  Carroll,  ed.  (New 
York:  W^iley  and  the  Technology  Press,  1956),  p.  252. 

Plans  for  Speaking  ■   155 


First,  the  pronunciation  of  a  sentence  in  a  normal  manner  is  a 
skilled  act,  acquired  after  many  years  of  practice.  Like  any  skill,  it 
must  be  guided  by  a  Plan.  That  is  to  say,  there  must  be  a  separate, 
distinct  Plan  for  every  separate  distinct  sentence  we  utter.  The  hier- 
archy of  the  Plan  for  some  particular  sentence  corresponds  with  the 
way  that  sentence  would  be  "parsed."  The  test  phases  of  the  TOTE 
units  in  this  Plan  involve  comparisons  of  the  uttered  sounds  and 
felt  movements  with  the  auditory  and  proprioceptive  Images  of  what 
they  should  be.  And  the  ultimate  operational  phase  of  the  sentence 
Plan  involves  the  movements  of  the  speech  musculature.  We  can 
refer  to  this  as  the  "motor  Plan"  for  the  sentence. 

Behind  the  motor  Plan,  however,  is  a  process  more  difficult  to 
understand,  a  process  which  generates  the  motor  Plan  itself.  That  is 
to  say,  there  must  be  another  level  of  Plan  that  operates  on  the  motor 
Plan.  We  have  encountered  this  notion  already  in  Chapter  10,  where 
we  considered  a  Plan  for  generating  a  Plan  to  recall  a  memorized 
passage.  The  situation  here  is  analogous.  In  order  to  keep  the  two 
straight,  let  us  call  this  the  "grammar  Plan."  The  grammar  Plan  has 
been  the  central  concern  of  this  chapter.  Its  structure  is  the  hierarchy 
of  grammatical  rules  of  formation  and  transformation.  The  object 
that  it  operates  upon  is  tested  for  its  "sentencehood."  This  reduces 
to  a  question  of  whether  it  has  a  noun  phrase  and  a  verb  phrase.  The 
test  of  whether  it  has  a  noun  phrase  fails  and  so  sends  the  system  off 
to  generate  one,  etc.,  until  eventually  all  the  subtests  and  subsub- 
tests  are  satisfied  and  the  system  returns  to  the  main  test,  which  now 
passes,  and  the  motor  Plan  is  complete.  Given  a  complete  motor  Plan 
for  a  kernel  string,  it  may  be  necessary  to  perform  transformations 
upon  it,  so  further  elaboration  of  the  grammar  Plan  would  be  re- 
quired to  do  that. 

There  are,  of  course,  many  substantive,  semantic  decisions  to 
be  made  in  the  operation  of  the  grammar  Plan.  That  is  to  say,  when 
the  test  for  a  noun  phrase  fails  and  the  operation  of  finding  a  noun 
phrase  is  begun,  the  system  must  have  some  way  of  determining 
which  kind  of  noun  phrase  to  select.  Questions  of  selection,  of  course, 
require  evaluation  functions.^*  One  way  to  conceive  of  it  is  to  think 

1*  The  test  phase  of  the  TOTE  would  presumably  consist  of  a  list  of  accept- 
able alternatives  from  which  the  choice  would  be  made  according  to  the  evalua- 

1 56  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


that  an  Image  of  the  result  which  the  sentence  should  produce,  or  of 
the  information  it  should  convey,  supplies  criteria  that  must  be  met 
before  the  tests  are  passed.  But  how  this  aspect  of  the  process  might 
function  would  be  completely  different  for,  say,  casual  greetings  and 
for  the  composition  of  a  sonnet — criteria  imposed  by  the  Image  un- 
doubtedly exercise  control  over  the  rate  at  which  the  motor  Plan 
can  be  fashioned.  But  here  our  speculations  encounter  larger  issues 
that  cannot  be  discussed  intelligibly  without  a  considerable  develop- 
ment of  the  properties  of  the  Image  and  the  question  of  meaning,  a 
development  that  the  authors  are  not  inclined  to  enter  into  here.  For 
the  moment  it  is  sufficient  to  see  verbal  skills  in  the  same  frame  of 
reference  as  other  hierarchically  organized  skills,  and  to  communi- 
cate the  opinion  that  a  system  organized  along  these  lines  could  speak 
gramatically — and  might  even  be  able  to  find  something  to  say. 

Where  does  this  leave  us  with  respect  to  the  problem  that  opened 
this  chapter?  Does  language  introduce  new  psychological  processes, 
or  are  all  our  verbally  acquired  skills  foreshadowed  by  processes  ob- 
servable in  lower  animals?  To  the  extent  that  language  relies  upon 
TOTE  hierarchies  and  we  have  seen  TOTE  hierarchies  in  animals, 
there  is  nothing  new  here  except  a  greater  degree  of  complexity.  But 
that  comment  is  about  as  helpful  as  the  remark  that  both  animals 
and  men  are  constructed  of  atoms.  A  more  interesting  question  con- 
cerns the  possibility  that  some  new  configuration  of  these  basic  com- 
ponents may  have  emerged.  In  particular,  we  might  ask:  Is  the 
capacity  to  use  Plans  to  construct  Plans  to  guide  behavior  a  new  psy- 
chological process?  A  motor  Plan  may  be  instinctive,  or  it  may  be  a 
skill  acquired  after  long  hours  of  practice — here  men  and  animals 
are  on  an  equal  footing.  But  in  the  discussion  of  memorizing  and  even 
more  clearly  in  the  discussion  of  speaking  we  have  found  it  necessary 
to  believe  that  a  motor  Plan  could  be  constructed  very  quickly  and 
efficiently,  not  by  rote,  but  by  the  operation  of  a  higher-level  Plan 
that  had  the  motor  Plan  as  its  object.  Something  more  is  involved 
here  than  the  usual  discussions  of  insight  versus  trial-and-error — a 


tion  function  supplied  by  the  Image  and  the  time  available  for  making  the  choice. 
Some  hint  as  to  how  this  might  work  is  given  by  the  observation  that  in  word 
association  studies  there  is  a  strong  tendency  for  the  subject's  reply  to  fall  in 
the  same  syntactic  category  as  the  stimulus  word.  See  R.  S.  Woodworth,  Ex- 
perimental Psychology  (New  York:  Holt,  1938),  pp.  347-348. 

Plans  for  Speaking  ■    157 


motor  Plan  could  be  insightfully  selected  by  an  organism  that  could 
not  execute  a  Plan  to  construct  a  motor  Plan.  Perhaps  some  of  the 
apes,  even  some  of  the  higher  mammals,  might  have  the  rudiments 
of  this  higher-level  planning  ability.  If  so,  then  man  may  indeed  have 
to  retreat  into  his  greater  complexity  to  explain  his  unique  accom- 
plishments. If  not,  we  may  have  here  the  key  to  an  evolutionary 
breakthrough  as  important  as  the  development  of  lungs  and  legs. 


158   ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


CHAPTER  12 


PLANS   FOR  SEARCHING 
AND   SOLVING 


Any  Plan  complicated  enough  to  be  Interesting  will  include 
steps  that  are  executed  for  no  other  reason  than  to  pave  the  way  for 
what  we  really  want  to  do.  In  Chapter  2  these  were  referred  to  as  the 
preparatory  phases  of  the  Plan — raising  the  hammer  was  a  prepara- 
tory phase  leading  up  to  striking;  it  was  the  striking  phase  that  ac- 
complished the  work,  that  is,  changed  the  conditions  involved  in  the 
tests  for  continuing  or  terminating  the  execution  of  the  TOTE  unit. 
There  are,  of  course,  many  kinds  of  preparatory  subplans.  A  neces- 
sary preparatory  phase  to  hammering,  as  every  carpenter  knows,  is 
the  (frequently  aggravating)  subplan  for  locating  a  hammer.  In  its 
simplest  form,  this  preparatory  subplan  consists  of  examining  one 
object  after  another  until  something  satisfactorily  matches  our  con- 
cept of  a  hammer;  only  then  are  the  conditions  appropriate  for 
initiating  the  next  part  of  the  Plan. 

How  do  we  conduct  a  search  of  this  kind?  Is  there  some  kind  of 
Plan  that  we  follow?  Certainly,  there  are  some  places  of  relatively 
high  probability  and  we  look  there  first.  If  these  do  not  produce  it,  we 

Plans  for  Searching  and  Solving  "159 


may  wander  aimlessly  about,  poking  into  corners,  often  returning  to 
look  in  the  same  place  two  or  three  times.  Eventually  it  occurs  to  us 
that  we  should  be  systematic.  So  we  start  off  in  one  room  and  search 
it  from  one  end  to  the  other,  then  move  on  to  the  next  room,  etc.  Or 
we  ask  somebody  if  he  knows  where  it  is.  Or  we  go  next  door  and  bor- 
row one.  If  all  else  fails,  we  can  go  to  the  hardware  store  and  buy  a 
new  hammer;  then  the  old  one  is  certain  to  reappear. 

There  is  an  item  on  an  intelligence  test  that  asks  how  you  would 
find  a  ball  that  was  lost  somewhere  in  an  open  field.  The  correct 
answer  is  any  systematic  procedure  for  covering  every  inch  of  the 
field  without  looking  in  the  same  place  twice.  If  the  ball  is  in  the  field, 
the  intelligent,  systematic  Plan  for  searching  will  lead  you  over  it 
eventually.  Systematic  Plans  are  sometimes  called  "algorithms." 
People  do  not  always  use  systematic  Plans  for  searching  because7  in 
spite  of  the  intelligence  test,  systematic  Plans  can  be  dull  and  ineffi- 
cient. The  alternative  is  to  be  unsystematic — in  a  clever  way.  If  we 
try  to  short-cut  the  systematic  Plan  by  guessing,  asking  for  help,  try- 
ing to  remember  where  we  saw  it  last,  etc.,  the  Plan  we  follow  is  said 
to  be  "heuristic."  ^  A  systematic  Plan,  when  it  is  possible,  is  sure  to 
work,  but  it  may  take  too  long,  or  cost  too  much.  A  heuristic  Plan  may 
be  cheap  and  quick,  but  it  will  sometimes  fail  to  produce  the  in- 
tended result. 

One  danger  in  executing  search  routines  is  that  the  object 
searched  for  may  not  exist.  If  the  hammer  is  no  longer  in  the  house, 
even  the  most  thoroughly  systematic  search,  inch  by  inch,  will  not 

1  The  recent  revival  of  interest  in  heuristic — the  art  of  discovery — seems  to 
stem  largely  from  the  work  of  the  mathematician  G.  Polya.  His  How  to  Solve  It 
(Princeton:  Princeton  University  Press,  1945)  attempts  to  state  the  heuristic 
maxims  of  mathematical  discovery,  and  this  work  was  continued  in  Mathematics 

Cand  Plausible  Reasoning,  2  vols.  (Princeton:  Princeton  University  Press,  1954). 
Among  psychologists  it  was  principally  K.  Duncker  who  emphasized  the  discovery 
of  the  heuristic  methods  that  people  use.  See  K.  Duncker,  On  problem-solving, 
L.  S.  Lees,  trans..  Psychological  Monographs,  1945,  No.  270.  The  study  of  algo- 
rithms— effective  computational  procedures — is  an  active  branch  of  modern 
mathematics,  a  field  usually  referred  to  as  the  theory  of  recursive  functions.  A 
good  introduction  to  the  theory  can  be  found  in  Martin  Davis,  Computability  and 
Unsolvability  (New  York:  McGraw-Hill,  1958).  An  algorithm  is  defined  intuitively 
as  any  completely  mechanical  procedure  for  computing  an  answer  in  a  finite 
number  of  steps.  For  some  problems  algorithms  are  known  that  are  very  efficient 
(e.g.,  finding  the  maximum  of  a  function).  For  some  problems  algorithms  are 
known  that  are  not  practical  (e.g.,  exploring  all  possible  continuations  of  a  chess 
position).  For  some  problems  it  is  known  that  no  algorithm  exists  and  only 
heuristic  methods  are  possible  (e.g.,  showing  that  a  particular  logical  proposition 
is  not  a  theorem  of  quantification  theory). 

i6o  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


produce  it — we  have  embarked  on  an  impossible  task.  Since  we  are 
never  absolutely  certain  in  advance  that  the  object  can  be  found,  the 
intelligent  thing  to  do  is  to  incorporate  a  stop-rule  in  the  search  Plan. 
That  is  to  say,  if  the  object  is  not  found  after  some  fixed  time,  or  some 
given  number  of  operations,  or  before  some  particular  event  occurs, 
the  search  will  be  halted  and  it  will  be  assumed  that  the  object  in  ques- 
tion does  not  exist.  (The  suspension  of  stop-orders  during  hypnosis 
has  already  been  discussed  in  Chapter  8.)  In  all  cases  of  human  Plans 
for  searching,  a  variety  of  such  stop-rules  will  be  built  into  the  test 
phases.  Many  searches  are  instituted  solely  for  the  purpose  of  check- 
ing on  the  Image,  either  to  confirm  or  infirm  it.  Such  searches  cannot 
occur  unless  we  have  a  clear  rule  for  determining  when  the  Image  is 
presumed  to  be  infirmed  because  the  object  does  not  exist.  We  know 
surprisingly  little  about  these  stop-rules  or  the  conditions  that  cause 
us  to  set  them  as  we  do.  What  makes  us  decide  that  the  thing  we  are 
looking  for  does  not  exist?  It  is  reasonable  to  suppose  that  both  the 
probability  of  discovery  and  the  utility  of  the  object  are  involved  in 
setting  the  stop-order,  as  well  as  the  kind  of  Plan,  systematic  or 
heuristic,  that  is  being  executed. 

Plans  for  searching  for  an  object  in  the  physical  environment 
are  usually  rather  simple.  There  is  a  perceptual  test  that  defines  the 
searcher's  "set,"  plus  an  operational  phase  for  orienting  the  recep- 
tors toward  another  object  where  the  perceptual  test  can  be  repeated, 
etc.,  until  an  object  is  discovered  that  satisfies  the  test  or  until  the 
stop-rule  is  effective.  The  search  Plan  holds  a  special  interest  for 
us,  however,  because  it  serves  as  a  model  for  many  other  cognitive 
processes  that,  at  first  glance,  we  would  not  consider  examples  of 
searching  at  all.  For  example,  we  say  that  we  "search"  through  our 
memory  for  a  name,  or  an  image,  or  an  association.  Or  we  "search" 
for  the  solution  to  a  problem,  an  answer,  or  a  method,  or  an  insight. 
We  speak  of  Edison  testing  thousands  of  substances  in  his  effort  to 
make  an  electric  light  as  "searching"  for  a  good  filament,  or  Ehrlich 
as  "searching"  for  a  cure  for  syphilis,  etc.  These  tasks  have  all  the 
formal  characteristics  of  search  except  that  the  object  sought  is  not 
located  in  spatial  coordinates. 

In  order  to  be  explicit  about  the  kind  of  search  that  is  involved 
in  solving  problems,  let  us  consider  a  problem  that  psychologists  have 

Plans  for  Searching  and  Solving  ■    i6i 


studied  rather  extensively  in  the  laboratory.  Subjects  are  shown  a  col- 
lection of  objects  that  differ  from  one  another  in  several  respects. 
For  example,  some  may  be  large  and  others  small,  some  may  be  red 
and  others  green,  some  may  be  circular  and  others  triangular,  some 
may  have  borders  and  others  not,  etc.  All  of  the  possible  combinations 
are  laid  out  neatly  for  the  subject  to  see.  He  is  told  that  some  of  the 
objects  are  examples  of  a  "concept"  and  that  the  others  are  not.  The 
concept  could,  of  course,  be  a  random  sample  from  the  set  of  objects, 
but  no  one  has  considered  that  condition  vi^orth  studying.  A  concept 
is  something  like,  "All  the  large,  green  ones,"  or,  "All  the  ones  with 
borders,"  etc.  The  subject  can  point  to  one  of  the  objects  and  the 
experimenter  will  tell  him  whether  or  not  that  object  is  an  example 
of  the  concept.  The  subject  continues  to  ask  about  the  various  objects 
until  he  has  attained  the  correct  concept  (that  is,  until  he  has 
read  the  experimenter's  mind  ) . 

For  example,  imagine  that  there  are  three  dimensions  of  varia- 
tion, and  that  two  values  of  each  dimension  are  possible.  In  that  case, 
there  are  2x2x2  =  8  different  objects  that  have  to  be  classified 
as  instances  of  the  concept  or  as  not  instances  of  it.  If  the  dimensions 
were  size,  shape,  and  color,  the  eight  objects  might  be  as  follows: 

(1)  Large,  white  circle  (5)  Small,  white  circle 

(2)  Large,  white  square  (6)  Small,  white  square 
( 3  )  Large,  black  circle  (7)  Small,  black  circle 
(4)  Large,  black  square  (8)  Small,  black  square 

The  various  hypotheses  that  the  subject  could  hold  about  the  concept, 
however,  might  be  the  following: 

(1)  Large  circles  (10)  White  squares 

(2)  Large  squares  (H)  Black  circles 

(3)  Small  circles  (12)  Black  squares 

(4)  Small  squares  (13)  Large  things 

(5)  Large,  white  things  (14)  Small  things 

(6)  Large,  black  things  (15)  White  things 

(7)  Small,  white  things  (16)  Black  things 

(8)  Small,  black  things  (17)  Circles 

(9)  White  circles  (18)  Squares 

162  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


Obviously,  we  might  have  still  other  hypotheses,  such  as  "all  the  ob- 
jects," or  "none  of  the  objects,"  or  disjunctions  of  the  form  "either 
large  circles  or  small  squares,"  or  "everything  except  large  circles," 
etc.  The  instructions  that  are  given  to  the  subject — and  perhaps 
some  instructions  he  assumes  without  being  told — will  determine  the 
exact  set  of  hypotheses  that  he  is  searching  through. 

This  concept-learning  task  is  commonly  employed  in  experi- 
mental studies  of  thinking.  It  can  be  described  as  a  search  problem  in 
almost  the  same  terms  as  were  used  above  for  perceptual  search 
problems.  The  subject  is  searching  through  a  set  of  possible  solutions 
for  the  correct  one.  The  alternative  solutions  he  is  searching  through 
are  not  the  objects  he  sees,  of  course,  but  the  set  of  possible  hypothe- 
ses he  could  hold  about  the  particular  concept  the  experimenter  has 
selected.-  Each  time  he  learns  about  the  status  of  a  new  object,  he  re- 
duces the  size  of  the  set  of  possible  hypotheses  that  are  compatible 
with  the  information  he  has  received.  The  experimenter  is  interested 
to  see  in  what  order  he  will  ask  about  the  objects  and  how  well  he  will 
be  able  to  use  all  the  information  he  has.  The  experiment  enables  us 
to  study  some  of  the  heuristic  Plans  people  will  use  for  gathering  in- 
formation about  the  world  they  live  in. 

The  concept  of  a  set  of^alterjiative  hypotheses  that  might  be  the 
solution  of  the  problem  is  a  very  useful  one,  since  it  enables  us  to  re- 
duce many  problems  to  a  similar  form — how  to  search  most  effi- 
ciently through  a  large  set  of  possibilities.  Sometimes  the  analogy 
can  get  a  bit  strained — it  is  difficult  to  think  of  vvrriting  a  book  as  a 
process  of  selecting  one  out  of  all  the  possible  ways  100,000  words 
could  be  strung  together.  The  legendary  monkeys  who  typed  at 
random  until  they  accidentally  produced  all  the  books  in  the  British 
Museum  could  be  hired  to  help  the  author,  whose  task  would  then  be 

~  This  insight  seems  to  have  occurred  independently  to  Hovland  and  Whit- 
field at  about  the  same  time.  See  J.  W.  Whitfield,  An  experiment  in  problem  solv- 
ing. Quarterly  Journal  of  Experimental  Psychology,  1951,  3,  184-197;  Carl  I. 
Hovland,  A  "communication  analysis"  of  concept  learning.  Psychological  Re- 
view, 1952,  59,  461-472;  Carl  I.  Hovland  and  Walter  Weiss,  Transmission  of 
information  concerning  concepts  through  positive  and  negative  instances,  Jotir- 
nal  of  Experimental  Psychology,  1953,  45,  175-182.  The  more  general  concep- 
tion— that  thinking,  problem  solving,  concept  attainment  can  be  modeled  after 
the  search  process — is  a  familiar  one  to  psychologists;  see,  for  example,  the 
review  by  Donald  M.  Johnson,  A  modern  account  of  problem  solving,  PsycJiologi- 
cal  Bulletin,  1944,  41,  201-229,  for  a  discussion  of  search  and  of  plans  of  action 
in  problem  solving. 

Plans  for  Searching  and  Solving  ■   163 


simply  to  read  all  they  wrote  and  select  the  book  he  wanted.  The  rea- 
son this  description  seems  unnatural  is  that  we  don't  attack  the  prob- 
lem of  making  a  book  in  that  way;  and  the  reason  we  don't  is  that  we 
use  heuristic,  rather  than  either  systematic  or  random,  Plans.  But  in 
spite  of  the  psychological  artificiality  of  such  a  notion,  it  provides  a 
valuable  formal  tool  for  the  analysis  and  understanding  of  problems 
and  puzzles. 

A  systematic  approach  to  learning  a  concept  would  be  to  write 
down  all  the  possible  hypotheses  about  the  concept,  as  we  did  in  the 
example  above.  Then  the  subjects  could  take  the  first  hypothesis  on 
the  list  and  begin  systematically  to  ask  about  the  objects  until  he 
finds  one  that  contradicts  the  hypothesis,  at  which  point  he  could  go 
on  to  the  next  hypothesis  and  start  all  over  asking  about  the  objects 
again.  When  he  can  proceed  all  the  way  through  the  entire  set  of  ob- 
jects without  finding  one  that  contradicts  the  hypothesis  he  is  testing, 
then  he  knows  that  the  hypothesis  must  be  correct.  In  executing 
the  Plan  he  makes  no  effort  to  remember  anything  or  to  understand 
anything — he  plods  systematically  ahead,  day  after  day,  until  a  hy- 
pothesis checks  out.  This  is  an  algorithm,  a  systematic  Plan  for  solv- 
ing the  problem,  and  it  is  guaranteed  to  work — but  it  is  not  a  very 
popular  approach.  Nobody  has  ever  been  known  to  use  it  in  any  of  the 
hundreds  of  experiments  that  have  been  done  with  thousands  of  sub- 
jects. No  subject  would  want  to  try  it,  and  no  experimenter  would 
have  the  patience  to  let  him. 

Another  systematic  Plan,  somewhat  more  intelligent,  would  be 
to  write  down  all  the  possible  hypotheses  and  then  to  test  them  all 
simultaneously.  After  asking  whether  an  object  is  an  example  of  the 
concept,  the  subject  would  then  relate  the  answer  to  each  hypothesis 
in  turn — hypotheses  that  failed  would  be  crossed  off  the  list.  This  ver- 
sion of  the  Plan  looks  much  more  efficient  to  the  experimenter  be- 
cause the  subject  asks  him  relatively  few  questions,  but  it  is  only 
trivially  different  from  the  preceding  Plan.  This  version  has  occa- 
sionally been  attempted,  but  without  pencil  and  paper  it  is  almost 
certain  to  fail — the  cognitive  strain  is  too  great. 

The  actual  behavior  of  subjects  in  this  situation  is  quite  differ- 
ent.  Some  people  tackle  the  problem  verbally,  symbolically;  others 
want  to  manipulate  the  objects,  to  group  them  perceptually  this  way 

164  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


and  that;  a  few  can  alternate  between  the  abstract  and  the  perceptual 
strategies.^  Most  people  devise  rather  elaborate  mnemonic  Plans  for 
remembering  which  objects  are  in  which  class,  positive  or  negative.* 
Each  person  has  his  own  style,  his  own  tricks,  his  own  heuristic  Plan 
for  discovering  the  concept. 

An  interesting  and  important  study  of  concept  attainment  by 
Jerome  S.  Bruner,  Jacqueline  Goodnow,  and  George  Austin  demon- 
strates that  a  subject's  Plan  for  concept-learning  can  be  discovered 
and  analyzed.^  They  were  able  to  distinguish  among  several  different 
heuristic  strategies  that  their  subjects  used.  For  example,  some  sub- 
jects sampled  at  random,  repeated  their  questions  about  the  same 
object  several  times,  and  generally  indicated  that  they  had  no  good 
use  for  the  information  they  were  collecting.  The  people  who  do  this 
tend  to  abandon  it  on  repeated  tests  with  more  concepts. 

An  interesting  Plan  that  many  subjects  developed  was  the  fol- 
lowing. First,  locate  a  positive  instance  of  the  concept.  Then  find 
another  object  that  is  just  like  the  positive  one  in  all  respects  but  one. 
If  the  first  positive  object  is  a  large,  red  circle  without  border,  then 
find  the  small,  red  circle  without  border  and  ask  about  it.  If  the 
answer  is  negative,  then  you  know  that  size  is  important.  If  the 
answer  is  positive,  then  size  has  nothing  to  do  with  it.  Next,  repeat 
the  test  for  color,  then  for  shape,  then  for  borders,  etc.,  until  the 
aspects  are  exhausted.  This  procedure  is  not  the  most  efficient  one 
imaginable,  but  it  enables  a  person  to  explore  the  various  hypotheses 
with  a  heuristic  Plan  that  almost  automatically  keeps  track  of  the 
information  he  has  received.  (As  a  matter  of  fact,  this  strategy 
would  be  an  algorithm  if  no  limit  were  placed  on  the  number  of 
instances  about  which  the  subject  could  inquire.)  The  cognitive 
strain  is  greatly  reduced  at  only  a  slight  penalty  in  extra  objects 
examined. 

When  subjects  are  put  under  pressure  to  find  a  concept  in  the 
smallest  possible  number  of  questions,  they  may  try  to  keep  track  of 
the  entire  set  of  hypotheses  through  which  they  are  really  searching. 

3  Eugenia  Hanfmann,  A  study  of  personal  patterns  in  an  intellectual  per- 
formance, Character  and  Personality,  1941,  9,  315-325. 

*  See,  for  example,  Edna  Heidbreder,  The  attainment  of  concepts.  III:  The 
process,  Journal  of  Psychology,  1947,  24,  93—138. 

5  J.  S.  Bruner,  J.  Goodnow,  and  G.  Austin,  A  Study  of  Thinking  (New  York: 
Wiley,  1956). 

Plans  for  Searching  and  Solving  ■    165 


Subjects  with  mathematical  or  logical  training  are  especially  likely 
to  try  this  heroic  Plan.  For  problems  of  any  degree  of  complexity 
it  is  almost  certain  to  fail,  because  the  person  cannot  keep  all  the 
implications  of  his  information  straight.  When  the  pressure  is  ap- 
plied, however,  other  subjects  can  frequently  succeed  by  gambling. 
They  use  the  Plan  of  changing  aspects  of  a  positive  instance,  as  be- 
fore, but  now  they  change  two  or  three  at  a  time.  If  they  change  two 
1 .  aspects  and  are  told  that  the  result  is  still  an  example  of  the  con- 
■•^o*  ^'^  cept,  then  both  of  those  aspects  are  known  to  be  irrelevant,  and  they 

^£,1^  have  settled  two  aspects  with  only  one  question.  If  the  result  is 

negative,  however,  they  do  not  know  which  aspect  of  the  two  is 
important.  With  a  little  bit  of  luck,  the  Plan  will  sometimes  work. 
The  important  point  to  note,  however,  is  that  there  are  many  different 
heuristic  Plans  a  subject  may  use.  All  involve  the  risk  of  failure,  but 
some  are  more  risky  than  others. 

As  another  example  of  the  important  difference  between  system- 
atic and  heuristic  Plans,  consider  an  anagram.  Imagine  that  we  are 
given  the  letters  EIMT  and  that  the  problem  is  to  spell  an  English 
word  with  these  letters.  We  can  systematically  work  through  all  the 
4!  =  24  orderings  of  these  four  letters,  relying  on  our  knowledge  of 
the  English  vocabulary  to  provide  the  test.  A  more  expensive,  but 
more  authoritative  test  would  be  to  look  for  each  string  of  letters  in 
the  Oxford  English  Dictionary.  In  this  way  we  would  be  certain  to 
discover  TIME  and  MITE  and  ITEM  and  EMIT  and  any  other  solu- 
tions the  anagram  may  have.  It  would  be  dull  work  and  it  would  be 
slow,  but  we  could  certainly  do  it  that  way.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  if  we 
could  mechanize  the  dictionary  test,  the  whole  procedure  might 
better  occupy  the  time  of  a  computing  machine  than  of  an  adult  man. 

It  is  obvious  that  few  normal  people  tackle  problems,  even  prob- 
lems as  simple  as  an  anagram,  with  a  systematic  Plan.  In  the  case  of 
an  anagram,  people  might  work  backwards — guess  some  English 
word  and  then  see  if  the  letters  can  spell  it.  Or  they  might  rely  upon 
their  feelings  about  the  probabilities  of  letter  pairs  to  guide  them.  For 
example,  they  would  not  bother  to  consider  such  possible  solutions  as 
TMIE,  since  they  know  that  there  are  no  English  words  beginning 
TM — .  They  would  probably  try  to  exploit  the  tendency  for  vowels  and 
consonants  to  alternate  in  English;  if  they  began  with  T,  they  would 

i66  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


next  form  TI  or  TE.  They  would  probably  not  bother  to  test  any  words 
ending  in  I.  Now,  note  that  most  of  these  heuristic  rules  are  fallible. 
Consonants  and  vowels  do  not  always  alternate.  Some  English  words 
end  in  I.  TM  can  occur  in  such  words  as  posTMan,  etc.  It  can  easily 
happen,  especially  in  longer  anagrams  with  unique  solutions,  that 
one's  intuitive  feeUngs,  or  hunches,  do  not  generate  the  solution  at 
all,  and  one  is  then  forced  to  adopt  some  exhaustive  Plan  for  per- 
muting the  letters  systematically  until  a  word  turns  up.  But  usually 
these  various  bits  of  information  about  where  it  is  worth  while  to 
look  for  the  solution  will  be  valuable  and  will  produce  correct  solu- 
tions more  quickly.  For  most  problems  the  only  Plans  we  have  are 
heuristic,  and  much  of  the  study  of  thinking  can  be  reduced  rather 
generally  to  the  study  of  the  heuristic  Plans  people  use  for  generating 
proposed  solutions  that  are  worth  testing. 

The  idea  that  problem-solving  can  be  represented  as  searching 
through  a  large  set  of  possibilities  until  we  find  one  that  solves  the 
problem  may  seem  odd  at  first,  and  somewhat  novel  to  a  person  who 
has  taken  his  heuristic  Plans  for  granted  and  who  has  never  bothered 
to  consider  the  multitude  of  alternatives  he  doesn't  need  to  reject 
because  he  doesn't  even  think  of  them.  But  the  notion  is  familiar  to 
mathematicians,  who  have  reflected  on  the  heuristic  art  a  great  deal 
more  than  most  of  us.  For  example,  Poincare  wrote : 

What,  in  fact,  is  mathematical  discovery?  It  does  not  con- 
sist in  making  new  combinations  with  mathematical  entities  that 
are  already  known.  That  can  be  done  by  anyone,  and  the  combi- 
nations that  could  be  so  formed  would  be  infinite  in  number,  and 
the  greater  part  of  them  would  be  absolutely  devoid  of  interest. 
Discovery  consists  precisely  in  not  constructing  useless  combina- 
tions, but  in  constructing  those  that  are  useful,  which  are  an  in- 
finitely small  minority.  Discovery  is  discernment,  selection.® 

Exhaustive  Plans  can  be  used  to  solve  some  mathematical  problems, 
but  unless  the  problem  is  simple,  the  number  of  hypotheses  that 
would  need  to  be  systematically  explored  usually  makes  them  im- 
practical. The  mathematician  A.  M.  Turing  illustrated  the  inefficiency 
of  systematic  Plans  several  years  ago — he  considered  the  number  of 

c  Henri  Poincare,   Science  and  Method,  F.   Maitland,  trans.    (New   York: 
Dover,  1952),  pp.  50-51. 

Plans  for  Searching  and  Solving  "167 


arrangements  that  would  have  to  be  looked  at  in  the  process  of  sys- 
tematically solving  a  common  puzzle  consisting  of  sliding  squares  to 
be  arranged  in  a  particular  way.  The  number  was  20,922,789,888,000. 
Working  continuously  day  and  night  and  inspecting  one  position  per 
minute  the  process  would  take  four  million  years. ^  In  a  similar  spirit, 
Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon  have  considered  the  set  of  all  possible 
sequences  of  expressions  in  prepositional  logic  and  tried  to  estimate 
what  fraction  of  them  were  proofs  of  theorems  in  the  second  chapter 
of  Whitehead  and  Russell's  Principia  Mathematica.  Working  at  the 
speed  of  modern  electronic  computers,  it  would  take,  they  surmised, 
hundreds  of  thousands  of  years  of  computation  if  the  machine  used  a 
systematic  "British  Museum  algorithm."  ^  Obviously,  Whitehead  and 
Russell  did  not  proceed  in  that  fashion;  they  must  have  worked 
heuristically. 

It  is  fairly  obvious  that  without  a  little  discernment  and  selec- 
tion among  the  alternatives  we  are  willing  to  consider,  we  will  not 
live  long  enough  to  solve  anything.  A  heuristic  is  a  way  of  exercising 
discernment — but  it  always  runs  the  risk  that  the  solution  will  be 
discarded  inadvertently  along  with  the  millions  of  apparently  useless 
combinations.  Thus  we  arrive  at  a  typically  human  dilemma — slow 
and  sure,  or  fast  and  risky?  All  of  us  are  cognitive  gamblers — some 
more  than  others,  but  most  of  us  more  than  we  reahze.^ 

The  reduction  of  thinking  and  problem-solving  to  a  matter  of  ef- 
ficient techniques  for  searching  is,  of  course,  quite  attractive  to  any- 
one who  takes  the  general  thesis  of  this  book  seriously.  We  think 
of  a  test  phase  and  an  operational  phase  alternating  until  the  opera- 
tions turn  up  something  that  passes  the  test.  Solving  a  problem  is  a 
matter  of  turning  up  a  lot  of  likely  hypotheses  until  either  one  satis- 
fies the  test  or  the  stop-rule  is  applied. 

7  Quoted  in  M.  Polyani,  Personal  Knowledge  (Chicago:  University  of  Chi- 
cago Press,  1958),  p.  126. 

8  Allen  Newell,  J.  C.  Shaw,  and  Herbert  A.  Simon,  Empirical  explorations  of 
the  logic  theory  machine:  A  case  study  in  heuristic.  Proceedings  of  the  Western 
Joint  Computer  Conference  (Los  Angeles:  February  1957),  218-230. 

9  A  Study  of  Thinking  by  Bruner,  Goodnow,  and  Austin  suggests  several 
ways  to  do  psychological  research  on  the  economic  analysis  of  the  costs  and  values 
of  different  strategies  for  processing  information  in  thinking  and  problem-solving. 
See  also  E.  Galanter  and  M.  Gerstenhaber,  On  thought:  the  extrinsic  theory, 
Psychological  Review,  1956,  63,  218-227,  for  a  discussion  of  the  relations  among 
payofFs,  achievements,  problem  complexity,  and  the  subject's  strategies  in  solving 
problems. 

i68  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


But  is  the  search  process  an  adequate  model  for  everything  that 
we  would  normally  call  thinking  and  problem-solving?  Some  people 
would  argue  that  it  is  not.  For  example,  there  is  a  distinction  between 
"problems  to  find"  and  "problems  to  prove"  that  goes  back  at  least  to 
300  A.D.  and  the  Greek  mathematician  Pappus,  whose  discussion  of 
heuristic  is  one  of  the  oldest  to  be  preserved. ^°  The  aim  of  a  "problem 
to  find"  is  to  locate  an  object — a  hammer,  a  concept,  an  invention, 
or  the  value  of  x.  The  aim  of  a  "problem  to  prove"  is  to  show  con- 
clusively that  some  clearly  stated  assertion  is  either  true  or  false. 
It  is  obvious  that  a  "problem  to  find"  involves  a  search,  but  can  a 
"problem  to  prove"  also  be  formulated  that  way? 

If  we  think  of  a  "problem  to  prove"  as  involving  a  clear  state- 
ment of  what  is  given  and  a  clear  statement  of  what  is  to  be  proved, 
then  we  can  consider  the  solution  of  the  problem  to  depend  upon  dis- 
covering a  path — a  sequence  of  steps — that  leads  from  one  to  the 
other.  When  the  problem  is  to  establish  that  A  (the  given)  imphes  C 
(to  be  proved),  we  must  search  for  some  X  such  that  A  imphes  X  and 
X  implies  C.  We  search  through  a  large  set  of  X  until  we  find  one, 
B,  that  provides  a  path:  A  to  B  to  C.  (Of  course,  B  may  also  involve  a 
sequence  of  two  or  more  steps.)  Pappus  discussed  the  solution  of 
"problems  to  prove"  in  just  these  terms,  so  it  is  scarcely  an  innova- 
tion to  point  out  that  the  search  for  a  path  to  connect  two  things  is 
just  a  more  complicated  version  of  the  search  for  any  other  kind  of 
unknown.  But  whereas  the  search  for  an  unknown  is  satisfied  when  a 
particular  hypothesis  or  number  is  selected,  the  search  for  a  path  is 
really  a  search  for  a  Plan.  In  short,  we  are  once  more  confronted  by 
the  necessity  to  think  of  one  Plan  as  testing  and  operating  upon  an- 
other Plan,  a  level  of  complexity  we  have  met  before  in  discussing 
remembering  and  speaking. 

In  the  more  complex  kinds  of  problem-solving,  therefore,  we 
must  have  some  way  to  generate  alternative  Plans  and  then  to  operate 
on  them,  test  them,  evaluate  them.  These  metaplans — Plans  for 
forming  other  Plans — will  be  discussed  in  the  next  chapter,  along 
with  some  of  the  techniques  available  for  studying  the  properties  of 
these  complicated  systems. 

For  the  moment,  however,  we  want  to  pursue  the  question  of  the 

"Cited  in  Polya,  How  to  Solve  It,  pp.  141-147. 

Plans  for  Searching  and  Solving  ■    169 


search  process  as  a  paradigm  for  thinking  and  problem-solving.  There 
is  one  feature  of  any  search  process  that  is  absolutely  indispensable 
— the  searcher  must  be  able  to  recognize  the  thing  he  is  looking  for. 
No  doubt  everyone  has  had  the  experience  of  going  to  meet  a  perfect 
stranger  because  the  problem  of  identification  was  forgotten  when 
the  appointment  was  made.  Exactly  the  same  helpless  impotence 
afflicts  the  thinker  who  cannot  recognize  the  solution  to  his  problem. 
If  a  satisfactory  test  exists,  the  problem  is  said  to  be  "well  defined." 

The  test  of  a  search  TOTE  need  not  be  simple.  The  way  a  chemist 
tests  to  see  if  he  has  sulphur  may  involve  several  steps  and  much 
time.  The  way  a  mathematician  tests  to  see  if  he  has  determined 
the  correct  value  of  x  may  be  similarly  tedious.  And  the  question  of 
whether  a  particular  Plan  leads  to  a  valid  proof  can  require  a  consid- 
erable amount  of  skill  and  judgment.  The  test  phase  may  be  extremely 
complex  and  the  ability  to  perform  it  adequately  is  not  always  a 
trivial  matter.  If  there  is  any  single  caution  that  should  be  empha- 
sized more  than  the  others  when  considering  search  as  the  paradigm 
of  problem-solving,  it  is  this:  There  are  important  problems  whose 
solutions  cannot  be  identified  in  a  finite  number  of  steps,  so  that  no 
satisfactory  test  is  possible.  We  can  get  caught  looking  for  a  solution 
that  we  would  not  be  able  to  recognize  if  we  had  it.  When  we  use  the 
search  paradigm  for  problem-solving,  we  must  remember  that  it 
includes  cases  where  the  person  cannot  recognize  what  he  is  looking 
for. 

An  interesting  and  important  example  of  a  problem  for  which 
no  test  exists  is  the  following:  We  have  spoken  (see  Chapter  2)  of  the 
possibility  of  a  TOTE  hierarchy  falling  into  a  'loop"  of  tests.  The 
prototest  may  fail,  sending  the  system  into  a  series  of  TOTEs,  all  of 
which  pass,  thus  returning  the  system  to  the  prototest,  which  fails 
again,  sending  the  system  into  the  same  series  of  TOTEs  again,  etc. 
In  this  situation  it  is  necessary  to  have  a  stop-order  to  break  up  the 
loop — only  so  much  time,  or  so  many  operations,  or  so  much  fatigue, 
etc.,  will  be  tolerated  before  the  execution  of  the  Plan  is  halted.  But 
we  also  know  that  sometimes  our  stop-orders  are  issued  too  soon — 
that  what  appeared  to  be  a  loop  really  was  not — and  that  if  we  had 
persisted  a  bit  longer  the  Plan  would  have  worked.  What  we  would 
like,  therefore,  is  some  way  to  apply  the  stop-order  only  when  we  are 

170  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


really  in  a  loop,  but  not  to  apply  it  when  we  merely  appear  to  be  but 
really  are  not.  That  is  to  say,  we  would  like  to  have  some  test  that  we 
could  perform  on  our  Plans  that  would  tell  us  in  advance  whether  they 
would  work  in  a  finite  number  of  steps  or  whether  they  would  fall  into 
a  loop  and  go  on  forever  without  success.  But  no  such  test  exists. 
The  "halting  problem"  is  unsolvable.  The  only  thing  we  can  do  is  to 
adopt  an  arbitrary  criterion  that  reflects  the  value  to  us  of  the  out- 
come.^^  We  can  say,  "I  will  try  to  do  it  in  this  way  and  if,  after  N 
years,  I  have  not  succeeded,  then  I  will  stop."  The  problem  is  then 
to  determine  N  as  a  function  of  the  importance  of  the  problem. 

An  alternative  to  the  stop-rule  is  a  modification  of  the  conditions 
that  are  imposed  in  the  test  phase.  After  searching  unsuccessfully 
for  a  pen,  we  settle  for  a  pencil.  After  searching  unsuccessfully  for  a 
concept  that  will  identify  every  good  risk,  a  banker  finally  settles  for  a 
concept  that  will  work  19  times  out  of  20.  After  searching  unsuccess- 
fully for  a  Plan  that  will  integrate  two  incompatible  Plans  into  one, 
a  person  settles  for  one  or  the  other.  Half  a  loaf  is  better  than  no 
loaf.  There  are,  fortunately,  many  ways  to  compromise  with  reality, 
and  people  probably  revise  the  Image  as  often  as  they  give  up  the 
Plan. 

In  ordinary  affairs  we  usually  muddle  ahead,  doing  what  is 
habitual  and  customary,  being  slightly  puzzled  when  it  sometimes 
fails  to  give  the  intended  outcome,  but  not  stopping  to  worry  much 
about  the  failures  because  there  are  too  many  other  things  still  to  do. 
Then  circumstances  conspire  against  us  and  we  find  ourselves 
caught  failing  where  we  must  succeed — where  we  cannot  withdraw 
from  the  field,  or  lower  our  self-imposed  standards,  or  ask  for  help, 
or  throw  a  tantrum.  Then  we  may  begin  to  suspect  that  we  face  a 
problem.  But  at  first  it  is  not  clear  what  the  problem  is,  or  what  test 
would  have  to  be  satisfied  by  any  solution.  There  is  an  important  kind 
of  thinking  that  goes  on  at  this  stage — the  stage  in  which  the  problem 
becomes  defined — and  it  is  not  obvious  that  the  search  paradigm  is  the 
best  way  to  discuss  it.  Indeed,  the  very  act  of  discussing  it  seems  to 

^1  The  psychological  aspects  of  the  halting  problem  involve  persistence, 
satiation,  level  of  aspiration — aspects  that  have  been  studied  primarily  by  Levvin 
and  his  students.  For  a  review  of  this  work,  see  Leonard  Carmichael,  ed.,  Maiiiial 
of  Child  Psychology  (New  York:  Wiley,  1946),  Chapter  16,  especially  pp.  823- 
832. 

Plans  for  Searching  and  Solving  ■    171 


lend  to  it  a  degree  of  clarity  and  objectivity  that  makes  it  difficult  to 
remember  how  ineffably  confused  we  are  before  a  problem  is  well 
defined.  We  search  about,  exploring  a  hunch,  gambling  that  we  might 
get  a  good  idea  if  we  spent  some  time  on  this  or  that,  fiddling  with  a 
few  examples,  trying  to  imagine  what  is  missing  or  what  we  could  get 
rid  of,  but  never  being  certain  precisely  what  we  are  searching  for.  We 
are  trying  to  construct  a  better  Image  of  the  situation.  Whereas  the 
subject  in  a  psychological  experiment  has  the  problem  explained  to 
him  and  can  be  reasonably  confident  that  a  solution  exists,  the 
average  person  is  not  sure  there  really  is  a  problem,  or,  if  there  is, 
that  any  simple  test  for  its  solution  can  be  found,  or,  if  the  test 
exists,  that  any  solution  can  be  found  that  will  meet  the  test.  There 
is  a  great  deal  more  uncertainty  in  an  actual  problem-solving  situa- 
tion than  there  is  in  its  laboratory  counterpart.  The  statement  of  the 
problem  is  revised  repeatedly  as  we  struggle  with  it,  learn  more 
about  it,  and  build  a  richer,  clearer  Image  of  it.  Given  an  adequate 
Image,  of  course,  the  test  required  to  define  the  problem  should,  if 
it  exists,  form  a  part  of  it.  Frequently  the  problem  may  become  well 
defined  and  the  test  for  a  solution  become  obvious  at  just  about  the 
same  instant  that  the  solution  for  it  is  found. 

During  the  period  when  we  are  fumbling  about,  trying  to  clarify 
the  Image  in  order  to  discover  a  test  that  will  define  the  problem, 
we  still  use  heuristic  tricks,  but  we  frequently  use  them  without  any 
feedback,  without  any  assurance  that  they  are  taking  us  nearer  to  the 
definition  or  the  solution  of  a  problem.  It  is  a  little  like  trying  to 
develop  a  good  filing  system  without  knowing  exactly  what  the 
file  will  be  used  for.^^  We  may  revise  it  several  times,  as  we  learn  more 
about  what  must  go  into  it,  thus  deliberately  reverting  to  a  confused 
state  in  the  hope  of  putting  it  back  together  again  in  a  more  useful 
or  novel  form.  It  would  be  quite  wrong  to  believe  that  all  problems 
are  given  in  a  well-defined  form  and  that  thinking  consists  merely  of 

12  In  his  Heuristic  Aspects  of  the  Artificial  Intelligence  Problem,  Group 
Report  34-55,  Lincoln  Laboratory,  Massachusetts  Institute  of  Technology,  17 
December  1956,  M.  L.  Minsky  discusses  in  rather  general  terms  a  "character 
generator"  that  classifies  situations  and  keeps  a  record  of  which  heuristic 
methods  have  been  successful  with  which  classes  of  problems.  What  we  have 
called  "building  an  Image  of  the  problem  situation"  may  correspond  to  the  de- 
velopment of  a  useful  classification  scheme  in  Minsky's  discussion — in  which 
case  the  analogy  to  a  filing  system  would  be  quite  appropriate. 

172  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


searching  through  a  set  of  alternatives  for  one  that  wOl  work.  In  fact, 
some  people  argue  that  once  the  problem  has  been  well-defined  the 
"real"  thinking  is  all  over — that  carrying  out  the  search  for  a  solution 
is  just  a  mechanical  exercise  in  which  it  is  possible  to  be  efficient  or 
ingenious,  but  not  creative.  The  opinion  is  extreme,  of  course,  but  it 
makes  us  remember  that  many  people  represent  their  problems  in 
terms  of  clarifying  their  Image,  rather  than  in  terms  of  forming  a 
Plan  to  discover  the  solution.  Once  the  Image  is  correct,  they  argue, 
the  Plan  will  follow  directly.  The  answer  to  this  argument  is  that, 
unfortunately,  it  happens  to  be  false.  But  there  is  enough  truth  in  it 
to  make  us  pause. 

Is  there  an  alternative  to  the  search  paradigm  of  thinking?  Of 
course,  there  are  several.  For  example,  instead  of  discussing  every 
problem  as  a  search  for  an  object,  or  a  concept,  or  a  Plan,  we  might 
just  as  well  have  discussed  them  as  attempts  to  predict  what  is  going 
to  happen.  We  predict  the  hammer  will  be  found  in  the  workshop, 
then  test  the  prediction  by  looking  there.  We  predict  that  object  X  will 
be  called  a  positive  instance  of  the  concept,  and  so  we  inquire  about 
it  in  order  to  test  the  prediction.  We  predict  that  such  and  such  a  se- 
quence of  steps  will  generate  a  proof,  so  we  execute  them  in  order  to 
test  the  prediction.  It  should  be  apparent  that  this  substitution  of 
prediction  for  search  is  merely  a  new  way  of  discussing  the  TOTE 
units  involved;  the  test  phase  remains  the  same,  but  the  operate  phase 
is  now  called  "predicting"  instead  of  "searching."  Nevertheless,  the 
substitution  has  heuristic  value,  for  it  encourages  us  to  look  at  the 
same  processes  in  a  different  way  and  so  enriches  our  understanding 
of  them. 

The  prediction  paradigm  for  thinking  and  problem-solving  tends 
to  direct  our  attention  more  to  the  Image  than  to  the  Plan,  because 
the  test  of  the  prediction  provides  us  with  a  confirmation  or  infirma- 
tion  of  the  Image  that  supported  the  prediction.  Galanter  and 
Gerstenhaber  comment  that  "imaginal  thinking  is  neither  more  nor 
less  than  constructing  an  image  or  model  of  the  environment,  running 
the  model  faster  than  the  environment,  and  predicting  that  the 
environment  will  behave  as  the  model  does."  ^^  According  to  this 
view,  the  elements  with  which  the  problem-solver  seems  to  work  are 

13  Galanter  and  Gerstenhaber,  op.  cit.,  p.  219. 

Plans  for  Searching  and  Solving  ■    173 


his  perceptual  image  of  the  situation  before  he  does  anything,  his 
imagination  image  of  what  the  situation  will  be  like  if  he  takes  a 
particular  course  of  action,  his  perception  of  the  situation  after  he 
does  something,  his  image  of  some  ideal  situation  that  he  might  hope 
to  attain,  etc.  And  each  of  these  images  must  have  some  evaluation 
on  a  utility  scale,  and  the  decision  to  execute  a  particular  Plan  will 
depend  upon  the  payoff  function  defined  by  these  utilities.  Descrip- 
tions of  problem-solving  and  thinking  that  place  the  emphasis  on  the 
Image  frequently  correspond  better  to  our  personal  intuitions  about 
what  is  going  on — the  imaginal  part  of  the  process  is  much  more 
accessible  to  awareness  than  is  the  part  that  deals  with  the  formation 
of  a  Plan.  An  ordinary  person  almost  never  approaches  a  problem 
systematically  and  exhaustively  unless  he  has  been  specifically 
educated  to  do  so.  It  is  much  more  natural  for  him  to  visualize  what 
is  and  what  ought  to  be  and  to  focus  on  the  gap  between  them  than 
to  visualize  some  huge  set  of  alternative  possibilities  through  which 
he  must  search.  In  other  words,  the  phenomenological  aspects  of 
problem-solving  are  more  frequently  connected  with  alternative 
Images  than  with  alternative  Plans. 

Thus  we  see  there  are  at  least  two  ways  to  represent  the  infor- 
mation-processing that  goes  on  during  thinking  and  problem-solving. 
According  to  the  prediction  paradigm,  the  main  source  of  trouble  in 
solving  problems  arises  from  the  inadequacy  of  the  Image  of  the 
problem  situation.  It  is  necessary  to  collect  more  information,  to  at- 
tempt various  organizations,  to  destroy  old  Images  in  order  to  replace 
them  by  new,  to  transfer  Images  from  more  familiar  situations.  In 
order  to  verify  an  Image  as  it  develops,  it  is  necessary  to  make  predic- 
tions and  to  test  them,  to  probe  for  the  places  where  our  knowledge  is 
thin  and  our  understanding  weak.  We  may  not  have  the  leisure  to 
collect  all  the  information  we  could  use  and  we  may  need  to  settle  for 
an  Image  that  is  only  approximate.  Moreover,  the  information  we 
need  is  not  "given"  with  some  guarantee  that  it  is  relevant  or  impor- 
tant— we  have  to  dig  for  it,  and  even  then  the  data  we  gather  may  be 
useless  once  we  achieve  a  stable  cognitive  structure.  The  process  of 
making  predictions  may  itself  involve  considerable  time  and  expense, 
so  that  we  must  be  quite  circumspect  about  the  predictions  we  decide 
to  test. 

174  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


All  of  these  comments  can  be  paralleled  in  the  search  paradigm : 
The  main  source  of  trouble  in  solving  problems  arises  from  the  fact 
that  the  set  of  alternatives  may  be  extremely  large,  perhaps  infinite, 
and  the  acceptable  solutions  may  be  scattered  haphazardly  so  that 
they  are  hard  to  find.  In  few  situations  are  w^e  completely  free  to 
start  examining  exhaustively  and  systematically  all  the  various  pos- 
sible permutations  of  atomic  elements.  If  a  test  is  expensive  to  apply, 
we  will  want  to  find  a  solution  with  as  few  applications  as  possible. 
Moreover,  alternative  hypotheses  are  seldom  "given"  in  the  sense 
that  we  need  merely  point  to  the  one  we  want — usually  they  must  be 
generated  according  to  rules.  The  process  of  generating  potential 
solutions  may  itself  involve  considerable  time  and  expense.  We  can- 
not dismiss  the  task  of  searching  efficiently  as  a  mere  mechanical 
exercise  suitable  only  for  second-rate  thinkers. 

Sometimes  one  of  these  representations  will  be  more  helpful, 
sometimes  the  other,  depending  upon  whether  the  heart  of  the  diffi- 
culty lies  in  the  construction  of  a  better  Image  or  the  elaboration 
of  a  better  Plan.  Both  can,  the  authors  believe,  be  discussed  in  terms 
of  the  TOTE  schema.  In  the  context  of  this  book,  however,  we  must 
concentrate  our  attention  principally  upon  the  latter  kind  of  problem. 
In  the  next  chapter,  therefore,  we  shall  consider  how  people  formu- 
late heuristic  Plans  to  search  for  the  answer  to  well-defined  problems. 
This  emphasis,  however,  should  not  be  understood  to  mean  that  the 
authors  wish  to  reject  the  vast  domain  of  ill-defined  problems  or  to 
deny  the  critical  importance  of  refining  our  Images.  For  as  our  Images 
become  more  accurate  and  more  elaborate  and  more  useful,  we  will 
become  able  to  define  more  and  more  problems — to  translate  them 
from  the  domain  of  mere  difficulties  into  the  domain  of  practical 
problems,  to  make  them  into  something  we  can  solve  instead  of  some- 
thing we  must  ignore  or  overpower  or  circumvent. 


Plans  for  Searching  and  Solving  •   175 


CHAPTER  13 


THE   FORMATION   OF 

PLANS 


Where  do  Plans  come  from?  Probably  the  major  source  of  new 
Plans  is  old  Plans.  We  change  them  around  a  little  bit  each  time  we 
use  them,  but  they  are  basically  the  same  old  Plans  with  minor  varia- 
tions. Sometimes  we  may  borrow  a  new  Plan  from  someone  else. 
But  we  do  not  often  create  a  completely  new  Plan. 

Consider  the  origins  of  the  Plans  we  have  discussed:  Instincts 
are  inherited  Plans  and  so  are  not  created  by  the  individual  who 
executes  them.  Habits  and  skills  are  most  frequently  acquired  by 
imitation  or  verbal  instruction  from  another  person,  although  they 
may  develop  inadvertently  as  we  attempt  to  cope  with  the  pattern  of 
events  around  us.  Shared  Plans  are  normally  communicated  to  us  as 
participants,  but  even  when  we  help  to  originate  a  new  shared  Plan 
we  usually  try  to  form  it  along  lines  already  familiar.  Plans  for  re- 
membering attempt  to  exploit  familiar  situations  and  previously 
established  associations.  When  we  speak  we  usually  try  to  say  some- 
thing that  is  not  completely  predictable,  but  the  novelty  of  what  we 
say  is  always  subject  to  well-established  grammatical  Plans  that  we 

The  Formation  of  Plans  "177 


are  not  at  liberty  to  revise.  Even  in  thinking  and  problem-solving 
we  are  continually  executing  Plans  tediously  mastered  at  school. 

This  attitude  toward  the  question  of  where  we  get  our  Plans  re- 
sembles the  attitude  of  Boston  matrons  toward  their  hats :  "My  dear, 
we  don't  get  our  hats,  we  have  them."  The  analogy  could  be  improved, 
however,  if  they  had  a  few  hats  and  only  the  pattern  for  many  others. 
When  we  say  that  most  Plans  are  remembered,  not  created,  we  do  not 
mean  that  the  Plan  is  stored  in  memory  ready  for  execution  down  to 
the  very  last  muscle  twitch.  Often  it  is  a  metaplan  that  is  stored — a 
metaplan  from  which  a  large  number  of  different  Plans  can  be 
generated  as  they  are  needed. 

When  do  we  store  Plans  directly  and  when  do  we  store  Plans  for 
generating  Plans?  For  example,  the  Plan  for  reciting  the  alphabet  is 
probably  stored — memorized — directly,  like  any  other  motor  skill. 
And  so  is  the  Plan  for  counting,  at  least  through  the  first  few  hundred 
integers.  But  as  the  numbers  begin  to  get  large  it  is  likely  that  we 
work  in  terms  of  a  metaplan,  a  set  of  rules  for  generating  N  +  1 
from  N,  rather  than  with  a  direct  Plan  for  uttering  the  successive 
integers.  There  are  interesting  questions  here  concerning  the  mental 
economies  involved — how  frequently  must  a  Plan  be  used  before  it  is 
worth  our  while  to  memorize  it  directly  rather  than  to  remember  a 
Plan  for  reconstructing  it? 

A  kind  of  low-level  creativity  is  displayed  by  any  system  complex 
enough  to  have  mataplans.  For  example,  in  using  an  electronic  com- 
puter to  make  calculations  involving  logarithms,  a  decision  must  be 
made  whether  to  store  a  table  of  logarithms  in  the  computer's  mem- 
ory or  to  give  the  computer  a  formula  for  calculating  logarithms  as 
they  are  needed.  If  the  table  is  used,  the  logarithm  will  be  rapidly 
found  if  it  is  in  the  table,  but  the  computer  will  be  unable  to  handle 
any  numbers  whose  logarithms  it  has  not  been  given  explicitly.  If  the 
formula  is  used  the  process  will  be  slower,  but  the  computer  will  be 
able  to  "create"  the  logarithms  of  numbers  it  has  not  seen  before. 
Therein  lies  a  great  advantage  of  formulas,  sets  of  rules,  metaplans: 
They  are  easily  stored,  and  when  there  is  time  to  use  them  they  can  be 
projected  into  an  infinite  variety  of  unforeseen  situations.  The  ad- 
vantages of  having  Plans  to  generate  Plans  is  so  great  that  no  intelli- 
gent automaton,  living  or  dead,  could  get  along  without  them.  They 

178  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


not  only  permit  the  electronic  computer  to  seem  creative  in  a  trivial 
way  with  logarithms,  they  permit  men  to  be  creative  in  significant 
ways  in  a  wide  variety  of  situations. 

Consider  some  well-defined  problem,  such  as  finding  a  proof  of  a 
mathematical  expression,  and  note  the  levels  of  metaplanning  that 
are  involved.  The  expression  is  itself  a  Plan  that  can  be  used  to  carry 
out  some  particular  arithmetic  operations — it  has  its  own  hierarchical 
organization  and  can  be  analyzed  in  much  the  same  way  a  sentence 
can  be  parsed.  The  proof  is  a  sequence  of  those  mathematical  expres- 
sions and  will  characteristically  have  its  own  hierarchical  struc- 
ture. Thus,  the  proof  is  also  a  Plan.  And  it  is  a  metaplan  because?  the 
objects  it  operates  on  are  themselves  Plans.  But  the  system  cannot 
stop  there.  There  is  a  third  level  of  planning  that  we  discover  as  soon 
as  we  think  of  the  procedures  that  the  mathematician  used  in  order 
to  generate  the  proof.  If  the  proof  is  a  path  leading  from  the  expres- 
sions that  were  given  to  the  expression  that  was  to  be  proved,  then 
the  mathematician  had  to  explore  a  great  variety  of  possible  paths  in 
order  to  find  this  one.  As  we  noted  in  Chapter  12,  searches  are  gen- 
erally conducted  according  to  some  kind  of  Plan,  usually  a  heuristic 
Plan.  So  we  must  have  a  heuristic  Plan  for  generating  a  proof  Plan 
for  transforming  a  mathematical  Plan  for  performing  certain  com- 
putations. Does  it  stop  there?  Is  it  necessary  to  add  the  students 
of  heuristic — mathematicians,  computer  engineers,  psychologists, 
teachers,  etc. — who  may  someday  be  able  to  specify  hierarchical 
organizations  for  generating  heuristics?  Is  it  possible  for  all  Plans 
to  have  metaplans  that  write  'em,  and  so  on  ad  infinitum?  Or  is 
heuristic  the  end  of  the  line?  It  seems  that  heuristic  Plans  ar6  as  far 
as  one  can  go  in  this  regression,  for  the  methods  used  to  discover  new 
heuristic  Plans  would  themselves  be  heuristic  Plans.  A  plausible 
account  of  heuristic  Plans,  therefore,  will  provide  the  general  out- 
lines within  which  a  theory  of  thinking  about  well-defined  problems 
can  eventually  be  constructed. 

In  his  popular  text,  Hoiu  to  Solve  It,  Polya  distinguishes  four 
phases  in  the  heuristic  process : 

— First,  we  must  understand  the  problem.  We  have  to  see  clearly 
what  the  data  are,  what  conditions  are  imposed,  and  what  the  un- 
known thing  is  that  we  are  searching  for. 

The  Formation  of  Plaris  ■    179 


— Second,  we  must  devise  a  plan  that  will  guide  the  solution 
and  connect  the  data  to  the  unknown. 

— Third,  we  must  carry  out  our  plan  of  the  solution,  checking 
each  step  as  we  go. 

— Fourth,  we  should  look  back  at  the  completed  solution,  review- 
ing, checking,  discussing,  perhaps  even  improving  it. 

Obviously,  the  second  of  these  is  most  critical.  The  first  is  es- 
sentially what  we  have  described  in  Chapter  12  as  the  construction 
of  a  clear  Image  of  the  situation  in  order  to  establish  a  test  for  the 
solution  of  the  problem;  it  is  indispensable,  of  course,  but  in  the 
discussion  of  well-defined  problems  we  assume  that  it  has  already 
been  accomplished.  The  third  is  what  we  have  described  as  the 
execution  of  a  Plan,  and  although  it  may  be  costly  or  require  much 
skill,  we  assume  that  it  can  be  performed  in  a  straightforward  man- 
ner. The  fourth  phase  is  important  for  the  student  who  wants  to 
develop  his  ability  to  solve  problems,  for  it  facilitates  storing  the 
method  for  future  use.  However,  it  is  in  the  second  phase,  the  actual 
formation  of  a  Plan,  that  something  creative  must  happen.  As  Polya 
describes  it : 

We  have  a  plan  when  we  know,  or  at  least  know  in  outline, 
which  calculations,  computations,  or  constructions  we  have  to 
perform  in  order  to  obtain  the  unknown.  The  way  from  under- 
standing the  problem  to  conceiving  a  plan  may  be  long  and 
tortuous.  In  fact,  the  main  achievement  in  the  solution  of  a  prob- 
lem is  to  conceive  the  idea  of  a  plan.  This  idea  may  emerge 
gradually.  Or,  after  apparently  unsuccessful  trials  and  a  period 
of  hesitation,  it  may  occur  suddenly,  in  a  flash,  as  a  'Ibright 
idea."  ^ 

Polya  presents  the  heuristic  devices  that  mathematicians  use  in 
the  form  of  questions,  a  kind  of  dialogue  between  a  teacher  and  a 
student.  The  first  question  to  ask  is  whether  you  know  of  a  related 
problem.  Usually  there  are  many  related  problems  and  the  problem 
is  to  choose  the  right  one.  A  suggestion  that  points  toward  an  essen- 
tial common  point  is:  Look  at  the  unknown  and  try  to  think  of  a 
familiar  problem  that  has  the  same  or  a  similar  unknown.  If  this  does 
not  suggest  a  plan,  can  you  restate  the  problem?  If  you  cannot  solve 

1  G.  Polya,  How  to  Solve  It  (Princeton:  Princeton  University  Press,  1945), 
p.  8. 

i8o  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


the  proposed  problem,  perhaps  you  can  solve  some  related  problem. 
Can  you  decompose  it  into  several  simpler  problems?  Perhaps  you 
can  work  backwards — from  what  antecedent  could  the  desired  result 
be  derived?  Each  of  these  heuristic  devices  is  discussed  by  Polya  in 
terms  of  specific  examples. 

Consider  this  puzzle:  How  can  you  bring  up  from  the  river 
exactly  six  quarts  of  water  when  you  have  only  two  containers,  a  four- 
quart  pail  and  a  nine-quart  pail?  The  answer  is  not  immediately  ap- 
parent. What  related  problem  can  we  solve?  We  could  get  eight 
quarts  by  twice  filling  the  small  pail  and  emptying  it  into  the  large 
pail.  Or  we  could  get  five  quarts  by  filling  the  larger  nine-quart  pail 
and  then  pouring  off  as  much  as  we  can  into  the  smaller,  four-quart 
pail.  But  the  desired  amount  is  six  quarts.  We  are  not  making  much 
progress  working  forwards  from  the  given  conditions  to  the  desired 
result.  Perhaps  we  could  work  backwards.  What  is  the  situation  we 
are  trying  to  reach?  Imagine  six  quarts  of  water  in  the  large  pail. 
From  what  antecedent  condition  could  this  be  derived?  If  the  large 
container  were  filled  and  we  could  pour  out  three  quarts,  we  would 
have  the  desired  result.  From  what  antecedent  condition  could  this 
be  derived?  If  the  small  pail  already  held  one  quart,  we  would  have 
the  condition  we  need.  From  what  antecedent  could  this  be  derived? 
We  could  measure  one  quart  by  filling  the  nine-quart  pail,  discarding 
four  quarts  twice  with  the  small  pail,  and  then  pouring  the  remaining 
one  quart  into  the  small  pail.  And  so,  by  working  backwards,  we  reach 
something  that  we  know  how  to  do.  If  we  now  reverse  the  whole 
process,  we  have  our  plan  for  measuring  out  the  six  quarts.  This 
heuristic  principle — said  to  have  been  described  first  by  Plato — is  to 
concentrate  on  the  unknown  and  to  try  to  see  what  could  have  led  to 
it;  it  works  not  only  in  solving  water-measuring  problems  but  in  a 
great  variety  of  other  problems  as  well.  (The  principle  is  perhaps 
most  apparent  when  we  note  how  easy  it  is  to  run  a  multiple-T  maze 
from  the  goal  box  to  the  start,  and  how  difficult  it  is  to  find  the  right 
path  in  the  opposite  direction.)  Working  backwards  is  one  of  many 
heuristic  methods  known  to  aU  good  problem-solvers. 

A  critic  of  the  present  argument  would  have  the  right  at  this 
point  to  register  a  number  of  protests.  His  complaints  might  run 
something  like  this:    (1)  Metaplans  that  generate  metaplans  that 

The  Formation  of  Plans  ■    i8i 


generate  still  more  Plans  are  far  too  complicated.  A  good  scientist  can 
draw  an  elephant  with  three  parameters,  and  with  four  he  can  tie  a 
knot  in  its  tail.  There  must  be  hundreds  of  parameters  floating  around 
in  this  kind  of  theory  and  nobody  will  ever  be  able  to  untangle  them. 
(2)  These  rough,  heuristic  rules  of  thumb,  these  probes  and  ques- 
tions, these  maxims  and  proverbs  can  be  used  only  by  people  with 
enough  intelligence  to  understand  them  and  see  how  to  apply  them. 
They  cannot  be  seriously  proposed  as  unambiguous  components  of  a 
scientific  theory.  (3)  Even  if  we  took  this  approach  seriously,  there 
is  no  way  to  put  it  to  the  test  of  experimentation.  The  evidence  for  it 
is  not  even  simple  introspection — the  argument  is  based  on  what 
must  lie  behind  introspection.  It  violates  all  the  rules  of  the  behav- 
ioristic  tradition  and  threatens  to  set  psychology  back  at  least  N 
years  (where  N  measures  the  intensity  of  the  critic's  emotional 
response). 

These  are  good  criticisms  and  they  must  be  met.  The  answer  to 
the  first  one  is  clear  enough :  If  the  description  is  valid,  then  the  fact 
that  it  is  very  complicated  cannot  be  helped.  No  benign  and  par- 
simonious deity  has  issued  us  an  insurance  policy  against  complexity. 
However,  there  is  no  need  to  become  discouraged  on  that  account,  for 
within  the  past  decade  or  so  electronic  engineers  have  begun  to  de- 
velop computing  machines  that  are  big  enough  and  fast  enough  to 
serve  as  models  for  testing  complicated  theories.  Describe  the  theory 
carefully,  translate  the  description  into  a  computer  program,  run  the 
program  on  a  computer,  and  see  if  it  reacts  the  same  way  organisms 
do.  Now  that  we  know  how  to  write  such  programs — especially  since 
the  work  of  Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon  ^ — we  can  begin  to  test  ideas 
that  would  probably  have  seemed  impossibly  complicated  to  an 
earlier  generation  of  psychologists.  Computer  engineers  have  only 
just  begun  to  explore  the  possibilities  of  self-programming  automata 
— we  can  look  forward  to  many  new  discoveries  as  they  learn  more 
and  more  about  what  Norbert  Wiener  calls  "the  problems  of  organ- 
ized complexity." 

2  The  earliest  description  of  the  use  of  list  structures  to  develop  flexible 
information-processing  languages  in  order  to  simulate  cognitive  processes  with 
heuristic  programs  seems  to  be  in  the  paper  by  AUen  Newell  and  Herbert  A. 
Simon,  The  logic  theory  machine:  A  complex  information  processing  system, 
IRE  Transactions  on  Information  Theory,  1956,  Vol.  IT-2,  No.  3,  61-79. 

182  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


The  possibility  of  using  electronic  computers  gives  us  an  answer 
to  the  second  criticism,  as  well.  If  the  heuristic  devices  that  thinkers 
say  they  are  using  can  be  translated  into  programs  that  reproduce 
the  results  obtained  by  the  person,  then  we  have  every  reason  to 
believe  that  the  heuristic  device  was  a  true  description  of  his  pro- 
cedure in  solving  the  problem.  If  the  heuristic  method  is  ambiguous, 
the  program  simply  wUl  not  work.  With  this  test  available,  therefore, 
heuristic  rules  of  thumb  can  indeed  be  proposed  as  elements  of  a 
serious  theory  of  thinking. 

The  proposal  that  a  theory  of  thinking  and  problem-solving 
should  include  all  the  heuristic  rules  men  have  discovered  does  not 
originate  with  the  present  authors,  of  course.  It  has  a  long  and 
distinguished  history,  for  it  appears  implicitly  in  almost  every  sub- 
jective description  of  the  problem-solving  process.  Without  a  good 
supply  of  heuristic  methods  no  artist  could  create,  no  scientist  could 
discover,  no  technician  could  invent.  In  most  cases,  however,  the 
discussions  of  heuristic  schemes  have  been  little  more  than  cata- 
logues of  useful  tricks.^  Only  recently  have  workers  begun  to  ex- 
plore the  possibility  that  the  catalogue  might  be  converted  into  a 
coherent  theory. 

Marvin  Minsky,  noting  the  extent  to  which  language  guides  our 
problem-solving  efforts,  has  suggested  that  one  way  to  develop  a 
theory  of  heuristic  would  be  to  design  or  evolve  a  language  through 
which  the  machine  can  be  given  heuristic  suggestions  which  it  can 
try  to  realize  in  a  variety  of  reasonable  ways.*  We  would  then  be  able 
to  communicate  with  the  machine  in  much  the  same  way  Polya  com- 
municates vvdth  his  students.  Of  course,  the  machine  would  have  to 
provide  an  intelligent  description  of  what  it  was  trying  to  do,  for 
otherwise  it  would  be  difficult  to  know  what  suggestions  to  make. 
But  the  machine  would  slowly  accumulate  its  own  private  catalogue 
of  heuristic  tricks,  just  as  the  student  does.  Then  we  could  take  the 
machine  apart  and  see  how  it  worked — an  analysis  to  which  few 

3  For  example,  in  Abraham  A.  Moles,  La  Creation  Scientifique  (Ren^  Kister: 
Geneva,  1957),  there  is  a  list  of  twenty-one  different  heuristic  methods  that 
Moles  has  been  able  to  distinguish  and  exemplify  in  the  historical  development 
of  science  and  technology. 

*  M.  L.  Minsky,  Heuristic  Aspects  of  the  Artificial  Intelligence  Problem, 
Group  Report  34-55,  Lincoln  Laboratory,  Massachusetts  Institute  of  Technology, 
17  December  1956,  p.  III-23. 

The  Formation  of  Plans  ■   183 


students  are  willing  to  submit.  In  Minsky's  view,  which  is  broadly 
the  same  as  the  present  authors',  verbal  information  provides  an 
organism  with  "a  set  of  instructions  for  constructing,  in  its  head, 
out  of  parts  available  there,  a  machine  to  perform  a  response  of  the 
desired  kind."  ^  As  he  points  out,  a  machine  that  uses  language  as  we 
do  would  have  to  contain  a  fairly  powerful,  general-purpose  machine 
that,  under  the  direction  of  linguistic  signals,  could  construct  a 
variety  of  special-purpose  machines.  If  such  a  machine  was  told  to  try 
to  construct  a  Plan  by  working  backwards,  for  example,  it  would 
presumably  know  how  to  do  so.  Children  acquire  their  store  of 
heuristic  methods  by  listening  to  verbal  suggestions  and  then  trying 
to  execute  them,  and  perhaps  that  is  also  the  best  way  to  let  the  ma- 
chines evolve.  If  we  want  to  develop  a  self-programming  automaton, 
maybe  we  should  let  it  learn  the  way  we  do. 

Yet  the  fact  that  students  of  heuristic  talk  about  such  schemes 
does  not  mean  that  they  are  able  to  carry  them  out.  Our  critic  should 
not  be  put  off  by  appeals  to  authority  or  by  evidence  that  computers 
are  both  impressive  and  fashionable.  Talk  about  self-programming 
machines  could  create  an  impression  that  all  of  psychology's  prob- 
lems have  been  locked  tightly  in  a  box  labeled  "Plan  Generator," 
never  to  be  opened  again.  In  order  to  meet  the  criticism  head-on, 
therefore,  we  should,  even  before  considering  the  third  complaint, 
give  some  more  concrete  description  of  how  heuristic  Plans  can  be 
realized  in  actual  machines. 

Let  us  consider  chess  and  the  way  a  computer  might  use  heuris- 
tic Plans  in  order  to  play  that  game.  One's  first  thought,  perhaps,  is  to 
compute  all  possible  continuations  from  a  given  position,  then  choose 
one  that  led  to  a  checkmate  of  the  opposing  king.  Unfortunately,  even 
the  fastest  electronic  computers  we  have  would  be  unable  to  execute 
that  exhaustive  Plan  in  a  reasonable  period  of  time.  It  is  necessary, 
therefore,  to  use  heuristic  Plans.  But  what  heuristic  Plans  do  we  have 
for  playing  chess?  These  can  be  found  in  any  chess  manual  for  begin- 
ners; they  include  such  maxims  as,  "Try  to  control  the  four  center 
squares,"  or  "Always  make  sure  your  King  is  safe  before  you  attack," 
or  "Do  not  attack  the  opposing  position  until  your  own  position  is 
developed,"  etc.  How  can  these  heuristic  principles  be  used  to  control 
what  the  machine  will  do? 

6  Ibid.,  p.  III-18. 

184  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon  have  analyzed  the  traditional  chess 
heuristics  into  six  independent  "goals":  (1 )  King  safety,  (2)  material 
balance,  (3)  center  control,  (4)  development,  (5)  King-side  attack, 
and  (6)  promotion  of  Pawns."  This  ordering  of  the  goals  is  significant, 
because  the  machine  always  tries  to  achieve  them  in  that  same  order. 
That  is  to  say,  first  the  machine  will  look  to  see  if  its  King  is  safe.  If 
not,  it  will  try  to  defend  it;  if  so,  it  will  go  on  to  the  next  goal.  The 
next  thing  the  machine  will  do  is  to  check  up  on  the  possible  ex- 
changes, to  make  sure  that  its  pieces  are  adequately  protected.  If 
not,  the  machine  will  protect  them;  if  so,  the  machine  will  turn  next 
to  center  control.  Can  it  move  its  Pawns  into  the  center?  If  so,  it  is 
done;  if  not,  the  machine  turns  to  development,  then  to  attacking 
the  King;  and  finally,  if  none  of  those  goals  leads  to  a  good  move,  the 
machine  will  consider  the  Pawn  structure. 

Associated  with  each  of  the  goals  is  a  set  of  rules  for  generating 
moves  that  are  relevant  to  that  goal.  For  example,  when  the  machine 
applies  the  center-control  heuristic,  it  will  first  propose  moving  Pawn 
to  Queen  4,  then  Pawn  to  King  4,  then  will  propose  moves  that  may 
prevent  the  opponent  from  making  these  two  key  moves,  then  pro- 
pose moves  that  prepare  for  making  these  moves  (e.g.,  adding  de- 
fenders to  the  Queen  4  or  the  King  4  squares,  or  removing  some  block 
to  moving  the  Queen's  Pawn  or  the  King's  Pawn). 

When  the  move  generator  has  proposed  something  to  do,  the 
machine  does  not  automatically  accept  it,  of  course.  The  proposal 
must  be  evaluated  to  see  if  it  really  achieves  the  desired  results.  The 
evaluation  cannot  be  limited  to  a  single  goal,  however,  for  a  move 
that  would  look  very  good  to  the  center-control  Plan  might  utterly 
destroy  the  King's  position,  or  lose  a  piece,  etc.  The  proposed  move 
must  be  analyzed  in  terms  of  aU  six  goals.  The  value  of  a  move 
is  a  vector.  The  value  of  a  move  for  center  control  is  obtained  by 
counting  the  number  of  blocks  there  are  to  making  the  two  key  Pawn 
moves.  The  component  representing  material  balance  will  assign  the 
conventional  numerical  values  to  the  pieces,  examine  certain  con- 
tinuations until  no  further  exchanges  are  possible,  and  note  the 

*  Allen  Newell,  J.  C.  Shaw,  and  H.  A.  Simon,  Chess-playing  problems  and 
the  problem  of  complexity,  IBM  Journal  of  Research  and  Development,  1958, 
2,  320-335.  This  article  contains,  in  addition  to  the  description  of  their  own 
work,  an  account  of  the  history  of  the  problem  beginning  with  Shannon's  paper 
in  1949  (see  footnote  25  in  Chapter  3). 

The  Formation  of  Plans  ■   185 


change  in  material.  (The  evaluation  of  moves  with  respect  to  mate- 
rial balance  is  exceedingly  complex  and  involves  numerous  other 
heuristic  principles.)  And  so  the  evaluation  proceeds  through  the 
different  goals. 

Now,  when  the  machine  has  found  a  move  that  all  the  different 
heuristic  goals  approve,  the  move  may  still  not  be  made.  There  may 
be  an  even  better  move  possible.  Thus,  the  machine  has  the  problem 
of  making  a  choice  among  the  moves  after  they  have  been  evaluated. 
There  are  several  different  ways  it  could  proceed,  but  there  is  one 
thing  it  cannot  do:  It  cannot  wait  until  all  the  possible  proposals 
have  been  made  and  evaluated  in  order  to  select  the  one  with  highest 
value.  There  are  far  too  many  proposals  possible.  Newell,  Shaw,  and 
Simon  suggest  that  the  simplest  choice  procedure  is  to  set  an  accept- 
ance level  arbitrarily  (a  mechanical  'level  of  aspiration")  and  simply 
to  take  the  first  acceptable  move.  In  order  to  avoid  the  possibility 
that  no  conceivable  move  would  meet  the  criterion,  a  stop-order  can 
also  be  imposed;  save  the  best  move  discovered  up  to  this  point  and, 
if  the  time-limit  expires  before  an  acceptable  move  has  been  found, 
make  the  best  one  that  was  found. 

In  order  to  be  completely  concrete,  we  should  examine  the 
routines  used  to  generate  and  evaluate  the  moves  in  more  detail,  but 
that  would  take  us  too  far  from  the  main  argument  of  this  book.  A 
critic  who  still  doubts  that  heuristic  rules  can  be  incorporated  into 
completely  deterministic  programs  suitable  for  guiding  the  behavior 
of  an  automaton  will  have  to  pursue  his  doubts  into  the  original 
articles  themselves.  We  should,  however,  pause  long  enough  to  try 
to  express  the  Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon  program  in  the  language  used 
in  the  present  book — not  because  it  adds  anything  to  their  descrip- 
tion, but  simply  to  make  clear  that  their  work  does  indeed  illustrate, 
and  lend  credibility  to,  the  less  explicit  notions  about  information- 
processing  that  we  have  applied  to  psychological  questions  in  these 
pages. 

There  are  several  ways  that  TOTE  hierarchies  could  be  organized 
to  play  chess,  all  of  them  using  the  heuristics  that  Newell,  Shaw,  and 
Simon  have  programmed,  but  the  one  that  seems  simplest  and  near- 
est to  the  spirit  of  their  work  has  two  major  subplans,  one  for  gen- 
erating the  moves,  the  other  for  evaluating  them.  The  prototest  could 

i86  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


be  the  question,  "Who  plays  next?"  If  the  machine  is  to  play,  the 
operational  phase,  "Make  a  move,"  is  executed.  This  operation 
has  two  tests,  "What  move?"  and,  when  that  has  been  answered,  "Is 
that  the  best  move?"  The  operational  phase  of  the  move  generator 
has  six  tests,  all  of  the  intuitive  form,  "If  you  do  not  have  a  move,  why 
not  try  to  X?"  where  X  is  one  of  the  six  goals.  If  no  move  has  been 
selected,  then  the  operational  phase  of  X  will  be  executed.  In  the 
case  of  center  control,  for  example,  it  will  consist  of  a  string  of  tests 
of  the  form,  "Have  you  tried  P-Q4?"  "Have  you  tried  P-K4?"  "Have  you 
tried  to  prevent  him  from  moving  P-Q4?"  and  so  on.  Each  of  these  can 
be  further  elaborated.  Eventually  a  legal  move  is  selected  and  then 
control  is  transferred  to  the  evaluation  routine.  This  also  has  six 
parts,  one  for  each  of  the  goals;  and  each  question,  "How  does  it 
affect  the  safety  of  the  King?"  or  "How  does  it  affect  the  balance  of 
material?"  etc.,  has  associated  with  it  operational  phases  which  are 
more  or  less  elaborate  according  to  how  difficult  the  question  is  to 
answer.  We  could,  if  it  seemed  desirable,  permit  any  of  the  six 
individual  evaluation  routines  to  reject  a  proposed  move  if  it  tested 
out  too  badly  with  respect  to  that  particular  goal — that  decision 
would  make  it  difficult  for  the  machine  to  offer  sacrifices,  however, 
so  it  is  probably  wiser  to  postpone  any  rejections  until  the  result  of  all 
six  evaluation  routines  are  collected  and  compared  with  similar 
evaluations  of  other  moves.  Amateur  chess-players  are  not  always 
that  wise,  however,  and  will  frequently  reject  a  move  because  of  some 
glaring  disadvantage — only  to  discover  its  compensating  advantages 
later  when  they  study  the  games  of  a  master.  It  is  not  our  present 
purpose  to  offer  alternatives  to  the  Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon  program, 
however,  but  merely  to  illustrate  that  their  heuristic  programs  do  not 
confute  or  conflict  with  the  idea  of  Plans  presented  here. 

There  are  many  other  heuristic  devices  that  we  might  discuss. 
One  of  the  most  interesting  is  the  use  of  a  "diagramming  heuristic" 
in  a  geometry  program  written  by  H.  L.  Gelemter  and  N.  Rochester.'' 
They    used    the    heuristic    programming    techniques    developed    by 

^  H.  L.  Gelemter  and  N.  Rochester,  Intelligent  behavior  in  problem-solving 
machines,  IBM  Journal  of  Research  and  Development,  1958,  2,  336—345.  The  idea 
seems  to  have  originated  at  the  Dartmouth  Summer  Research  Project  on  Artifi- 
cial Intelligence  in  1956,  particularly  in  discussion  among  John  McCarthy, 
Marvin  L.  Minsky,  and  Nathaniel  Rochester. 

The  Formation  of  Plans  ■   187 


Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon  in  order  to  make  a  computer  tackle  geom- 
etry problems  in  the  same  fashion  as  a  high-school  student.  Geomet- 
ric proofs  are  typically  rather  long  and  it  is  almost  impossible  to 
discover  them  by  any  exhaustive  procedure  of  trying  all  possible 
sequences  of  transformations.  In  this  situation  the  human  geometer 
will  draw  a  figure  that  contains  the  essential  conditions  of  the  prob- 
lem and  then  study  the  figure  until  he  develops  some  Plan  for  the 
proof.  He  may  check  with  other  figures  in  order  to  make  sure  he  is 
not  trapped  by  some  accidental  property  of  the  one  figure  he  has  used. 
Or  he  may,  following  standard  heuristic  methods,  try  to  restate  the 
problem  or  analyze  it  into  steps  that  create  new  problems,  then  con- 
struct figures  to  help  him  prove  those  ancillary  problems.  The  ways 
in  which  he  exploits  this  Image  of  the  problem  are  quite  interesting 
and  complex,  and  it  is  a  challenging  task  to  try  to  convert  them  into 
explicit  rules  that  can  be  programmed  for  a  machine.  The  rules 
would  be  such  things  as,  "If  the  figure  has  an  axis  of  symmetry  and 
it  is  not  drawn,  then  draw  it."  Or,  most  important,  "If  two  line  seg- 
ments or  angles  are  to  be  proved  equal,  determine  by  measuring  on 
the  diagram  whether  they  are  corresponding  parts  of  apparently 
congruent  triangles."  When  the  machine  discovers  by  measurement 
that  certain  things  are  equal  or  proportional,  it  can  set  these  up  as 
hypotheses  and  inquire  whether,  if  they  are  true,  they  will  contribute 
to  the  construction  of  a  proof. 

It  is  certainly  true,  as  our  critic  pointed  out,  that  these  systems 
become  extremely  complicated.  There  is,  however,  a  kind  of  back- 
handed comfort  to  be  found  in  that  fact.  Most  scientific  advances 
have  reduced  man's  dignity,  moved  him  out  of  the  center  of  the 
universe,  given  him  apes  for  cousins,  subjected  his  brain  to  the 
fickle  endocrines  and  his  mind  to  the  unconscious  forces  of  lust — 
the  reduction  of  his  cognitive  processes  to  machine  operations  would 
seem  to  be  the  final,  crushing  blow.  At  least  we  can  take  comfort  in 
the  fact  that  we  are  too  compUcated  to  reduce  to  simple  machines. 
Thus  far  the  human  brain  seems  to  be  the  most  amazing  computing 
machine  ever  devised — nothing  else  we  know  even  approaches  it. 
The  more  carefully  we  analyze  the  information-processing  that  must 
go  on  in  order  to  solve  even  the  simplest  problems,  the  more  respect 
we  gain  for  this  beautiful  piece  of  biological  equipment. 

i88  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


Before  we  try  to  meet  our  critic's  final  objection,  however,  let 
us  consider  two  more  heuristic  methods.  These  two  are  quite  general 
methods  described  by  Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon  and  tested  for  their 
effectiveness  in  enabling  a  computer  to  solve  problems  in  logic, 
chess,  and  trigonometry.^  They  refer  to  them  as  "means-ends  anal- 
ysis" and  the  "planning  method."  The  former  attempts  to  analyze  a 
problem  into  a  sequence  of  subproblems,  and  the  latter  attempts  to 
find  a  plan  by  ignoring  some  of  the  complicating  factors  in  the  situa- 
tion. Undoubtedly  there  are  many  other  heuristics  that  we  use  to 
solve  problems,  but  these  two  are  certainly  ubiquitous,  important, 
and  powerful. 

The  means-ends  analysis  runs  something  like  this:  First,  see  if 
you  know  any  way  to  transform  the  given  into  the  desired  solution. 
If  no  way  is  known,  then  try  to  reduce  the  difference  between  them; 
find  some  transformation  that  reduces  the  difference,  and  then  apply 
it.  Then  try  the  first  step  again — see  if  you  know  any  way  to  transform 
the  new  version  of  the  given  into  the  desired  solution.  If  not,  search 
again  for  a  way  to  reduce  the  difference,  etc.  Each  time  the  difference 
is  reduced,  the  problem  gets  a  little  easier  to  solve.  Intuitively,  the 
heuristic  works  something  like  this:  "I  want  to  get  from  A  to  B,  but 
I  do  not  know  how.  What  is  the  difference  between  what  I  have  and 
what  I  want  to  get?  The  difference  is  D.  How  can  I  reduce  D?  Oper- 
ator T  will  reduce  D,  but  I  do  not  see  how  to  apply  it.  Transform  A 
so  that  operator  T  will  apply  to  it.  Now  apply  operator  T  and  get  a 
new  object  A'.  The  new  problem  is  to  get  from  A'  to  B,  but  I  do  not 
know  how.  What  is  the  difference?"  And  so  the  means-ends  analysis 
continues.^  The  argument  attempts  to  make  progress  by  substituting 
for  the  achievement  of  any  goal  the  achievement  of  a  set  of  easier 
goals.  Its  success  will  depend  upon  how  shrewdly  the  measure  of 
difference  is  defined  and  the  transformations  are  selected. 

No  doubt  it  is  obvious  that  any  method  we  can  discover  for 

8  Allen  Newell,  J.  C.  Shaw,  and  Herbert  A.  Simon.  Report  on  a  general 
problem-solving  program.  Proceedings  of  the  International  Conference  on  In- 
formation Processing,  Paris,  1959   (in  press). 

9  What  Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon  call  "means-ends  analysis"  is  similar  to 
the  theory  of  productive  thinking  described  by  K.  Duncker.  From  his  analysis  of 
the  situation  and  of  the  goal,  the  person  locates  a  source  of  difficulty  that  he  then 
attempts  to  remove.  See  K.  Duncker,  On  problem-solving,  L.  S.  Lees,  trans.. 
Psychological  Monographs,  1945,  No.  270.  The  important  advance  over  Duncker's 
work,  of  course,  is  to  be  completely  explicit  in  terms  of  a  computer  program. 

The  Formation  of  Plans  "189 


breaking  up  a  big  problem  into  smaller  problems  will  tremendously 
simplify  the  solution.  This  approach  is  valuable  when  the  solution  can 
be  characterized  by  several  simultaneous  attributes.  That  is  to  say, 
if  a  situation  differs  from  the  goal  with  respect  to  both  attribute  A 
and  attribute  B,  we  can  try  to  factor  the  problem  into  two  parts. 
Instead  of  looking  for  a  Plan  to  remove  both  differences  simultane- 
ously, we  can  search  first  for  a  set  of  Plans  that  will  take  care  of 
attribute  A,  then  search  through  that  smaller  set  of  Plans  for  one  that 
will  also  handle  attribute  B.  When  we  proceed  in  this  way  we  are  free 
to  decide  in  which  order  to  search  for  each  aspect,  in  which  order  to 
eliminate  the  differences.  In  the  language  of  children's  games,  we  get 
progressively  "warmer"  as  we  solve  each  successive  component  of 
the  problem. 

A  second  very  general  system  of  heuristic  used  by  Newell, 
Shaw,  and  Simon  consists  in  omitting  certain  details  of  the  problem. 
This  usually  simplifies  the  task  and  the  simplified  problem  may  be 
solved  by  some  familiar  plan.  The  plan  used  to  solve  the  simple  prob- 
lem is  then  used  as  the  strategy  for  solving  the  original,  complicated 
problem.  In  solving  a  problem  in  the  propositional  calculus,  for  ex- 
ample, the  machine  can  decide  to  ignore  differences  among  the 
logical  connectives  and  the  order  of  symbols  and  to  look  only  at  what 
the  symbols  are  and  how  they  are  grouped.  The  logical  operators  that 
add,  delete,  or  regroup  symbols  are  then  applied  to  the  abstracted 
propositions,  regardless  of  their  connectives.  The  steps  required  to 
get  the  right  symbols  correctly  grouped  then  serve  as  a  possible 
strategy  for  a  complete  proof.  The  critical  feature,  of  course,  is 
whether  or  not  the  neglect  of  the  details  changed  the  problem  so 
much  that  the  solution  of  the  simple  problem  was  irrelevant. 

Most  heuristic  methods  involve  some  way  to  use  the  information 
already  acquired.  If  correct  solutions  are  literally  scattered  at  random 
through  the  set  of  possible  solutions,  then  previous  search  through 
one  part  of  the  solutions  can  be  of  no  aid  to  the  subsequent  search 
through  the  remainder.  However,  in  most  situations  where  men  have 
been  successful  in  solving  problems,  the  successful  solutions  he  in  a 
neighborhood  of  successful  solutions.  Hamlet,  for  example,  is  still  an 
excellent  play  even  when  an  actor  accidentally  changes  a  few  of 
Shakespeare's  lines,  thus  changing  it  into  another,  but  very  similar, 

190  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


play.  The  general  concept  of  biological  evolution  is  a  good  one,  even 
though  the  sequence  of  development  of  different  species  may  in  some 
instances  require  revision  in  the  light  of  future  evidence.  When  we 
get  into  situations  where  the  modification  of  any  slight  detail  of  a 
correct  solution  changes  it  into  an  incorrect  solution — as  in  opening 
a  combination  lock,  for  example — we  are  usually  unsuccessful.  When 
the  best  solution  is  in  a  neighborhood  of  good  solutions,  however,  it 
is  possible  to  explore  the  neighborhood  of  any  relatively  successful 
solution  to  see  if  a  better  one  turns  up  near  by. 

If  a  set  of  possible  solutions  are,  in  this  loose  sense,  clustered 
together  in  a  space  defined  by  the  attributes,  or  dimensions,  of  the 
problem,  it  may  be  possible  to  simplify  the  problem  by  ignoring  one  or 
two  of  the  attributes  entirely.  If  the  simplified  problem  can  be  solved, 
the  steps  in  its  solution  can  suggest  a  Plan  for  solving  the  original 
problem.  With  luck,  the  steps  that  led  to  a  successful  region  in  the 
smaller  space  may  still  lead  to  a  successful  region  in  the  larger  space. 
This  is  the  sort  of  heuristic  we  use,  for  example,  when  we  try  to  find 
ways  to  settle  disputes  between  nations  by  thinking  how  we  might 
settle  similar  disputes  between  individuals.  Another  example  is  the 
use  of  the  diagram  heuristic  by  Gelernter  and  Rochester — the  steps 
involved  in  solving  the  problem  posed  by  a  particular  diagram  may 
provide  a  Plan  suitable  for  proving  the  general  theorem. 

Means-ends  analysis  and  the  planning  method  are  two  of  the 
most  powerful  heuristic  methods  used  by  Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon 
in  their  development  of  a  general  problem-solving  program,  one  gen- 
eral enough  to  deal  with  a  wide  range  of  well-defined  problems  in 
essentially  the  same  way.  Once  they  have  succeeded,  their  computer 
programs  vsdll  indeed  have  risen  above  the  level  of  heuristic  "cata- 
logues," such  as  those  offered  by  Polya  and  others,  to  the  status  of  a 
heuristic  "theory"  of  thinking. 

After  studying  this  pioneering  work  by  Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon 
it  is  quite  difficult  to  recapture  one's  innocent  respect  for  parsimony 
in  psychological  theories.  Certainly,  we  can  no  longer  think  that  any- 
one who  postulates  complicated  information-processing  by  an  organ- 
ism is  appealing  to  mysterious,  vitaHstic,  ambiguous,  or  unscientific 
principles.  Complicated  information-processing  according  to  heuristic 
principles  is  not  only  conceivable — it  has  actually  been  accomplished. 

The  Formation  of  Plans  ■   191 


demonstrated  on  existing  computers.  Henceforth,  it  is  not  necessary 
to  suspect  metaphysical  booby  traps  in  every  psychological  process 
more  compUcated  than  a  conditioned  reflex.  The  work  of  Newell, 
Shaw,  and  Simon  shows  in  detail  how  the  processes  of  solving  prob- 
lems can  be  compounded  out  of  more  elementary  processes  that  can 
be  executed  by  machines.  And  it  shows  that  those  elementary  proc- 
esses, properly  organized,  can  in  fact  solve  complex  problems;  no 
ghostly  assistance  from  an  undefined  source,  human  or  divine,  is 
needed. 

But,  while  all  of  this  work  is  clear  progress  in  dealing  with  the 
problems  of  organized  complexity,  we  still  have  hanging  over  our 
heads  the  third  complaint  by  our  patient  critic.  He  may  by  now  have 
finally  granted  that  heuristic  methods  can  be  incorporated  into  ma- 
chines, but  he  must  still  feel  that  the  behavioral  evidence  can  never 
be  collected  for  really  testing  these  ideas.  It  is  a  serious  complaint. 
If  people  must  be  this  complicated,  and  if  things  this  complicated 
cannot  be  studied  experimentally,  then  scientific  psychology  must  be 
impossible.  It  is  a  complaint  that,  if  true,  would  certainly  be  im- 
portant to  prove. 

But  is  it  true?  Certainly,  if  one  interprets  "scientific"  to  mean 
that  all  of  a  subject's  verbal  reports  must  be  ignored,  then  it  will  be 
Impossible  to  study  thinking  at  the  level  of  complexity  required  for 
programming  computers  or  for  understanding  the  neurology  and 
physiology  of  the  brain.  But  are  such  Spartan  strictures  necessary? 
They  would  protect  us  from  long,  violent  disputes  about  "imageless 
thoughts,"  perhaps,  because  they  would  make  it  impossible  to  say  any- 
thing at  all  about  thoughts,  but  that  is  a  high  price  to  pay  for  con- 
sonance. 

The  most  valuable  approach  seems  to  be  the  "thinking  aloud" 
method  used  by  Binet,  Duncker,  Claparede,  and  many  others."  Un- 
like the  usual  introspective  or  retrospective  methods  that  require  a 
subject  to  analyze  his  experience  into  meaningless  mental  contents — 
sensations,  images,  feelings — thinking  aloud  requires  merely  that  the 
person  talk  while  he  is  working,  that  he  should  comment  on  what  he 
is  doing,  what  he  is  looking  for,  what  his  intentions  are,  what  objects 
or  relations  catch  his  attention,  etc.  As  Claparede  pointed  out,  the 

1°  E.  Claparede,  La  genese  de  I'hypothese,  Archives  de  Psychologie,  1934,  24, 
1-154. 

192  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


method  has  many  shortcomings — the  task  of  talking  may  inhibit  the 
thought  processes,  or  slow  them  down,  it  may  make  the  process  sound 
more  coherent  and  orderly  than  it  would  otherwise  be,  the  referents 
for  some  of  the  utterances  are  not  clear,  the  subject  may  fall  silent 
at  just  the  critical  moment  when  the  experimenter  would  most  hke 
to  know  what  he  is  doing.  But  when  the  method  is  used  intelligently 
and  conscientiously,  it  can  provide  a  tremendous  amount  of  informa- 
tion about  the  detailed  process  of  thought.  The  problem  is  not  so 
much  to  collect  the  data  as  it  is  to  know  what  to  do  with  them. 

The  subject  will  say,  in  effect,  "I  want  to  do  A,  but  before  I 
can  do  A  I  have  to  prepare  for  it  by  doing  B."  He  then  proceeds  to  do 
JB,  which  may  lead  on  to  unforeseen  consequences  that  prevent  his 
ever  returning  to  do  A.  Nevertheless,  the  consideration  of  A  was  an 
essential  step  in  the  thought  processes  leading  to  B.  If  we  are  to 
develop  an  adequate  heuristic  description,  one  that  will  solve  the 
problem  in  the  same  manner  as  the  subject,  it  must  consider  A, 
then  do  B.  But  if  we  had  not  recorded  the  things  the  subject  said  he 
was  considering,  along  with  the  things  he  actually  did,  the  task  would 
be  hopeless.  It  is  actually  easier  to  simulate  the  person's  spoken 
thoughts  than  to  simulate  only  the  decisions  that  appear  in  his  behav- 
ior. Since  thinking  aloud  permits  more  of  the  person's  thought  proc- 
esses to  project  through  the  plane  of  perception,  it  helps  to  limit  the 
variety  of  conceivable  descriptions  to  a  handful  that  are  reasonably 
accurate. 

Newell,  Shaw,  and  Simon  have  found  that  the  subject's  descrip- 
tion of  what  he  is  doing  is  exactly  the  kind  of  data  they  need  to  formu- 
late a  theory  that  will  predict  his  behavior.^^  They  ask  a  subject  to 
derive  one  logical  expression  from  another  by  the  application  of  a 
given  set  of  transformation  rules.  The  subject  talks  about  the  task  as 
he  does  it.  He  may  look  at  the  two  expressions  he  is  given  and  say 
that  the  one  he  has  to  start  with  has  too  many  propositions  to  the 
left  of  the  main  connective,  so  he  will  have  to  get  rid  of  some  (an 
application  of  the  "planning  method").  He  looks  at  the  hst  of  trans- 
formations until  he  finds  one  that  gets  rid  of  things  to  the  left  of  the 
main  connective,  so  he  would  like  to  apply  that.  But  then  he  realizes 
that  he  cannot,  because  the  proposition  he  wants  to  transform  has 

11  H.  A.  Simon  in  an  invited  address  before  the  Eastern  Psychological 
Association  in  Atlantic  City,  April,  1959. 

The  Formation  of  Plans  ■   193 


"and"  in  it,  whereas  the  rule  he  wants  to  apply  works  only  for  "or." 
So,  he  says,  the  job  is  to  get  that  connective  changed  in  order  to  apply 
the  transformation  that  will  shorten  the  left  side.  He  looks  for  a 
transformation  that  turns  "and"  expressions  into  "or"  expressions 
and  elects  to  try  it  as  his  first  step.  Now,  it  is  possible  to  find  a  fairly 
simple  set  of  heuristic  methods  to  describe  what  this  subject  is  doing 
(e.g.,  his  method  is  to  make  the  propositions  more  important  than  the 
connectives  in  guiding  the  choice  of  transformations),  and  to  predict 
that  he  would  mention  the  left-shortening  transformation  before  he 
adopted  the  connective-changing  transformation.  But  if  the  only 
datum  that  the  experimenter  records  is  the  bald  fact  that  the  sub- 
ject's first  choice  of  a  transformation  was  the  connective-changing 
transformation,  it  is  impossible  to  see  how  the  subject's  strategy  can 
be  inferred. 

It  is  tempting  to  say  that  a  successful  theory  "predicts  the  sub- 
ject's verbal  behavior."  In  fact,  no  one  is  yet  much  interested  in  the 
verbal  behavior  as  behavior,  but  only  in  the  meaning  of  what  is  said. 
The  subject  may  say,  "Use  number  8  next,"  or,  "Let's  try  that  one 
again,"  or  any  of  a  variety  of  equivalent  verbal  behaviors,  yet  these 
differences  are  ignored  when  testing  the  adequacy  of  the  theory. 
Obviously,  therefore,  the  interest  lies  in  the  subject's  Plan,  not  in  his 
specific  actions. 

When  the  psychologist  says  that  his  subject  in  these  experi- 
ments was  following  such-and-such  a  Plan,  or  was  using  a  particular 
metaplan  for  generating  Plans  to  solve  the  problem,  it  is  clear  that 
this  is  a  hypothetical  statement.  The  Plan,  or  the  metaplan,  represents 
the  psychologist's  theory  about  that  chunk  of  observed  behavior.  Ob- 
viously, we  can  never  know  whether  or  not  we  have  the  theory  for 
any  domain  of  inquiry.  There  is  always  a  variety  of  alternative  Plans 
that  could  have  led  the  subject  to  exhibit  the  same  behavior;  the  best 
we  can  hope  to  do  is  to  select  the  simplest  one  compatible  with  all  the 
facts.  But,  because  this  kind  of  ambiguity  is  such  a  pervasive  feature 
of  behavioral  analysis,  it  is  important  to  reduce  it  as  far  as  possible. 
In  this  endeavor,  the  subject's  verbal  report  has  one  great  recom- 
mendation in  its  favor,  because  language,  for  aU  its  notorious  short- 
comings, is  still  the  least  ambiguous  of  aU  the  channels  open  from 
one  human  being  to  another. 

194  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


CHAPTER  14 


SOME 

NEUROPSYCHOLOGICAL 

SPECULATIONS 


"A  hole  is  to  dig."  The  child  amuses  us  with  his  operational 
definitions.  "A  knife  is  to  cut."  "A  book  is  to  read."  "Milk  is  to  drink." 
Each  concept  is  defined  by  the  concrete  operations  that  it  customarily 
evokes.  The  child  is  learning  what  to  do  with  things.  Or,  to  put  it  in 
our  present  language,  the  child  is  building  up  TOTE  units  by  as- 
sociating a  perceptual  Image  used  in  the  test  phase  with  an  action 
pattern  used  in  the  operational  phase  of  the  unit.  The  number  of 
these  TOTE  units  that  a  child  must  learn  is  enormous  and  he  prob- 
ably learns  them,  initially  at  least,  by  following  this  simple  verbal 
formula  that  associates  a  subject  with  a  predicate.  It  is  not  enough 
for  the  child  simply  to  be  able  to  name  the  object  or  to  distinguish  it 
from  other  objects.  He  must  know  what  actions  can  be  released  when 
the  test  phase  indicates  the  object  is  now  at  hand. 

Children,  however,  are  not  the  only  ones  who  produce  definitions 
of  this  type.  Kurt  Goldstein  has  widely  publicized  the  fact  that  they 

Some  Neuropsychological  Speculations  ■   195 


can  appear  after  certain  types  of  brain  damage.^  The  unfortunate 
patient  is  confronted  with  a  knife,  or  with  a  picture  of  a  knife.  He  is 
unable  to  supply  the  name.  But  if  he  is  given  the  object,  he  knows  how 
to  use  it.  He  may  indicate  that  he  recognizes  it  by  making  the  gestures 
that  imitate  its  use.  He  may  even  say,  "It  is  to  cut  with,"  thus  echoing 
the  child.  According  to  Goldstein's  interpretation,  this  behavior  on  the 
part  of  the  patient  indicates  an  impairment  of  the  "abstract  attitude." 
The  injury  to  the  brain  leaves  the  patient  vsdth  a  simpler,  more  con- 
crete way  of  dealing  with  his  world.  Goldstein's  famous  theoretical 
analysis  of  the  abstract-concrete  dimension  of  mental  life  is  one  way 
of  looking  at  the  symptoms  he  describes  in  the  patients.  Another, 
more  in  keeping  with  the  proposals  made  in  this  book,  suggests  that 
the  brain  can  be  damaged  in  such  a  way  that  some  of  the  simplest 
processes  of  retrieving  stored  information  cannot  be  performed,  but 
other  Plans  normally  initiated  by  the  object  are  left  intact.  The  patient 
may  have  lost  the  ability  to  execute  the  Plans  involved  in  naming 
objects,  but  retained  the  ability  to  execute  all  other  Plans.  Or  the 
patient  may  have  lost  the  ability  to  recall  a  Plan  by  internal,  verbal 
processes  and  be  completely  dependent  upon  external  memory  de- 
vices. 

In  any  case,  there  seems  to  be  good  evidence  for  the  age-old  belief 
that  the  brain  has  something  to  do  with  the  mind.  Or,  to  use  less  dual- 
istic  terms,  when  behavioral  phenomena  are  carved  at  their  joints, 
there  will  be  some  sense  in  which  the  analysis  will  correspond  to  the 
way  the  brain  is  put  together.  Psychological  problems  may  not  be 
solved  by  making  measurements  on  the  brain;  but  some  more  modest 
aim  may  be  accomplished.  A  psychological  analysis  that  can  stand  up 
to  the  neurological  evidence  is  certainly  better  than  one  that  can  not. 
The  catch,  obviously,  is  in  the  phrase  "stand  up  to,"  since  consider- 
able prejudice  can  be  involved  in  its  definition.  In  any  case,  each  time 
there  is  a  new  idea  in  psychology,  it  suggests  a  corresponding  insight 
in  neurophysiology,  and  vice  versa.  The  procedure  of  looking  back 
and  forth  between  the  two  fields  is  not  only  ancient  and  honorable — 
it  is  always  fun  and  occasionally  useful. 

The  present  authors  determined  to  follow  tradition  and  to  look 

1  Kurt  Goldstein  and  Martin  Scheerer,  Abstract  and  concrete  behavior:  an 
experimental  study  with  special  tests,  Psychological  Monographs,  1941,  No.  329. 

196  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


at  the  nervous  system  through  the  same  theoretical  spectacles.  In 
fact,  the  brain  was  never  far  from  the  focus  of  discussion.  Innumer- 
able alternative  interpretations  of  the  available  neuropsychological 
data  were  invented  and  discarded.  In  the  hope  of  communicating  the 
flavor  of  the  arguments,  this  chapter  reports  a  few  of  the  ideas  that 
were  considered.  However,  the  authors  feel  somewhat  less  than  con- 
fident that  they  have  discovered  the  one  best  line  to  pursue.^ 

The  arguments  revolved  around  a  three-way  analogy:  The  rela- 
tion of  a  Plan  to  the  mind  is  analogous  to  the  relation  of  a  program  to 
a  computer,  and  both  are  analogous  to  the  relation  of  X  to  the  brain. 
Question :  What  is  X?  -- 

Of  these  three  systems,  the  one  we  know  most  about  is  the  com- 
puter. When  a  large,  modern,  general-purpose  computer  is  turned  on 
in  the  morning  and  sits  there  warming  up,  purring  through  its  mag- 
netic drums  and  scratching  its  multivibrators,  it  is  not  yet  a  true 
computing  machine.  It  will  not  begin  to  act  like  a  computmg  machine 
until  it  is  given  some  instructions.  Depending  upon  what  kind  of  in- 
structions it  is  given  it  may  act  like  any  one  of  an  infinite  variety  of 
different  computing  machines  that  might  have  been  built  with  the 
particular  instructions  locked  in  and  unchangeable.  But  without  the 
instructions,  or  program,  the  computer  will  do  no  processing  of  in- 
formation. It  may  have  all  kinds  of  fascinating  data  stored  in  its 
memory  or  being  fed  into  it  from  the  outside,  but  without  a  program 
nothing  can  happen.  A  computer  must  have  a  program.  \ 

Now,  as  soon  as  someone  suggests  that  people  are  like  computing 
machines — and  we  hear  that  said  every  day — it  should  become  clear 
that  if  the  suggestion  is  true,  people  must  have  programs,  also.  If  a 
man  is  like  a  computer,  then  the  man  must  have  somewhere  avail- 
able an  organized  set  of  instructions  that  he  attempts  to  execute.  That 
is  to  say,  the  man  must  have  a  Plan.  By  taking  the  analogy  be- 
tween man  and  computer  with  complete  sincerity  is  one  driven  to 

2  One  reason  for  much  of  the  trouble  in  reaching  an  agreement  about  the 
way  the  brain  works  was  that  two  of  the  authors  stubbornly  persisted  in  trying  to 
talk  about  it  in  terms  appropriate  to  the  dry  hardware  of  modern  digital  com- 
puters, whereas  the  third  was  equally  persistent  in  using  language  appropriate 
to  the  wet  software  that  lives  inside  the  skull.  After  a  decade  of  cybernetics  you 
might  think  the  translation  from  one  of  these  languages  into  the  other  would  be 
fairly  simple,  but  that  was  not  the  case.  The  relation  between  computers  and 
brains  was  a  battle  the  authors  fought  with  one  another  until  the  exasperation 
became  unbearable. 

Some  Neuropsychological  Speculations  ■   197 


search  literally  for  the  source  of  instructions  that  guide  human  be- 
havior. The  preceding  pages  try  to  describe  the  results  of  that  search 
in  psychological  terms.  Now  we  are  interested  to  see  what  results  the 
same  attitude  might  produce  in  neurology. 

In  the  broadest,  crudest  terms,  what  is  the  pattern  to  be  trans- 
ferred from  computers  to  brains?  There  are  many  ways  to  build  elec- 
tronic computers,  but  most  machines  seem  to  involve  a  memory — r 
where  both  the  program  and  the  data  and  any  intermediate  results 
and  the  final  answer  can  all  be  stored — with  facilities  for  transferring 
information  into  it  and  out  of  it,  and  a  processing  unit — where  the 
actual  operations  of  comparison,  addition,  multiplication,  shifting, 
etc.,  are  performed.  The  computer  begins  by  taking  the  first  instruc- 
tion on  the  program  and  moving  it  from  the  memory  to  the  processing 
unit.  Whatever  instruction  is  in  the  processing  unit  has  control  over 
what  the  machine  will  do,  so  it  executes  the  instruction  and  goes  on 
to  the  next  instruction,^ etc.,  etc.,  with  tremendous  speed  and  blind 
persistence  until  an  instruction  tells  it  to  stop.  The  instruction  that  is 
temporarily  in  the  processing  unit  can  be  said  to  be  the  one  that  the 
computer  is  "attending  to"  at  the  moment.  Note  that  the  center  of 
attention  is  a  fiLxed  place  and  that  symbols  are  shifted  into  and  out  of 
it  from  the  memory;  the  center  of  attention  does  not  go  wandering 
around  through  the  memory  itself,  as  a  beam  of  Hght  might  scan  a. 
darkened  room.  No  doubt  there  is  nothing  necessary  about  this  pat- 
tern for  computers,  but  at  least  it  is  familiar  and  we  know  that  it  vsdll 
work.^ 

Is  it  possible  to  locate  parts  of  the  brain  that  correspond,  how- 
ever crudely,  to  these  parts  of  a  computer?  To  look  for  some  particu- 
lar place  in  the  brain  to  represent  a  locus  of  consciousness,  or  a  focus 
of  attention,  or  whatever  it  is  that  corresponds  to  a  computer's  proc- 

3  We  have  considered  only  the  possibility  that  the  nervous  system  performs 
one  operation  at  a  time;  an  equally  plausible  alternative  would  be  to  allow 
different  parts  of  the  brain  to  perform  computations  at  the  same  time.  At  the 
London  Symposium  on  Mechanization  of  Thought  Processes  in  1958  Oliver 
Self  ridge  of  the  Lincoln  Laboratory  gave  a  talk  entitled,  "Pandemonium:  a 
Paradigm  for  Learning,"  in  which  he  described  a  hierarchical  organization  of 
parallel  computers  that  could  learn  to  recognize  patterns  and  illustrated  its 
operation  in  terms  of  a  machine  that  would  learn  to  recognize  manually  keyed 
Morse  code.  Ulric  Neisser,  in  Hierarchies  in  Pattern  Recognition  (Group  Report 
54-9,  Lincoln  Laboratory,  Massachusetts  Institute  of  Technology,  9  October, 
1959),  explores  some  of  the  virtues  of  Pandemonium  as  a  model  of  human 
cognition  in  general. 

198  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


essing  unit,  is  a  naive  and  impossible  oversimplification.  But  the 
alternative  metaphor — that  a  focus  of  activity  moves  about  in  the 
brain  carrying  consciousness  with  it  from  place  to  place — seems  just 
as  ad  hoc  in  the  light  of  available  evidence.  Regardless  of  what  con- 
sciousness may  be,  however,  the  computer  analogy  would  say  to  look 
for  some  particular  place  that  could  be  used  to  store  programs  and 
data,  that  is,  to  serve  as  the  memory.  And  it  would  tell  us  to  look  for 
another  part  of  the  brain  into  which  an  instruction  could  be  trans- 
ferred when  the  time  arrived  for  the  execution  of  that  instruction. 

After  several  months  of  discussion,  the  present  authors  were 
almost  (but  not  quite)  convinced  that  you  could  put  the  names  of 
parts  of  the  brain  on  slips  of  paper,  scramble  them  up,  draw  two  at 
random,  assign  them  in  either  order  to  serve  either  as  the  memory 
or  as  the  processing  unit,  and  you  would  be  able  to  interpret  some 
evidence  somehow  as  proof  that  you  were  right.  One  notion,  for  ex- 
ample, is  that  the  cerebral  cortex  provides  the  memory  unit,  that  the 
limbic  areas  somewhere  house  the  processing  unit,  and  that  the  cere- 
bellum is  a  digital-to-analogue  converter  in  the  output  system.  The 
primary  projection  areas  could  provide  short-term  storage  for  images 
that  would  be  operated  upon  by  programs  stored  in  the  adjacent  as- 
sociation areas.  And  so  on.  It  is  wonderful  to  see  how  these  analogies 
can  blossom  when  they  are  given  a  little  affection. 

Eventually,  however,  even  the  most  optimistic  theorist  feels  the 
need  for  evidence.  What  does  the  neurologist  have  to  contribute  to 
this  discussion?  In  the  broadest,  crudest  terms,  once  again,  what 
pattern  can  be  discerned  in  the  organization  of  the  brain? 

JLike  Caesar's  Gaul,  the  brain  is  divided  into  parts,  a  conceptual 
operation  that  always  reflects  a  conviction  that  when  two  things  live 
close  together  they  probably  cooperate  with  each  other.  A  fourfold 
division  of  the  f orebrain  can  be  made :  first  into  an  internal  core  vs. 
an  external  portion;  then,  each  of  these  can  be  divided  into  two  parts. 
The  internal  core  is  made  up  of  limbic  systems  and  a  frontal  "associ- 
ation area."  The  external  portion  is  divided  into  projection  system? 
for  the  different  sense  modalities  and  a  posterior  "association  area."  * 

^  The  evidence  on  which  these  divisions  are  based  has  been  summarized  by 
Karl  Pribram,  Comparative  neurology  and  the  evolution  of  behavior,  in  A.  Roe 
and  G.  G.  Simpson,  eds.,  Behavior  and  Evolution  (New  Haven:  Yale  University 
Press,  1958).  Chapter  7,  pp.  140-164. 

Some  Neuropsychological  Speculations  ■   199 


These  divisions  are  based  on  neuroanatomical  evidence,  but  they  also 
indicate  relatively  consistent  differences  in  the  kinds  of  psychological 
functions  that  they  serve.  Concerning  the  major  division  into  an  in- 
ternal core  and  an  external  portion,  Pribram  comments  as  follows: 

[It  is  assumed]  that  the  internal  core  is  primarily  related  to 
changes  in  central  nervous  system  excitability;  that  the  external 
portion  serves  propagation  of  patterns  of  signals;  that  the  in- 
ternal core  is  primarily  concerned  in  mechanisms  necessary  to 
the  performance  of  behavior  sequences  vv^hile  the  external  por- 
tion is  related  to  informational  processes  necessary  in  discrim- 
inative behavior.^ 

The  reader  who  has  come  this  far  through  the  present  text  should 
react  with  interest  to  this  division  of  the  brain  into  an  internal  part 
that  handles  sequences  of  acts  and  an  external  part  that  handles  dis- 
crimination. Once  the  present  distinction  has  been  drawn  between 
the  Plan  and  the  Image,  it  is  almost  inevitable  that  one  should  iden- 
tify the  internal  core  as  the  part  of  the  brain  involved  in  planning 
(i.e.,  "sequences")  and  the  external  portion  as  the  part  of  the  brain 
involved  in  our  organized  system  of  facts  and  values  (i.e.,  "discrimi- 
nation"). Thus,  one  begins  to  think  of  the  internal  core  as  a  place  that 
governs  the  execution  of  Plans;  of  the  limbic  portions  of  the  internal 
core,  along  with  their  closely  related  subcortical  centers,  as  if  they 
performed  the  functions  of  a  processing  unit  in  a  computer;  and  of 
the  frontal  lobe,  which  is  the  "association  area"  in  the  inner  core  sys- 
tem, as  a  "working  memory"  where  various  Plans  could  be  tempo- 
rarily stored  (or,  perhaps,  regenerated)  while  awaiting  execution. 

There  are  problems  with  this  schema,  of  course.  One  difficulty 
is  the  disposition  of  different  motivational  processes.  Since  it  has  been 
argued  in  these  pages  that  values  are  part  of  the  Image,  consistency 
would  demand  that  evaluation  must  be  mediated  by  the  external  por- 
tion of  the  forebrain.  However,  current  research  on  the  limbic  areas 
— the  part  of  the  inner  core  that  might  govern  the  execution  of  the 
Plan — suggests  that  they  are  involved  in  motivational  processes  in  a 
most  intimate  fashion.  Thus  we  seemed  to  face  a  dilemma,  which 
took  some  careful  analysis  of  the  behavioral  evidence  to  resolve.  The 
matter  is  quite  important,  so  let  us  pursue  it  here  and  now. 

5  Ibid.,  p.  143. 

200  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


Analysis  of  the  functions  of  the  limbic  systems  of  the  forebrain 
has  been  one  of  the  outstanding  achievements  of  neurophysiology 
during  the  1950's.  These  systems  are  located  deep  in  the  center  of  the 
brain,  and  because  they  are  difficult  to  get  at  surgically,  they  were 
neglected  until  recently.  In  spite  of  a  great  deal  of  research,  however, 
the  functions  that  these  structures  serve  in  normal  behavior  have 
eluded  precise  specification.  The  trouble  stems  from  the  fact  that  a 
wide  variety  of  seemingly  unrelated  effects  on  behavior  result  when 
these  regions  are  stimulated  electrically  or  are  surgically  destroyed. 
Two  different  points  of  view  have  been  adopted  in  the  various  at- 
tempts to  explain  the  observed  behavior:  (1)  The  limbic  systems 
comprise  the  substrate  concerned  with  motivational  and  emotional 
behavior,  motivation  and  emotion  being  conceived  as  primitive,  in- 
stinctual, "visceral"  reactions.''  (2)  The  limbic  systems  are  primarily 
concerned  with  "memory."  ^  Clinical  and  experimental  observations 
can  be  advanced,  of  course,  to  support  both  of  these  interpretations. 

What  sort  of  evidence  is  there  for  the  first  view,  that  the  limbic 
systems  are  concerned  vvath  primitive  motivational-emotional  proc- 
esses? For  one  thing,  homeostatic  mechanisms  are  abundant  in  the 
central  core  of  the  nervous  system  and  are  located  especially  around 
the  third  and  fourth  ventricles  of  the  rostral  end  of  the  neuraxis.  Take, 
for  example,  the  thirst  mechanism.  Goats  have  been  made  to  drink 
large  quantities  of  water  by  injecting  a  few  drops  of  concentrated 
table  salt  solution  into  the  third  ventricle.  The  osmoreceptors  in  this 
region  of  the  brain  are  activated  and  the  goats  continue  to  drink 
water  until  an  equilibrium  is  reached.  That  is  to  say,  they  drink  until 
a  sufficient  amount  of  water  is  absorbed  from  the  gut  through  the 
vascular  system  and  into  the  cerebrospinal  fluid  to  return  its  salinity 
to  normal.  This  is  the  kind  of  "motivational"  process  one  finds  situ- 
ated in  the  internal  core.  Should  the  present  authors  be  embarrassed 
and  revise  their  opinion  about  the  relegation  of  dynamic  factors  to  the 
Image  on  the  basis  of  such  evidence?  Not  at  all.  The  thirst  homeostat 
is  a  Plan,  a  relatively  simple,  innate  TOTE  unit. 

G  p.  D.  MacLean,  The  limbic  system  with  respect  to  self-preservation  and  the 
preservation  of  the  species,  Journal  of  Nervous  and  Mental  Diseases,  1958,  1, 
1-11. 

"B.  Milner,  Psychological  defects  produced  by  temporal  lobe  excision,  in 
The  Brain  and  Human  Behavior,  Research  Publication,  Association  for  Research 
in  Nervous  and  Mental  Disease,  XXXVI  (Baltimore:  Williams  and  Wilkins,  1958), 
Chapter  VIII,  pp.  244-257. 

Some  Neuropsychological  Speculations  "201 


As  elsewhere,  the  TOTE  phases,  once  they  have  been  initiated, 
run  themselves  off  until  the  incongruities  that  activated  them  are 
resolved.  The  organism  will  continue  activities  that  tend  to  complete 
the  TOTE  sequence:  i.e.,  the  organism  will  show  "intentional  behav- 
ior." A  statement  that  the  animal  "intends  to  quench  its  thirst"  seems 
more  appropriate  than  a  statement  that  the  animal  values  water.  The 
distinction  made  in  Chapter  4  between  values  and  intentions  is  cru- 
cial here.  What  would  really  be  surprising  would  be  to  discover  that 
a  lesion  in  the  central  core  could  cause  a  man  to  reverse,  say,  his 
preference  for  Rembrandt  over  Picasso,  or  for  capitalism  over  com- 
munism. The  evaluative  factors  involved  in  such  choices  as  these 
must  be  mediated  somehow  in  the  external  portion  of  the  forebrain. 

In  the  normal  animal — one  which  does  not  have  concentrated 
salt  solution  in  its  third  ventricle — the  number  of  swallows  of  water 
taken  is  determined  by  the  amount  of  water  the  body  needs,  and  the 
drinking  will  terminate  long  before  there  has  been  time  for  any  dilu- 
tion of  the  cerebrospinal  fluid.  What  terminates  the  TOTE  unit  activ- 
ity for  drinking  in  this  case?  Presumably  the  number  of  swallows  is 
recorded — we  hesitate  to  say  "counted,"  since  that  might  be  mis- 
understood as  meaning  that  the  animal  pronounced  the  names  of 
integers  subvocally  as  it  drank — and  is  compared  with  some  pre- 
determined number  that  depends  upon  the  body's  water  balance. 
After  each  swallow  the  amount  of  drinking  that  has  been  done 
is  compared  with  the  predetermined  amount  that  is  to  be  done  and 
when  the  two  are  equal  the  TOTE  unit  is  terminated.  How  the  num- 
ber can  be  predetermined  is  not  clear,  but  presumably  it  depends 
upon  previous  experience  in  some  way.  We  might  think  of  the  in- 
formation about  how-many-swallows-are-needed-as-a-function-of -how- 
much-water-deprivation-has-been-endured  as  forming  a  part  of  the 
Image,  a  stored  relationship,  which  must  be  drawn  upon,  activated, 
before  the  TOTE  unit  for  drinking  is  set  up  for  execution.  There- 
fore, the  present  authors  are  not  disconcerted  to  discover  that  lesions 
in  the  limbic  systems  of  the  central  core  disrupt  the  execution  of 
such  behavior. 

This  distinction  between  the  automatic  execution  of  TOTE  units 
concerned  with  vital  functions  and  the  evaluation  of  these  same  func- 
tions in  the  Image  can  be  illustrated  by  an  actual  case.  Bilateral  sur- 

202  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


gical  ablation  of  certain  parts  of  the  limbic  systems  characteristically 
result  in  excessive  eating  and  obesity.  One  patient,  who  had  gained 
more  than  one  hundred  pounds,  was  examined  at  lunch  time.  Was  she 
hungry?  She  answered,  "No."  Would  she  like  a  piece  of  rare,  juicy 
steak?  "No."  Would  she  like  a  piece  of  chocolate  candy?  She  an- 
swered, "Um-humm,"  but  when  no  candy  was  offered  she  did  not  pur- 
sue the  matter.  A  few  minutes  later  when  the  examination  was  com- 
pleted, the  doors  to  the  common  room  were  opened  and  she  saw  the 
other  patients  already  seated  at  a  long  table,  eating  lunch.  She  rushed 
to  the  table,  pushed  others  aside,  and  began  to  stuff  food  into  her 
mouth  with  both  hands.  She  was  immediately  recalled  to  the  examin- 
ing room  and  the  questions  about  food  were  repeated.  The  same  nega- 
tive answers  were  obtained  again,  even  after  they  were  pointedly  con- 
trasted with  her  recent  behavior  at  the  table.  Somehow  the  lesion 
had  disrupted  the  normal  relation  between  the  evaluation  of  an  ob- 
ject and  the  execution  of  Plans  for  obtaining  it — between  Image  and 
Plan — a  fact  that  we  interpret  as  further  evidence  for  a  clear  separa- 
tion between  value  and  intention,  the  two  aspects  of  motivated  be- 
havior. Just  how  the  lesion  could  have  such  an  effect  is  a  topic  to 
which  we  shall  return  shortly. 

What  sort  of  evidence  is  there  for  the  second  view,  that  the  lim- 
bic systems  are  concerned  with  memory?  A  large  lesion  in  the  limbic 
systems  in  man  (more  extensive  than  that  described  in  the  patient 
above)  can  produce  a  very  odd  type  of  memory  loss.  Patients  with 
lesions  in  this  part  of  the  internal  core  of  the  forebrain  are  able  to 
repeat  correctly  a  series  of  digits  that  they  have  just  heard  for  the 
first  time.  On  this  test  of  immediate  memory  they  are  practically  as 
efficient  as  they  were  before  the  lesion  occurred.  Moreover,  their 
memory  for  events  prior  to  their  surgical  operation  is  apparently 
normal.  But  if  distracted,  they  are  unable  to  carry  out  a  sequence  of 
orders.  If  you  are  called  away  for  ten  or  fifteen  minutes  in  the  middle 
of  administering  some  test  to  such  a  patient,  when  you  return  he  will 
not  be  able  to  continue  where  he  left  off.  He  will  not  recall  where  he 
was  in  the  task.  In  fact,  he  will  not  even  recall  that  there  was  any  task 
or  that  he  had  ever  seen  you  before.  Such  a  patient  can  be  directed  to 
a  grocery  store  where  he  can  purchase  the  items  on  a  wiritten  hst 
without  having  to  refer  to  that  list  any  oftener  than  would  a  person 

Some  Neuropsychological  Speculations  ■   203 


with  an  intact  brain.  But  once  he  has  completed  the  shopping  he 
does  not  recall  what  he  is  supposed  to  do  with  his  purchases  and  he  is 
completely  incapable  of  finding  his  way  home.  Unless  given  new  in- 
structions at  this  point  he  will  wander  about  aimlessly  until  some- 
thing in  the  environment  sets  off  a  habitual  reaction,  such  as  waiting 
for  a  red  light  to  change  before  he  crosses  a  street.  His  behavior  is  not 
organized  into  a  Plan,  but  rather  is  a  mere  concatenation  of  discrete 
acts. 

On  the  surface,  this  peculiar  defect  of  memory  would  not  seem 
to  have  anything  in  common  with  the  disturbed  thirst  and  hunger 
mechanism  mentioned  above.  Yet  this  patient's  behavior  illustrates 
perfectly  what  would  happen  if  a  person  were  unable  to  formulate 
Plans  for  remembering  (cf.  Chapter  10).  Given  an  external  Plan  writ- 
ten out  on  a  sheet  of  paper,  the  patient  can  carry  on  quite  well. 

Neurobehavioral  studies  conducted  on  animals  support  this  no- 
tion that  the  limbic  systems  of  the  internal  core  of  the  forebrain  play 
an  essential  role  in  the  execution  of  Plans.  Ablation  and  stimulation 
of  various  structures  within  these  systems  interfere  with  feeding, 
fleeing,  fighting,  mating,  and  maternal  behavior.  Two  kinds  of  effects 
are  obtained,  depending  on  which  of  the  major  divisions  of  the  limbic 
systems  is  experimentally  involved. 

The  first  kind  of  effect  we  have  already  met  in  the  patient  at 
lunch  time.  It  seems  to  involve  a  failure  of  some  sort  in  the  test  phase 
of  the  TOTE  unit.  Either  the  test  will  not  indicate  that  the  operational 
phase  should  occur,  or  the  test  will  not  indicate  that  it  should  termi- 
nate. If  a  lesion  is  made  in  one  spot,  the  animal  will  starve  to  death  in 
the  presence  of  food.  If  the  location  of  the  lesion  is  shifted  slightly, 
the  animal  will  eat  continuously  as  though  it  is  impossible  for  him  to 
stop.  (Interestingly  enough,  preferences  among  foods  are  not  dis- 
turbed; monkeys  will  still  prefer  peanuts  to  lab  chow  and  prefer  lab 
chow  to  feces.) 

When  a  normal  baboon  is  handed  a  lighted  match  for  the  first 
time  he  will  grab  it  and  put  it  into  his  mouth  and  perhaps  set  his 
whiskers  afire  in  the  process.  He  douses  his  snout  in  a  water  trough. 
When  he  is  offered  another  lighted  match  he  may  reach  for  it,  but  he 
will  stop  before  he  grabs  it,  or  if  he  does  take  it,  he  will  fling  it  into 
the  trough  or  out  of  the  cage.  If  he  has  had  an  ablation  of  the  amyg- 
daloid complex — one  of  the  major  subdivisions  of  the  limbic  systems 

204  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


— he  behaves  quite  differently.  If  he  reaches  for  the  first  match  he 
will  continue  to  reach  for  subsequent  matches,  and  each  time  he  will 
complete  the  entire  sequence  of  putting  it  into  his  mouth,  firing  his 
whiskers,  and  dousing  his  snout.  The  test  phase  of  the  TOTE  unit 
which  initiates  the  actions  of  oral  exploration  cannot  be  modified  in 
the  Hght  of  experience. 

In  a  similar  fashion,  sexual  activity,  once  it  has  been  initiated, 
will  be  displayed  by  these  operated  animals  under  circumstances  in 
which  normal  animals  show  no  such  behavior.^  And  the  effects  of 
such  lesions  on  fleeing  can  also  be  understood.  The  animals  develop 
a  conditioned  avoidance  reaction  only  with  great  difficulty:  they  ap- 
parently cannot  establish  the  conditioned  stimulus  as  part  of  the  test 
phase  of  the  avoidance  behavior.  And  once  conditioned  avoidance  has 
been  established  it  is  very  easily  extinguished — perhaps  the  animal  is 
unable  to  terminate  other  TOTE  units  in  which  he  is  engaged  in  time 
to  make  the  conditioned  response.^ 

An  efPect  of  lesions  in  this  part  of  the  limbic  systems,  therefore, 
can  be  interpreted  as  a  disruption  of  the  test  phase  of  different  TOTE 
units.  TOTE  units  that  are  already  established  may  get  their  testing 
routines  "jammed,"  so  that  the  test  always  passes  or  always  fails.  And 
experience  in  the  situation  does  not  enable  the  operated  animal  to 
learn  new  testing  procedures  to  substitute  for  the  ones  he  has.  An 
Interesting  sidehght  on  this  inability  to  impose  new  tests  on  a  TOTE 
unit  comes  from  electrophysiological  studies  of  cortical  conditioning. 
The  electrical  activity  produced  in  the  visual  cortex  under  ordinary 
circumstances  by  visual  stimulation  can  be  conditioned,  after  several 
paired  auditory-visual  presentations,  to  occur  when  only  the  auditory 
stimulus  is  given.  The  only  selective  ablation  that  is  known  to  inter- 
fere wdth  this  conditioning  process  is  that  of  the  limbic  structures  we 
have  been  considering.^" 

Interference  with  the  test  phase  of  various  TOTE  units  is  only 

8  J.  D.  Green,  C.  D.  Clemente,  and  J.  de  Groot,  Rinencephalic  lesions  and 
behavior  in  cats:  an  analysis  of  the  Kliiver-Bucy  syndrome  with  particular 
reference  to  normal  and  abnormal  sexual  behavior.  Journal  of  Comparative 
Neurology,  108,  1957,  505-545. 

9  L.  Weiskrantz,  Behavioral  changes  associated  with  ablation  of  the  amygda- 
loid complex  in  monkeys.  Journal  of  Comparative  and  Physiological  Psychology, 
1956,  49,  381-394. 

10  F.  Morrell  and  H.  H.  Jasper,  Electrographic  studies  of  the  formation  of 
temporary  connections  in  the  brain,  EEG  and  Clinical  Neurophysiology,  1956, 
8,  201. 

Some  Neuropsychological  Speculations  ■   205 


one  of  two  kinds  of  symptoms  that  are  produced  by  lesions  in  the  lim- 
bic systems.  A  second  kind  of  symptom  appears  as  damage  to  the 
hierarchical  relation  between  TOTE  units.  In  order  to  execute  a  plan 
of  any  complexity  at  all  it  is  necessary  to  keep  track  of  where  in  the 
plan  one  has  gotten.  What  happens  when  the  hierarchical  structure 
of  TOTEs  is  disrupted  is  nicely  illustrated  by  the  behavior  of  a  mother 
rat  with  limbic  lesions.  When  a  normal  mother  rat  is  faced  with  a 
situation  in  which  her  brood  has  been  strewn  around  the  cage,  she 
will  pick  up  one  baby  rat  and  carry  it  to  the  nest,  go  back  to  pick  up 
another  and  return  it  to  the  nest,  etc.,  until  all  the  youngsters  are 
safely  back  in  the  nest.  This  behavior  does  not  appear  when  the 
mother  has  had  a  surgical  operation  to  remove  the  cingulate  cortex 
— another  of  the  major  subdivisions  of  the  limbic  systems.  The  sur- 
gically operated  mother  will  pick  up  an  infant,  carry  it  part  way  to 
the  nest,  drop  it  in  favor  of  another  which  may  be  carried  to  the  nest 
only  to  be  removed  on  subsequent  trips.  After  half  an  hour  of  this  the 
baby  rats  are  still  strevsni  all  over  the  nest  and,  eventually,  are  left  to 
die.^^  Similar  disorganization  occurs  when  these  operated  animals 
try  to  hoard  food,  an  activity  that  is  quite  common  among  normal 
rodents  when  they  become  hungry. 

A  little  can  be  surmised  about  how  the  hierarchical  relation  be- 
tween TOTE  units  is  accomplished  in  the  nervous  system.  The  amyg- 
dala seems  to  be  necessary  to  the  test  phase  of  many  innate  TOTE 
units.  Under  normal  conditions  the  electrical  activity  recorded  from 
the  amygdaloid  complex  changes  only  when  the  animal  is  startled 
or  when,  as  a  result  of  conditioning,  his  "attention"  is  focused  on 
some  environmental  event.  However,  when  the  hippocampus — still 
another  subdivision  of  the  limbic  systems — is  inactivated  by  ablation 
or  by  massive  electrical  stimulation,  the  electrical  activity  recorded 
from  the  amygdala  changes  whenever  the  animal  touches,  or  hears, 
or  catches  sight  of  any  environmental  event.  It  is  tempting  to  specu- 
late that  the  hippocampus  normally  protects  the  amygdala  from  all 
incoming  information  except  that  appropriate  for  the  TOTE  unit  cur- 
rently in  control.  The  hippocampus  could  perform  this  "gating"  func- 

11  J.  S.  Stamm,  The  function  of  the  median  cerebral  cortex  in  maternal 
behavior  of  rats,  Journal  of  Comparative  and  Physiological  Psychology,  1955, 
87,  77-88. 

2o6  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


tion  via  the  reticular  formation  in  the  internal  core  of  the  brain  stem, 
which,  in  turn,  is  known  to  influence  the  receptors,  the  afferent  path- 
ways into  the  central  nervous  system,  and  the  activities  of  the  entire 
external  portion  of  the  forebrain.  Thus  the  hippocampus  may  be  in- 
timately involved  in  the  business  of  keeping  the  brain  at  work  on  the 
successive  steps  in  the  Plan  and  preventing  it  from  being  shunted 
haphazardly  about  by  every  fluctuation  in  the  environment.^-  If  so,  it 
would  fit  very  nicely  into  our  conception  of  how  the  hierarchy  of 
TOTEs  (within  the  operational  phases  of  their  proto-TOTEs)  can  be 
established. 

The  frontal  "association  areas,"  sometimes  referred  to  as  "the 
organ  of  civilization,"  are  intimately  connected  with  the  limbic  sys- 
tems to  form  the  internal  core  of  the  forebrain.  This  most  forward 
portion  of  the  primate  frontal  lobe  appears  to  us  to  serve  as  a  "work- 
ing memory"  where  Plans  can  be  retained  temporarily  when  they  are 
being  formed,  or  transformed,  or  executed.  This  speculation  appears 
to  be  consistent  with  the  fact  that  animals  with  lesions  in  the  frontal 
lobes  have  difficulty  with  the  delayed-reaction  and  the  delayed-alter- 
nation  tests.  Both  of  these  tasks  require  the  animal  to  follow  an  inter- 
nally stored  Plan  of  action.  The  behavioral  evidence  is  compUcated, 
however,  and  it  may  well  be  that  it  is  the  transformation  of  Plans, 
rather  than  merely  the  storage  of  them,  for  which  the  frontal  lobes 
are  required. 

The  effects  of  frontal  ablation  or  lobotomy  on  man  are  surpris- 
ingly subtle.  Very  few  of  the  usual  psychometric  tests  turn  up  any 
deficits  at  all.  One  that  frequently  shows  a  deficit  is  the  Porteus  maze, 
a  pencil-and-paper  labyrinth  that  would  seem  to  require  some  plan- 
ning. It  should  not  be  difficult  to  devise  many  more  tests  of  planning 
ability  and  to  use  them  on  these  patients.  Clinical  observations  of 
their  behavior  would  encourage  us,  at  least  in  some  cases,  to  expect 
that  such  tests  would  succeed  in  diagnosing  the  patient's  difficulties. 
Such  a  patient  is  apt  to  "fall  apart"  when  some  minor  detail  goes  awry 
in  the  Plan  he  is  executing.  If  he  is  preparing  dinner  when  the  trouble 
occurs,  he  may  not  be  readily  capable  of  reshuffling  the  parts  of  the 

12  M.  A.  B.  Brazier,  ed.,  The  Central  Nervous  System  and  Behavior,  Transac- 
tions of  the  Second  Conference,  February  22-25,  1959,  Josiah  Macy,  Jr.,  Founda- 
tion. 

Some  Neuropsychological  Speculations  ■  207 


Plan.  Segments  of  the  Plan  may  simply  be  omitted — the  vegetables 
are  served  raw — or  the  whole  dinner  may  be  lost.  Even  if  these 
speculations  prove  to  be  wrong  in  detail,  the  notion  that  the  frontal 
"association  areas"  are  intimately  linked  to  the  limbic  systems  in  the 
transformation  and  execution  of  Plans  is  worth  pursuing.  Clinical 
and  laboratory  observations  that  investigate  how  rather  than  what 
behavior  is  changed  by  the  frontal  lesions  have  hardly  begun. 

One  fairly  obvious  consequence  of  looking  at  the  relation  of  brain 
and  behavior  in  the  way  proposed  here  is  that  we  need  a  much  more 
elaborate  and  precise  theory  than  we  have  about  an  organism's  Plans 
before  we  can  predict  what  any  particular  lesion  may  do  to  him. 
Overly  simple  indicators,  such  as  the  strength,  rate,  or  latency  of 
some  isolated  movement  pattern,  will  only  delude  us  into  thinking 
the  processes  are  simpler  than  they  really  are.  The  ethologists  are 
among  the  few  students  of  behavior  who  have  been  willing  to  look 
for  the  Plan  behind  the  actions  and  to  describe  it  literally  in  the  kind 
of  flow  diagrams  that  an  engineer  would  need  in  order  to  construct  a 
machine  to  perform  the  same  functions.  Given  such  a  detailed  speci- 
fication of  what  is  guiding  the  muscle  twitches  it  may  then  be  possible 
to  see  certain  critical  points  at  which  the  behavior  can  be  disrupted 
by  lesions  in  certain  parts  of  the  brain.  To  hope  for  relations  between 
brain  structures  and  crude,  ad  hoc,  statistical  indicants  of  some 
loosely  defined  abstraction  called  "response"  is  apt  to  be  very  mis- 
leading. The  problem  of  specifying  what  constitutes  a  "stimulus"  for 
an  organism  has  long  been  recognized  to  be  more  difficult  than  it  ap- 
pears on  the  surface;  the  chapters  in  this  book  must  make  it  equally 
clear  that  the  mechanism  that  generates  any  "sequence  of  responses" 
may  not  be  as  simple  as  it  may  at  first  seem. 

One  of  the  most  interesting  aspects  of  brain  function,  therefore, 
is  how  Plans  are  constructed  in  the  first  place,  how  they  are  formed. 
The  present  discussion  has  been  confined  to  the  more  limited  task  of 
describing  how  Plans  must  be  executed.  These  speculations  may 
throw  some  light  on  the  functions  of  the  limbic  systems.  But  the  au- 
thors are  not  sure  where  or  how  the  brain  might  generate  Plans. 
When  a  familiar  Plan  is  remembered  and  only  slightly  modified  to 
fit  a  new  situation,  we  might  find  that  its  selection  depended  somehow 
upon  the  posterior  "association  areas"  in  the  external  portion  of  the 

208  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


forebrain — selecting  a  Plan  from  memory  is  closely  related  to  using 
the  Image,  and  the  Image,  in  turn,  would  seem  to  be  mediated  by  the 
external  portion.  Perhaps  the  decision  to  execute  a  particular  Plan 
is  equivalent  to  transferring  control  from  the  posterior  "association 
areas"  to  the  frontal  "association  areas."  Perhaps. 

These  speculations  about  the  functions  of  the  central  nervous 
system  take  on  a  kind  of  finality  and  solidity  when  they  are  com- 
mitted to  paper  that  they  did  not  have  so  long  as  they  remained  con- 
versational. The  authors  know  how  fuzzy  their  own  Image  of  this 
marvelous  organ  is  and  how  oversimplified  or  arbitrary  these  state- 
ments must  appear.  Yet  the  notions  of  a  reflex  telephone  system  with 
an  enigmatic  switchboard,  or  inhibitions  and  excitations  rippling 
majestically  over  the  surface  of  the  brain,  or  little  homunculi  inside 
the  pineal  glands  of  little  homunculi  inside  the  pineal  glands  of  little 
homunculi  ad  infinituTn,  or  empty  black  boxes  that  absorb  S's  and  emit 
R's,  are  so  thoroughly  unsatisfactory  that,  although  the  present  ideas 
may  be  wrong,  they  are  likely  to  be  a  great  deal  less  wrong  than  the 
metaphors  many  psychologists  have  used  heretofore.  Anybody  who 
tries  to  do  the  research  needed  to  put  this  approach  to  test  will  dis- 
cover things  that  he  would  not  otherwise  have  thought  to  look  for. 


Some  "N euro-psychological  Speculations  ■  209 


EPILOGUE 


As  our  debate  progressed  and  our  conception  of  Plans  became 
clearer,  a  conviction  grew  on  us  that  we  were  developing  a  point  of 
view  toward  large  parts  of  psychology.  We  then  began  to  wonder  how 
we  might  best  characterize  our  position  so  as  to  contrast  it  with  others 
more  traditional  and  more  familiar.  The  question  puzzled  us.  We 
did  not  feel  that  we  were  behaviorists,  at  least  not  in  the  sense  J.  B. 
Watson  defined  the  term,  yet  we  were  much  more  concerned — in  that 
debate  and  in  these  pages,  at  least — with  what  people  did  than  with 
what  they  knew.  Our  emphasis  was  upon  processes  lying  immediately 
behind  action,  but  not  with  action  itself.  On  the  other  hand,  we  did 
not  consider  ourselves  introspective  psychologists,  at  least  not  in  the 
sense  Wilhelm  Wundt  defined  the  term,  yet  we  were  willing  to  pay 
attention  to  what  people  told  us  about  their  ideas  and  their  Plans. 
How  does  one  characterize  a  position  that  seems  to  be  such  a  mixture 
of  elements  usually  considered  incompatible?  Deep  in  the  middle  of 
this  dilemma  it  suddenly  occurred  to  us  that  we  were  subjective  be- 
haviorists. When  we  stopped  laughing  we  began  to  wonder  seriously 
if  that  was  not  exactly  the  position  we  had  argued  ourselves  into.  At 
least  the  name  suggested  the  shocking  inconsistency  of  our  position. 

Epilogue  ■  211 


As  a  matter  of  fact,  we  recognized  that  we  had  been  drifting  in 
that  direction  for  several  years.  In  1957,  for  example,  Pribram,  in  the 
course  of  reviewing  the  interrelations  of  psychology  and  the  neuro- 
logical disciplines  for  "Project  A,"  made  this  comment: 

As  a  rule,  the  extreme  behaviorist  has  become  overly  sus- 
picious if  the  psychological  concepts  derived  from  behavioral 
observation  too  closely  resemble  those  derived  introspectively 
(the  "mental").  The  position  accepted  here  is  that  behaviorally 
derived  concepts  are  to  be  compared  with  those  derived  intro- 
spectively. Two  extremes  must  be  avoided,  however.  When  the 
behaviorally  derived  concepts,  because  of  a  lack  of  empirical 
evidence,  are  indistinguishable  from  those  derived  from  intro- 
spection, confusion  results;  when  the  two  classes  of  concepts 
are  so  distinct  that  no  relation  between  them  is  recognizable, 
the  behaviorally  derived  concept  is  apt  to  be  trivial. 

We  hope  that  in  these  pages  we  have  hit  some  sort  of  happy  com- 
promise between  these  two  extremes  and  that  we  can  both  distinguish 
and  compare  the  Plan  with  the  Behavior.  But  the  point  is  that  the 
need  for  reconciliation  has  bothered  us  for  some  time.  Galanter  had 
struggled  with  the  same  problem  in  a  discussion  of  thinking: 

Classical  theories  of  thinking  fall  into  two  general  (and 
oversimplified)  categories.  These  classes  of  theories  have  been 
termed  variously  (a)  S-R,  association,  trial-and-error,  or  sign 
theories;  and  (b)  image  or  model  theories.  ...  It  is  difficult  to 
specify  the  behavioral  manifestation  or  identification  of  an 
image,  and  in  addition,  image  theories  rarely  give  more  than  a 
sUpshod  account  of  how  the  image  comes  into  its  full-blown 
existence.  Even  so,  the  fuzzy  description  of  the  role  of  images  in 
complex  thinking  does  a  fuzzy  kind  of  justice  to  our  introspec- 
tions. .  .  .  Most  early  theorists  attempted  a  synthesis.  Such 
synthesizing  went  out  of  vogue  during  the  "behavioral  revolu- 
tion," and  now  most  psychologists  espouse  either  an  S-R  theory 
or  a  cognitive  theory.  Our  ultimate  aim  is  to  try  again  the  de- 
velopment of  a  synthetic  theory.^ 

Again  we  note  the  theme — how  to  pull  together  two  conceptions  that 
were  both  necessary  yet  apparently  incompatible.  Our  aim  is  still  to 
develop  a  synthetic  theory.  But  now  we  think  that  a  clear  description 

IE.  Galanter  and  M.  Gerstenhaber,  On  thought:  the  extrinsic  theory. 
Psychological  Review,  1956,  63,  pp.  218-219. 

212  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


of  the  role  of  Plans  is  the  link  that  will  hold  the  two  together — that 
will  make  subjective  behaviorism  possible. 

Why  not  be  subjective  behaviorists?  The  objection,  of  course, 
is  that  "subjective"  and  "behaviorism"  do  not  go  together.  We  might 
as  well  talk  about  a  black  whiteness,  or  a  square  circle.  But  almost 
every  behaviorist  has  smuggled  into  his  system  some  kinds  of  invis- 
ible gimmicks — internal  responses,  drives,  stimuli,  or  whatnot — that 
are  as  "objective"  as  John  Locke's  ideas  used  to  seem  to  be.  Every- 
body does  it,  for  the  simple  reason  that  you  cannot  make  any  sense 
out  of  behavior  unless  you  do.  J.  B.  Watson  himself  talked  about 
"covert  speech,"  which  is  certainly  a  kind  of  subjective  behavior.  Of 
course,  we  could  call  our  Plans  by  some  such  operationally  accept- 
able name  as  "intervening  variables"  and  so  pretend  that  we  are 
really  talking  about  tacit  behavior,  but  what  would  that  accomplish? 
If  a  behaviorist  is  willing  to  introspect  on  what  he  would  do  if  he 
found  himself  in  the  predicament  that  his  rats  are  in,  then  he  is,  in 
our  opinion,  a  subjective  behaviorist  whether  he  admits  it  or  not. 

What  matters  to  us  far  more  than  a  name,  however,  is  whether 
or  not  we  have  glimpsed  an  important  aspect  of  human  intelligence. 
Psychologists  who  have  been  content  to  describe  the  mind  as  though 
it  were,  in  turn,  nothing  but  a  description  of  its  own  experience  have 
scarcely  noticed  how  sedentary  they  seem  to  others,  especially  to 
those  who  are  more  concerned  vdth  actions  and  results.  At  first  the 
behaviorists  seemed  to  be  the  men  of  action.  But  the  correction  they 
should  have  supplied  was  somewhere  lost  in  the  rituals  and  taboos 
of  objectivity.  Eventually,  they  too  slipped  into  a  tradition  of  descrip- 
tion until  they  differed  from  their  colleagues  only  in  the  fact  that  the 
object  they  described  was  behavior,  not  mind.  Indeed,  it  scarcely 
jars  our  modern  ear  to  hear  behavior  called  an  object  for  description. 

Description  is  of  course  important.  Even  more,  it  is  essential  to 
science  that  we  have  accurate  descriptions  available.  But  there  is  an- 
other ingredient  required,  one  that  we  seem  to  forget  and  rediscover 
in  every  generation  of  psychologists,  at  least  since  Brentano's  Act 
first  competed  with  Wundt's  Content.  Life  is  more  than  a  thing,  an 
object,  a  substance  that  exists.  It  is  also  a  process  that  is  enacted.  We 
have  a  choice  in  our  approach  to  it.  We  can  choose  to  describe  it,  or 
we  can  choose  to  re-enact  it.  Description  in  its  various  ramifications 

Epilogue  ■   213 


is  the  traditional  approach  of  the  scientist.  Re-enactment  has  been 
the  traditional  approach  of  the  artist.  And  just  as  description  depends 
upon  an  Image,  re-enactment  depends  upon  a  Plan. 

Re-enactment  has  Uved  on  the  technological  borders  of  pure 
science  for  a  long  time — the  planetarium  is  an  astronomer's  re- 
enactment  of  the  solar  system,  the  model  is  an  engineer's  pre-enact- 
ment  of  his  structure,  the  wind  tunnel  is  an  aeronautical  re-enact- 
ment of  the  atmosphere — but  it  has  usually  played  a  supporting  role. 
If  a  description  is  correct  and  accurate,  re-enactments  based  upon  it 
should  closely  resemble  the  natural  phenomenon  that  was  described. 
Now,  however,  re-enactment  is  emerging  as  a  scientific  alternative  in 
its  own  right.  The  development  of  modern  computing  machines, 
more  than  anything  else,  has  given  scientists  the  tools  required  to 
re-enact,  or  simulate,  on  a  large  scale,  the  processes  they  want  to 
study.  The  program  for  a  computer  that  re-enacts  a  process  is  becom- 
ing just  as  acceptable  a  theory  of  that  process  as  would  be  the  equa- 
tions describing  it.  There  is  stOl  much  that  needs  to  be  clarified  in 
this  new  application  of  the  artist's  ancient  attitude,  but  clarification 
will  not  lag  far  behind  application.  And  as  the  understanding  of  these 
complex  systems  grows,  the  need  to  distinguish  between  introspec- 
tively  derived  and  behaviorally  derived  concepts  should  decline — 
until  eventually  both  our  experience  and  our  behavior  will  be  under- 
stood in  the  same  terms.  Then,  and  only  then,  wiQ  psychologists  have 
bridged  the  gap  between  the  Image  and  Behavior. 


214  ■  Plans  and  the  Structure  of  Behavior 


INDEXES 


INDEX    OF   AUTHORS 


Alderstein,  A.  M.,  142tc 
Alexander,  I.  E.,  142n 
Allport,  G.,  114,  122 
Ameen,  L.,  152?! 
Anscombe,  B.  E.  M.,  61n 
Anthony,  S.,  142n 
Arrow,  K.  J.,  146n 
Ashby,  W.  R.,  3,  42n 
Attneave,  F.,  28n 
Austin,  G.,  165n,  168?i 

Baerends,  G.  P.,  79 
Baernstein,  H.  D.,  46n 
Barker,  R.  G.,  15n,  96n 
Bartlett,  F.  C,  7 
Beach,  F.,  74 
Beebe-Center,  J.  G.,  54n 
Bennett,  G.  K.,  46n 
Bergson,  H.,  45n 
Bernstein,  A.,  55n 
Bigelow,  J.,  42 
Binet,  A.,  192 
Bishop,  G.,24n 
Book,  W.  F.,  86 
Boothe,  A.  D.,  53n 
Boring,  E.  G.,  46n 
Boulding,  K.  E.,  1,2 
Bradner,  H.,  46n 
Brazier,  M.  A.  B.,  207n 
Brower,  R.  A.,  53n 
Bruner,  J.  S.,  165n,  168n 
Bryan,  W.  L.,  86 
Burton,  N.  G.,  146n 


Campbell,  D.  T.,  88n 

Cannon,  W.  B.,  43 

Carmichael,  L.,  12l7i,  171ra 

Carroll,  J.  B.,  14n,  52n 

Chauncey,  H.,  122n 

Cherry,  C,  28n 

Chomsky,  N.,  3,    14n,   15-16,   23,   52, 

144, 145n,  148n 
Claparede,  E.,  192n 
Clark,  W.  A.,  50to 
Clemente,  C.  D.,  205n 
Cleveland,  A.  A.,  130n 
Colley,  R.  S.,  142n 
Craik,  K.,  50 
Crozier,  W.  J.,  44n 

Davis,  M.,  46n,  160n 
de  Groot,  J.,  205n 
Dennis,  W.,  43n,  44n 
Descartes,  R.,  42 
Dewey,  J.,  30n,  43n 
Dinneen,  G.  P.,  50n 
Driesch,  H.,  457i 
Duda,  W.  L.,  50n 
Duncker,  K.,  160,  189n,  192 

Ebbinghaus,  H.,  69,  70 
EUis,  W.  D.,  60n 
EUson,  D.  G.,  46n 
Elsasser,  W.  M.,  45n 
Estes,  W.  K.,9n 

Farley,  B.  G.,  50n 
Festinger,  L.,  32n 


Index  of  Authors  ■   217 


Freud,  S.,  69,  142n 
Frick,  F.  C,  52n 

Galanter,  E.,  47,  51,  146n,  168n,  173, 

212 
Gardner,  M.,  55n 

Gelernter,  H.  L.,  51,  55n,  56n,  187,  191 
Gerstenhaber,  M.,  51,  168n,  173,  212n 
Gleason,  H.  A.,  144n 
Goldstein,  K.,  195,  196 
Goodnow,  J.,  165n,  168n 
Gorn,  S.,  46n 
Green,  J.  D.,  205 
Green,  W.,  119n 
Guthrie,  E.  R.,  9,  10 

Haibt,  L.  H.,  50n 

HaU,  E.  T.,  lOln 

Hanfmann,  E.,  165n 

Harter,  N.,  86 

Hartley,  D.,  44n 

Hebb,  D.  O.,  9,  50n,  51,  142n 

Heidbreder,  E.,  165n 

Hilgard,  E.  R.,  9n 

Hockett,  C.  F.,  145n 

Holland,  J.  H.,  50n 

Holt,  E.  G.,  44 

Hovland,  C.  I.,  163n 

Hull,  C,  15n,  41n,  44-45,  46n 

Hunter,  W.  S.,  88 

Irion,  A.  L.,  125n 

James,  W.,  11,  12,  64,  144,  145n 
Jasper,  H.  H.,  205 
Jeffress,  L.,  lln,  154n 
Johnson,  D.  M.,  163n 
Jung,  C.  G.,  122n 

Karlin,  S.,  146n 
Kister,  J.,  55n 
Kluckhohn,  C,  102n 
Kluckhohn,  F.,  102n 
Kochen,  M.,  47 
Kohler,  W.,  10 
Kreuger,  R.  G.,46 

Laffal,  J.,  152n 
Lashley,  K.,  10,  88n,  154 
Lees,  L.  S.,  160,  189 
Leibnitz,  G.,  42 
Lenkoski,  L.  D.,  152n 
Lewin,    K.,    11,   60,   61,   64-68,    102n, 
121n, 171n 


Lewis,  C.  I.,  59,  71 
LickKder,  J.  C.  R.,  146n 
Lindzey,  G.,  142n 
Locke,  J.,  213 
Locke,  W.  N.,  53n 
Loeb,  J.,  44 
Lorenz,  K.,  75 
Lotka,  A.  J.,  44n 
Luchins,  A.  S.,  1207z 
Luria,  A.  R.,  140n 

McCarthy,  J.,  32n,  49n,  56n 

McCuUoch,  W.  S.,3,49 

McGeoch,  J.  A.,  125n 

MacKay,  D.  M.,  3,  32n,  50,  51n 

MacLean,P.  D.,  201n 

McNemar,  O.,  120n 

Mandler,  G.,  88n 

March,  J.  G.,  101 

Miller,  G.  A.,  3,  28n,  52,  53n,  54n,  1307Z, 

132n, 145n, 146n 
Milner,  B.,  201tc 
Milner,  P.  M.,  50ji 
Milton,  G.  A.,  119n 
Minsky,  M.  L.,  3,  49n,  55n,  172n,  183, 

184 
Moles,  A.  A.,  183n 
Morrell,  F.,  205n 
Miiller,  G.  E.,  134 
Murchison,  C.,  44n 
Murray,  J.  A.,  102ra 

Neisser,  U.,  198n 

NeweU,  A.,  3,  15n,  16,  17n,  37to,  55n, 

56,  96n,  168,  182,  185-193 
Nissen,  H.  W.,  140n 

Pavlov,  L  P.,  6,  23,  91n 

Pearson,  K.,  42n 

Perkins,  C.  P.,  136 

Perky,  C.W.,  110 

Pitts,  W.,  49 

Plato,  181 

Poincare,  H.,  167 

Polya,  G.,   160n,   169n,   179,  180,   183, 

191 
Polyani,  M.,  87n,  168n 
Pribram,  K.,  199n,  212 

Rapaport,  D.,  60n,  68n 

Rashevsky,  N.,  49n 

Riesman,  D.,  119 

Roberts,  M.,  557z 

Rochester,  N.,  50n,  51,  55n,  187,  191 


21 8  ■  Index  of  Autnors 


Rock,  I.,  137 
Roe,  A.,  140n,  199n 
Rosenblueth,  A.,  42 
Ross,  T.,46n 
Ruch,  T.  C.,91,92 
Russell,  B.,  168 

Saltznian,  I.  J.,  130n 

Samuel,  A.  L.,  55ti 

Scheerer,  M.,  196n 

Schlosberg,  H.,  86n,  127n 

Schneider,  D.  M.,  102n 

Schumann,  F.,  134 

Selfridge,  O.,  50n,  198n 

Shannon,  C.  E.,  3,  28,  32n,  49n,  52n, 

55n, 145n,  146n 
Shaw,  J.  C,  3,  15n,  16,  17n,  37n,  55n, 

56,  96n,  168,  182,  185-193 
Sherrington,  C,  23,  24 
Simon,  B.,  91n 
Simon,   H.   A.,   3,   15n,   16,   17n,   37n, 

55n,  56,  96n,  101,  168,  182,  185- 

93 
Simon,  J.,  140n 
Simpson,  G.  G.,  140n,  199n 
Skinner,  B.  F.,  21,  22 
Sluckin,  W.,  27n 
Smith,  W.  A.  S.,  51n 
Stamm,  J.  S.,  206?! 
Stephens,  J.  M.,  46n 
Stevens,  S.  S.,  91n 
Sullivan,  H.  S.,   115n 
Suppes,  P.,  146n 

Taylor,  D.  W.,  120n 
Thompson,  W.  R.,  142n 
Thorndike,  E.  L.,  134n 


Thorpe,  W.  H.,  75n 
Tinbergen,  N.,  75,  76,  78,  79 
Tolman,  E.,  8,  9,  13,  44n,  61n 
Troland,  L.  T.,  44 
Turing,  A.  M.,46,  167 
Turner,  S.  H.,  136 

Ulan,  S.,  55n 
Underwood,  B.J. ,  131 

von  Neumann,  J.,  3,  90n 

Walden,  W.,  55n 

Wallace,  W.  H.,  136 

Walton,  A.,  46n 

Ward,  L.  B.,46n 

Watson,  J.  B.,  104,  211,  213 

Weiskrantz,  L.,  205n 

Weiss,  W.,  183n 

Weitzenhoffer,  A.  M.,  104,  106,  107 

WeUs,  F.  L.,  12071 

Wells,  M.,  55n 

White,  L.D.,  17n 

Whitehead,  A.  N.,  168 

Whitfield,  J.  W.,  163n 

Whorf,  B.  L.,  154,  155 

Wiener,  N.,  3,  27n,  28,  42,  43,  182 

Wisdom,  J.  O.,  27n 

Woodworth,  R.  S.,  32n,  37,  86,  127, 

134n, 157n 
Wright,  H.  F.,  15n,  96n 
Wundt,  W.,211 

Yngve,  v.,  148n 
Yudovich,  F.  la.,  140n 

Zeigarnick,  B.,  68 


Index  of  Authors  ■  219 


INDEX    OF    SUBJECTS 


ablation,  203,  204 

accessibility,  of  Plans,  100 

activity 

patterns  of,  12,  13 
spontaneous,  of  nerve,  24 

adaptive  concatenations,  79 

algorithms,  160,  164 

ambiguities,  153 

amnesias,  109,  110 

amygdaloid  complex,  204 

anagram,  166 

analogue  computer,  90n 

ancillary  Plan,  110,  111 

anesthesias,  109,  113 

anxiety,  116 

apprehension,  span  of,  131 

aspiration,  level  of,  171n 

association,  60,  129 

attention,  65,  198,  206 

automatization,  of  Plans,  82 

automation,  self-programming,  184 

behavior 

configuration  of,  12 

emotional,  201 

hierarchical  organization  of,  13,  15 

instinctive,  73 

intentional,  202 

levels  of,  13,  14,  78 

motivated,  61 

multiple  causation  of,  95 

organization  of,  13 


behavior   (Continued) 

stimulus  control  of,  75 

verbal,  14,  139  S. 
behaviorism,  125 

subjective,  211,213 
bicycle  riding,  87 
borrowed  Plans,  1 13 
brain,  196,  197 

amygdaloid  complex,  204 

association  area,  200 

cerebellum,  91,  92,  199 

cerebral  cortex,  199 

cingulate  cortex,  206 

external  portion,  199 

frontal  association  area,  199,  207, 
208 

hippocampus,  206,  207 

internal  core,  199,  200,  201 

limbic  systems,  199,  200  S. 

osmoreceptors,  201 

posterior  association  areas,  208 

projection  systems,  199 

reticular  formation,  207 

subcortical  centers,  200 

ventricles,  201 

visual  cortex,  205 

vyaves.  111 
brightness  discrimination,  140 
British  Museum  algorithm,  163,  168 

catatonia,  113,  116 
cerebellum,  91,  92,  199 


Index  of  Subjects  "221 


cerebral  cortex,  199 
chaining,  77,  78,  84,  144 
character  disorders,  123 
chess,  55,  184,  185 
cingulate  cortex,  206 
circular  reflexes,  44 
cognitive 

strain,  164,  165 

structure,  63 
cognitive  theory,  11 

criticism  of,  9,  10,  41 
commitment,  116 
communicable  Plans,  82,  89,  143 
communication,  155 
compatible  Plan,  97 
compulsive  person,  119 
computer,  178,  197 

analogue,  90n 

digital,  48,  90n 

electronic,  46 

memory  of,  49,  54 
concatenation,  77,  78,  204 

adaptive,  79 
concept,  162 

attainment,  165 

learning,  163 

positive  instance  of,  165 
conditioned  avoidance,  205 
conditioning,  cortical,  205 
confirmation  of  Image,  161 
conflicting  Plans,  97 
consciousness.  111,  145,  198 

of  Plans,  65 
consummatory  acts,  76,  77 

hierarchical  organization  in,  77 
control,  27,  28,  198 
coordination  of  Plans,  96,  98,  120 
cortical  conditioning,  205 
creativity,  178,  179 

in  thinking,  173 
culture,  95,  119,  123 
cybernetics,  2,  3,  26,  49 

death,  141 

defense  mechanisms,  116 
dependencies,  nested,  148 
depression,  agitated,  115 
desertion  of  Plans,  98 
detail  of  Plans,  119 
digital  computer,  48,  90n 
digital-to-analogue  converter,  91,  92, 

199 
discrimination,  200 
of  brightness,  140 


disorganization,  206 
dual  personality,  97 
dynamic  property,  118 

of  instincts,  73 

of  Plans,  62  ff . 

efficiency,  96,  131 
emotional  behavior,  201 

excitation  of,  116 
emotions,  98,  114 
entelechy,  42,  45n 
environment,  internal  representations 

of,  7fE. 
ethical  guilt,  98 
ethology,  74,  75 
evaluation,  62,  156 
evolution,  38,  142 
execution  of  Plans,  17,  59,  61,  64,  69, 

105,  116 
external  memory  devices,  68,  70 

feasibility  of  Plans,  70,  113 
feedback,  26,  42,  51,  91 

loop,  30 

mechanism,  43 

sensory,  44,  91 
flexible  Plan,  67,  78,  82,  89,  96,  120 
formation  of  Plans,  69,  177 
frontal  association  area,  199,  207,  208 

gambling,  166 
generator  of  Plans,  184 
grammar,  144,  145  ff. 

of  behavior,  155 

dependency  in, 148 

level  of,  143 

machine,  149 

Plan,  155,  156,  177 

sentences  and,  146 

theory  of,  153 
grouping,  131 
guilt,  ethical  and  moral,  98 

habit,  81,82,  177 

hallucinations.  111 

halting  problem,  171 

hebephrenia,  115 

heuristic  Plan,  160,  163,  167,  168,  179 

hierarchy 

of  consummatory  acts,  77 

of  behavioral  units,  85 

instinctive,  76 

in  organization  of  behavior,  15,  32 

in  organization  of  word  list,  155 


222  ■  Index  of  Subjects 


hierarchy  (Continued') 

in  Plans,  155 

structure  of,  33 
hippocampus,  206,  207 
homeostatic  mechanisms,  27,  201 
human  Plans,  154 
hypnosis,  103,  106  ff. 

anesthesias  in,  109 

inducing,  106 

levels  of,  108 

speech  during,  107 
hypotheses,  162 

alternative,  163,  175 
hysteria,  116 

ideo-motor  action,  12 

Image,  1,  2,  5  fF.,  17,  157,  202 

alternative,  174 

in  computer,  50  ff . 

confirmation  of,  161 

definition  of,  17 

imaginative,  110 

infirming  of,  161 

perceptual,  110,  195 

Plan  symbolized  in,  116 

public,  98 

revising  of,  171 

use  of,  2 
imagery,  129 
imaginal  thinking,  173 
imagining,  131 
imitation,  177 
imprinting,  75 
incongruity,  26,  31,  82,  202 
inflexible  Plan,  67,  74,  78,  89,  96 
information,  27,  28 

processing,  91,  174,  188 

processing  languages,  16 
innate  Plan,  74,  78 
innate  releasing  mechanism,  75 
inner  speech,  71,  105,  111 
insight,  10,  157 
instinctive  Plan,  74,  78 
instincts,  73,  74,  93,  177 

dynamic  aspects  of,  73 

innate  character  of,  73 

motivational  aspects  of,  73 

as  Plan, 74, 177 

reproductive,  76 
instruction,  155 

verbal,  177 
integration  of  Plans,  95 
intelligence,  artificial,  55 


intention,  59,  60,  62,  202 

dynamic  property  of,  61 

forgotten,  69 

invariance  of,  63 

to  learn, 129 
intercalated  act,  84 
internal  core  of  brain,  199,  200,  201 
interruption  of  Plans,  67 
intervening  variables,  213 
introspection,  117,  127,  140,  182 
involuntary  Plans,  74,  81,  82,  116 

kernel  strings,  152 

language,  14,  38,  104,  139 

in  animals,  140 
learning,  83 

rote,  130,  131 

verbal,  137,  153 
lesion  of  brain,  203,  204,  207,  208 

symptoms  of,  206,  207 
life  space,  60 

limbic  systems,  199,  200,  201-205,  208 
linguistics,  144 
lists,  15,  132,  134 
lobotomy,  effects  of,  207 
loop,  37,  170 

feedback, 30 

machine  imagery,  51 
Markov  processes,  52,  145,  147 
maze,  Porteus,  207 
meaningful  discourse,  133 
meaningfulness,  125 
means-end  analysis,  189,  191 
mediating  organization,  8 
memorization,  128 
memory 

of  computer,  49,  198 

external  devices  for,  68,  70,  196 

function,  66 

immediate,  148,  203 

and  limbic  system,  201,  203 

loss,  203 

trace,  127 

unit,  199 

working,  64,  200,  207 
message  source,  148 
metaplan,  129,  169,  178,  179 
mnemonic  devices,  134,  136 
mnemonic  Plans,  165 
model 

left-to-right,  146 

mechanical,  42 

stochastic,  47 


Index  of  Subjects  ■  223 


motion  study,  85 
motions,  sequence  of,  13 
motivation,  61,  95,  201 

and  instincts,  73 

processes  of,  200 
motor  Plan,  156 
motor  skills,  81,  82,  93 
motor  unit,  13,  32,  83 

polyphase,  37 

needs,  64 
negation,  151 

negative  evaluation,  62,  63 
nerve,  spontaneous  activity  of,  24 
nested  dependencies,  148 
neural  nets,  49 
neuropsychology,  195 
neurotic  personality,  97 
nonrecurrent  Plans,  130 
nonsense  syllables,  70,  126,  127 
operationism,  126 
organizations,  99 
osmoreceptors,  201 
outline,  15 

pain,  109 

paired  associates,  136 
paranoid  reaction,  115 
parataxic  modes,  115 
payofF  function,  174 
persistence,  121 
personality,  117,  122 

neurotic,  97 
persuasion,  103 
phase  sequences,  51 
physiological  limit,  110 
planlessness,  112 
planning 

higher-order,  128 

method  of,  189,191,193 

social,  99 

speed  of,  120 
Plans,  2,  5,  16,  29,  31,  33,  37,  38,  50, 
62,  63,  102,  104 

accessability  of,  100 

alternative,  174 

ancillary,  110,  111 

automatized,  82 

borrowed:^^13 

communicable,  82,  89,  143 

compatible,  97 

complex,  72 

conflicting,  97 

coordination  of,  96,  98,  120 


Plans  (Continued') 

detail  of,  119 

definition  of,  16 

desertion  of,  98 

dynamic  properties  of,  64 

ef&cient,  96 

execution  of,  17,  59,  60,  64,  65,  69, 
105,116 

exhaustive,  167 

feasible,  70,  113 

fixed,  78 

flexible,  67,  78,  82,  89,  96,  120 

formation  of,  69,  177 

generator,  184 

grammatical,  155,  177 

for  hammering  nails,  34 

heuristic,  160,  163,  167,  168,  179 

hierarchical,  16,  155 

for  housekeeping,  108 

human,  154 

inflexible,  67,  74,  78,  89,  96 

inherited,  74,  177 

innate,  74,  78 

instinctive,  74,  78 

integration  of,  95 

interruption  of,  67 

involuntary,  74,  81,  82,  116 

locked  in,  81,89 

mnemonic,  165 

nonrecurrent,  130 

openness  of,  121 

pruning  of,  115 

pubKc,  98,  101 

ready-made,  134  ff. 

reconstructing,  178 

relevant,  113 

remembering,  204 

retrieval  of,  121 

revision  of,  70 

rigid,  78 

search, 161 

several  at  once,  78,  79 

shared,  177 

source  of,  119 

span  of,  119 

stopping,  105 

stored,  178 

symbolized  in  Image,  116 

systematic,  160,  166 

voluntary,  82,  89 

working  memory,  65 
polyphase  motor  units,  37 
posterior  association  areas,  208 
posthypnotic  suggestion.  111 


224  ■  Index  of  Subjects 


prediction  paradigm,  173,  174 
primary  projection,  199 
priorities,  101 
problem 

non-numerical,  54 

search,  163 

simplified,  191 

solving,  167,  169,  178 

well-defined,  170 
processing  unit,  198 
program,  15n,  16,  28,  37n,  48,  56,  184, 

197 
projection  systems,  199 
protaxic  modes,  115 
proximal  stimulus,  25 
psychometrics,  118 

quasi-need,  60 

ready-made  Plans,  134  £F. 

recall,  of  interrupted  tasks,  65,  66 

recitation,  130 

reconstructing  Plans,  176 

re-enactment,  214 

reflex,  21,24,  77 

circular,  44 

conditioned,  46 
reflex  arc,  6 

criticism  of,  18,  22-25 

definition  of,  22 
reflex  theorist,  7,  41 
reinforcement,  7,  30,  118,  128 
remembering,  125,  177 

Plans  for,  204 
repression,  69 
reproductive  instinct,  76 
resumption,  of  interrupted  tasks,  65,  66 
reticular  formation,  207 
retrieval  of  Plans,  121 
retroflex,  44 
revision 

of  Image,  171 

of  Plans,  70 
rhythmic  grouping,  128 
risk  in  Plans,  166 
roles,  social,  99,  100 
Rorschach  ink-blot  test,  119 
rote  learning,  130,  131 
rules,  151 

schema,  7 
schizophrenic,  115 


gearch,  159  fF. 

Plans,  161 

problem,  163 

routines,  160 
sentence,  144,  145 

generators,  151,  152 

planner,  146 
sequence 

of  acts,  200 

of  motions,  13 
sensory  feedback,  44,  91 
servomechanism,  31,  44 
sexual  activity,  205 
shared  plans,  99,  100,  177 
short-term  storage,  199 
simulation,  47,  50 
skiUs,  81,82,  93,  156,  177 

acquisition  of,  86,  87 

development  of,  85 

verbal,  157 
sleep,  105 

solution,  neighborhood  of,  191 
span 

of  apprehension,  131 

of  Plans,  119 
speaking,  139 

in  hypnosis,  107 
space,  101 

statistical  theory,  133 
steady  state,  24 
stimulus,  208 

magnitude,  140 

reinforcement,  7,  118 

response  relation,  6 
stochastic  chains,  146 
stochastic  models,  47 
stop-orders,  121,  170 
stop  rule,  33,  109,  110,  161,  168 
stopping  of  Plans,  105 
stored  Plans,  178 
strategy,  32,  74,83,  119 

definition  of,  17 

habitual,  89 

integrated,  90 

for  learning,  129 

perceptual,  165 

verbalized,  89 
style,  118 

subcortical  centers,  200 
subplans,  96,  159 
suggestion,  posthypnotic.  111 
suicide,  141 

symptoms,  of  lesions  of  Limbic  systems, 
206 


Index  of  Subjects  ■  225 


synapse,  24,  45n 
syntax,  144,  154 

taboo,  112 
tactics,  32,  74,  119 

definition  of,  17 

during  hypnosis,  107 

idiosyncratic,  84 
talking,  145,  193 
tasks,  interrupted,  65,  66 
teleological  argument,  42 
tension  system,  66,  67 
test 

delayed  alternation,  207 

delayed  reaction,  207 

perceptual,  161 

proximal  stimulus,  25 
test  phase,  of  TOTE,  25,  29,  109 
thinking,  163,  169,  178 

aloud,  192 

creative,  173 

imaginal,  173 
thirst,  201 
thought 

control,  112 

imageless,  192 

laws  of,  155 
threshold,  25 
time,  101,  123 


TOTE,  27,  29,  32-38,  62,  63,  75,  170, 
175,  195,202 

hierarchy  of,  63,  98,  156,  186,  206 

operational  phase,  37 

pattern  as  hypothesis,  31 

test  phase,  109 
trait,  122 
translating,  131 

translation,  mechanical,  52,  53,  54 
trial-and-error,  52,  157 
tropism,  44,  77 

transfer,  of  previous  learning,  125 
Turing  machine,  46,  49 
two-phase  motor  units,  32 

units  of  action,  13,  32 
utUity  scale,  174 

valence,  60 

values,  59,  62,  122,  200 

differences  in,  118 
ventricles,  201 
visual  cortex,  205 
volition.  111 
voluntary  Plans,  82,  89 

Whorfian  hypothesis,  155 
vidll,  12,  71,  104,  112 
working  memory,  64,  200,  207 


226  ■  Index  of  Subjects 


Dnlo    Diio 


DuQ  Koiurned 


Fie  Q  imr^ 


i3HOE 


*!)5V5 


AUG  »i  fl»| 

"TJCT  2     t99ir^ 


JAH2  5^^ 


...^^Hf^LLllILiLSjgC- 


Duo 


RcJurnoti 


JL_-'- 


1 


!{»g"50054  6803 


♦'-;rf»»'^ 


ji